Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
Lawyers’ Perceptions of Their Values: An
Empirical Assessment of Monash University Graduates in Law, 1980–1998
ADRIAN EVANS*
INTRODUCTION
Public and professional discussion about the behaviour of lawyers is
perennial to the point of cliché. Commentary about perceived
inadequacies
is also commonplace, but it is ordinarily based on anecdotal, though powerful,
“war” stories. It seems,
however, that legal educators and
regulators must tackle the “ethics issue” with renewed vigour if
legal institutions
are to retain moral, and perhaps even spiritual,
relevance.1 Ethics awareness projects are, of course,
under way in many places (for example, the American Bar Association’s
“Ethics
2000” programme2); however, often
they proceed with little direct information from the mass of legal practitioners
as to their own perceived standards
of conduct. As legal educators we can only
design and teach ethics courses and help the legal profession describe the
desirable attributes
of the future lawyer using indirect information as to what
is needed. My concern here is that legal ethics programmes, both in and
after
law school, may be proceeding on a comfortable, but possibly unfounded,
assumption – that as legal educators or regulators
we can simply appeal to
the supposed better nature of our students and members in order to improve
attitudes3 and, hence, behaviour. While, in my opinion,
there is a link between lawyers’ attitudes/values and their behaviour, we
first
need to know about these attitudes and values.
The context for this
discussion – an urgent one – is the acknowledgment that justice and
human rights are under challenge
in many parts of the world. Those who stand up
for justice often need and receive advice and representation from courageous
lawyers.
Yet we do not know if courage or resilience or a willingness to take
unpopular decisions in defence of these causes is the norm or
is exceptional. We
may suspect that it is exceptional, but we do not know. The direct relationship
between the quality of justice
and the values/behaviour of legal practitioners
is, accordingly, of direct importance to the international concern for human
rights
and fair systems of justice.
In this paper I will discuss a survey of
graduates in law from Monash University4 and comment on
the implications of the results for Australian legal education. The aim of the
survey was to establish what values
are important to lawyers in their
professional lives. I did not on this occasion attempt to look at actual
behaviour because it was
too large an undertaking for the time and funds
available. This project is, nevertheless, important because it attempts to deal
with
what I consider to be implicit assumptions by legal educators that the
values of their students are sufficiently uniform and “good”
(enough) to enter professional practice. The understandable5
comfort of legal educators with the “values status quo” is
now, I think, a risky educational strategy. The results of
the survey that I
conducted suggest that there is a convincing case for introducing and
integrating a values awareness process6 within legal
education.
An initial task in this investigation is to establish whether
there is an empirical basis for the assumption that an appeal to lawyers’
aspirations is based on shared personal and professional values.
Tremblay’s reflection on the American Association of Law Schools
Clinical
Section Conference on values formation, held in Portland, Oregon in 1998,
suggests a commonality of values. He seems to
assume that lawyers have “in
place” their own sense of “moral judgment and responsibility,”
thus implying
that this is a shared sensitivity.7
Tremblay further suggests that the majority of lawyers share common values and
that the problems in professional behaviour stem from
differing views as to what
the facts of any ethical situation may be. In other words, the
circumstances of a matter can be variously interpreted, and this variety
produces
different decisions. Thus, we would agree, presumably, that human life
is sacred, as a value; however, we may argue for capital punishment,
depending
upon the circumstances of a particular offence. The difficulty here –
apart from the inevitable blurring between
“fact” and
“value” – is that there is a considerable assumption
underlying that logic. We do not really
have much rigorous
information8 to suggest that particular values –
however defined – are in fact shared by the mass of lawyers.
“Values”
are here intended to denote the beliefs that (it is hoped)
actually underlie and determine professional choices and not just those
which
are articulated.
In particular, we legal educators have no empirical basis on
which to conclude that clinical methodologies, which are internationally
growing
in acceptance within law school curricula, are effective in raising the
“moral tone” of the efforts that law
schools make to increase
student awareness of any justice imperative. I have a sense that law schools are
also slowly regaining (or,
for some, just establishing) the idea that their
primary mission is to inculcate in their students a desire to do justice, as
the goal of legal practice. If this is true, then the “moral
shape” of students – that is, the presence or absence
of moral
health in each individual – becomes a crucial concern in that mission.
Until now, only anecdotal evidence suggests
that law school graduates with
certain types of clinical experience – that is, those who have had
personal involvement with
indigent clients who have compelling legal
problems9 – enter legal practice with attitudes
that are different from those who do not choose to study this option within
their law
course.
A SURVEY OF MONASH UNIVERSITY LAW GRADUATES
A survey10 of a sub-population of Australian lawyers
to discover what values play a role in their professional decisions now provides
some information.
This article reviews the issues raised in this survey and
describes the survey process and the results obtained from a questionnaire
answered by 700 respondents, all former students of the Faculty of Law at Monash
University in Melbourne, Victoria, Australia. Questions
designed to place the
respondent in a personally challenging situation were composed around scenarios
of local socio-legal significance
and factual ambiguity. Respondents had to opt
for a “yes/no” response to a request for a specific action on their
part
and were then asked to rate the significance of various specific motivating
values to their choice. The questions were dispersed
purposefully in the
questionnaire to expose any inconsistencies in their responses. Demographic data
and a comparative standard personal
values survey (Rokeach) were also completed
by the respondents so that correlations could emerge and contradictions could be
highlighted.
The Rokeach instrument – a series of questions designed to
bring out respondents’ personal values – is a standard
statistical
device developed by Milton Rokeach.11 One of its
applications is to gauge, by comparison with the answers to the questions
concerning so-called “personal”
values, the accuracy of answers to
other occupationally specific questions asked of the same set of
respondents.
As discussed in detail below, this analysis strongly suggests
that there are considerable differences in the value-base – ie
the set of
values actually held by an individual – of this sub-population. Thus, for
example, in a question designed to require
a choice by an employee solicitor
between pro bono work and extra hours “in the firm” that were
demanded by a partner with influence in the firm but not necessarily the
immediate superior of the employee, a small majority (357) of those surveyed
preferred their firm’s interests, citing a mixture
of “employer
loyalty” and “employment security” as their motivating values.
This apparent lack of commitment
to the public interest might be justifiable in
a workforce that is known to be as difficult to enter as law is in Australia.
Even
though one’s first concern may well be to remain employed because of
job insecurity, this value does not necessarily exclude
other
“higher” values when employment is secure. However, nearly half
(324) of this large sample were just as comfortable
to choose the pro
bono priority, requiring a negative response to their employer and citing
“access to justice” as their motivator.
Other questions also
brought divergent answers. Taken as a whole, this study suggests, but does not
confirm, that clinical experiences
may make some difference to the attitudes
that lawyers hold. It is probable that a comprehensive longitudinal study of
lawyers’
values and correlating behaviour across many different
jurisdictions will expose compelling associations between values that lawyers
hold and their behaviour. Efforts to address the justice priority in legal
education and in the practice of law could then proceed
on a firmer foundation
– one that is based on actual knowledge of the values that underlie
notions of legal ethics.
VALUES BEFORE ETHICS?
In order to place this research in its international context, I refer to some
of the debate about legal ethics.12 The debate is not
confined to issues of interpretation surrounding, for example, conflicts of
interest or duties to the courts, though
these and many others are of central
importance. Increasingly, the accumulation of issues surrounding legal ethics is
producing a
systemic agenda. Commentators regularly decry the apparent general
lack of ethical practice in lawyers today.13 The
repetition of the assertion is likely to be demoralising and irritating to those
many lawyers who, credibly, see themselves as
ethical practitioners.
Nevertheless, these lawyers will likely acknowledge that the problem is now
chronic. One view is that a distinctive
and regressive “lawyer
personality” has emerged which is responsible for much of the
disquiet,14 though it seems pertinent to focus equally
on the causes of the lawyer “personality,” if it can be determined.
A recent issue of the International Journal of the Legal Profession
entitled “Lawyering for a Fragmented
World”15 brackets the discussion of causes
succinctly. In that issue, Pue asserts that nothing less than the “death
of God”16 and the consequential weakening of
“lesser gods” – rationality, the rule of law, and cultural
identity –
have taken away from many Westerners the basis for any value
choices. Reciting Margaret Thatcher’s comment that “there’s
no
such thing as society,”17 Pue suggests that there
are no longer any agreed scripts upon which a single values base can proceed for
any sector of a “post-Society
society.”18
Indeed, so many variables affect value choice that the very notion that we share
the same values seems offensively patronising. This
is a bleak present with a
potentially bleak future.
How are lawyers to proceed? If this question
suggests a refusal to sink in social and spiritual quicksand, then there is
hope. Hope,
however, is quite difficult when we are faced with the
inconsistencies in our justice system, as they are reported almost daily on
each
page of the newspapers and case reports. To take a compelling example,
McGillivray19 illustrates the “horror” of
valueless existence with her acute retelling of the Bernado/Homolka murderers in
Ontario.
In this case, one of the world’s most advanced justice systems
was relatively content to see a husband and wife, mutually responsible
for
ghastly serial rapes and killings, receive very different sentences. The case
demonstrated how fraying threads of law, gender,
and psychiatry were badly
entangled. Each murderer was as culpable as the other. The male is never to be
released; the female –
Karla Homolka – received just 14 years
imprisonment. There was no adequate reason to discriminate between the two in
the expiation
of an identical guilt. Referring to the values conflicts behind
this depressing result, McGillivray asks, “What is guilt when
discourses
collide?”20 In all, the law and its lawyers were
central players.
If there is definition to the issue of guilt – and,
hence, responsibility – within law, it must be in the discourse, whether
colliding or not. Continuing the discourse on values is at the centre of this
struggle. But is this suggestion too glib? As Pue reminds
us,
[l]awyers, unfortunately, are daily called upon to “judge,” to
decide for others, and to decide for themselves how they
will empower or
frustrate others. Aware, perhaps . . . that the core of our
professionalism rests on “just another” contested
“set of
narratives,” that our history provides no definitive answers for our
present, we can take no joy in the “laid
back pluralism” literary
scholars detect in life after God.21
If, however, we regard our dilemma as
involving a journey rather than a destination, this melancholy can be
challenged, not with a
solution but with a process. This would not be a
new road, merely one less known. It would also be one of the oldest. As Solomon
states,
Part of the problem is the way we tend to separate – or pretend to
separate – our business from our personal lives, as
if these were
unrelated and independent, as if one “left one’s values at the
office door.” But of course, not only
do we spend an enormous amount of
our waking lives “in the office;” our values are not divided up into
two (or more)
categories. . . . The point is to view one’s life
as a whole and not separate the personal and the public or professional,
or duty
and pleasure.22
A focus on the ideal lawyer as one who integrates her or his
professional and personal lives could begin with lawyers’ individual
initiatives. Some consciously attempt this now. They seem likely, however, to
remain in the minority in the face of a jurisprudence
and a system of legal
education that remains reluctant to weigh up the impact of its players and their
competing values as formal
contributors to a distinctly impersonal concept, that
of the Rule of Law.
A CRUCIAL OBJECTIVE – IDENTIFYING VALUES
A central foundation of lawyers’ ethics (related no doubt to the
derivation of the word “ethos” from the notion
of
custom23) is this basic creed of the Rule of Law
– that is, the notion that fairness to all people can only be guaranteed
by “the
law” (and not by individuals,24 in
the strict sense). Although battered by the modern crisis of
meaning,25 this creed, nevertheless, remains essential
for our social well-being. Social progress and good lawyering are indispensable
to each
other. Under attack from social apathy and community distrust, the Rule
of Law is in fact acutely dependent upon lawyers who personally
value justice
before income. In my view, the Rule of Law will only be upheld by individual,
honourable practitioners.
The obvious fact that society needs credible and
honest lawyers – and that they are perceived to be in short
supply26 – makes it more important to be precise
about the values base that underlies their actions. It is not enough to dismiss
the
need for investigation27 and impatiently state that
there is an urgent need to get on with the task of redefining the model lawyer,
post haste. It will be
difficult to position remedial education or values
awareness programmes in the profession and in our law schools unless we have
real
information about values diversity.
Thus, an essential preliminary task
in many jurisdictions is to identify exactly what values govern the mass of
Western lawyers’
behaviour. While as yet there is only limited and
indirect28 empirical research material available to
provide an answer, a workable hypothesis is that “values” ought to
be the focus
here rather than “ethics” as such. The latter it would
appear, in my experience, are now confused in the minds of many
Western lawyers
with proscriptive rules of conduct, and this regrettable association tends to
kill off the most active exploration
of the rich and diverse roots of
ethics.29
It is also possible, as Simon suggests,
that the study of formal codes of ethics undermines “complex, creative
judgment and
. . . subverts the vital aspirations of
professionalism.”30 Hutchinson is quite definite
when he states that
[r]eliance on codes atrophies the moral intelligence and leaves
lawyers’ adrift without a moral compass when the professional
rules run
out or give conflicting advice.31
Although a code can tend to promote purely
instrumental actions, there remain many situations where lawyers can, in fact,
decide with
some freedom how they will behave. It is possible, therefore, that
values affect practitioner motivations and, hence, their behaviour
just as
keenly as, for example, the fear of sanction (or the faint promise of praise)
under a law society code.
A BUSINESS OR A PROFESSION?
A popular hypothesis32 is that the
“conversion” of many legal practices from a professional to a
business orientation for economic reasons has
cut across attempts by governments
(and, ironically, the organised profession) to improve practitioner behaviour
– and with
it access to justice. I suggest that this situation will not
change appreciably unless and until there is a reawakening of the discourse
about personal and so-called “professional” values among
lawyers.
There is, of course, a great deal of scholarship, principally in the
United States, concerning the perceived lack of values of practising
lawyers. In
particular, in his bleak but influential book The Lost
Lawyer,33 Kronman describes his understanding of
the legal malaise for an audience beyond lawyers. Kirby and Dawson, judges of
the High Court
of Australia, have weighed in with their views; they essentially
agree with Kronman that the influence of business has undermined
the ethical
practice of law.34
Journal articles since the
publication of Kronman’s book in 1993 have discussed various dimensions of
the problem: for example,
they have considered the effect of modern legal
practice on lawyers’ ethics and35 the importance
of “nourishing” the profession;36 some have
attempted to rebut Kronman’s thesis.37 A recent
article by Robert MacCrate, former American Bar Association (“ABA”)
President and highly influential authority
on American legal education, does not
dispel concern. MacCrate, who is clearly proud of the profession’s
achievements, suggests
that the problems with ethical conduct in
the American legal profession that are identified by Kronman are restricted
to the impact
of the culture of “elite law schools and . . .
large law firms over the last 25 years.”38 While
MacCrate argues that Kronman does not make the same specific criticism of the
mass of the 800,000 American lawyers and draws
some comfort from this
distinction, he is not sanguine about the situation. It is significant that in
his 1992 report to the ABA
on the relationship between legal education and
professional development39 he did, pointedly, identify
a number of skills and, significantly, four “professional
values”40 (as opposed to personal values) that
should be taught in law schools.
While MacCrate considers that the amount of
professional and academic debate since the release of his
report41 suggests that things are
improving,42 it is clear that there is as yet no
large-scale empirical evidence for this confidence. The US profession, for one,
is not sanguine
about the situation. In 1996 the ABA weighed in again with
another report recommending extensive strategies for teaching professionalism
in
law schools and in a post-admission context; however, it would not (and, in my
opinion, probably could not) mandate any of
them.43
There are signs that lawyers’
intentions to practice law honourably cannot be assumed any longer. In January
1999 the Conference
of United States Chief Justices adopted “A National
Lawyer Plan on Lawyer Conduct and
Professionalism”44 which brought together many
credible initiatives to improve the court-based supervision of American lawyers.
While the language of
this report remains firmly in the land of aspiration and
prescription rather than in the examination of causative issues, the plan
called
for the provision of
accurate information [to the Court] about the character and fitness of
law students who apply for bar admission.45 (emphasis added)
One might wonder
how can this be done with confidence by law schools without an in-depth
investigation that identifies students’
values. Even if commitment to this
sort of investigation existed, there is, I believe, the risk that the
investigation would result
only in a great deal of academic, judicial, and
professional discussion. This debate could, of course, be a good thing; it could
in some diffuse way indicate that improvement is occurring in practising
lawyers’ values – and demonstrate that their
behaviour is improving.
Alternatively, the debate may only be evidence of the thought processes of those
of us discussing the issues,
as I suspect it is.
American concern with the
professional values of lawyers is shared in the United Kingdom, where the
emphasis is upon the role of law
schools. Economides directly raises the values
issue in his introduction to a collection of essays on the ethics challenge for
law
schools.46 After acknowledging that a
“gap” exists in law school curricula in the United Kingdom, he
asserts that there “is
no consensus as to what should fill this moral
vacuum . . . .”47 In my opinion,
the vacuum is not just an irritation to practitioners but a positive
disadvantage to their craft: it is patent that
so much of modern professional
life – in and beyond the law – positively requires the ability to
reason ethically and
to make ethical judgments.48 And
this goes well beyond an automatic reliance upon the methodology of technical
dissection that pervades law school teaching. Traditional
casebook methods on
their own, while crucial for discerning substantive rules of law, can engender a
delusional confidence among
students that this (exciting) process of
legal delineation also represents the peak of professional aspiration. It is no
longer enough to argue that this necessary “forensic”
ability is
dispassionate (requiring no moral position) in either an adversarial or
non-adversarial setting.
Eschete, in particular, makes clear that in a
social, cultural, and professional sense, the very qualities of successful
adversarial
lawyering gradually produce “undesirable features
. . . [of the lawyer’s]
character.”49 Hutchinson describes it thus:
[O]n the basis that lawyers tend to identify more than most with their jobs,
the amorality of their professional role will begin to
infect their personal
lives – the amorality will become its own impoverished morality by
default.50
If this is true, it is not useful to argue that typical
adversarial lawyers can separate their personal and professional lives
indefinitely.
Eschete maintains that the justification of adversarial positions
– the resolution of individual conflict without violence
– does not
insulate lawyers from its moral consequences:
[T]he law is not, like a sport or . . . [philosopher’s]
. . . skirmish, sealed off from moral life. Accordingly, lawyers
cannot
use the permissible skills of their trade with ruthless efficiency for
the sake of the client’s triumph without working wrong.51
I would
assert that the lawyer knows, even if the client does not, that bigger issues
and principles are at stake in every small contest
and that even those
practitioners who profess to see no ethical issue in certain behaviour have
simply chosen not to look.
The combative, adversarial practitioner –
the archetype most commonly promoted by law school curricula – will
obviously
remain with us. However, I ask whether this breed of “character
impoverished” lawyer is too ill-suited to do anything
less than fight
– unless an awareness of values diversity is acquired early in law school
and nurtured throughout the lawyer’s
professional
life.52
In my observation of former clinical
students at Monash University, lawyers’ personal satisfaction with their
working lives
is already adversely affected by the conflict between law as a
business and law as a profession. I see apathy towards, or dislike
of,
commercial legal practice among lawyers with about three to five years
experience. This dissatisfaction is echoed by senior jurists
and
others.53 Professional commitment is put at real risk
when, in addition, the moral “abyss” is made public by the
circumstances
of malpractice.54 If this gap is to be
filled and legal professionalism protected, lawyers must come to grips with what
lies at the bottom of their
personal, moral crevasse: with their values –
good and bad.
DEFINING VALUES
There is considerable, though incomplete, discussion in the literature about
values and ethics. I will make an effort to tease out
these terms as I see them
before I discuss the survey so that the purposes of the latter are clear. Much
of the literature discussion
involves overlapping definitions that are sometimes
difficult to distinguish. Thus, the United Kingdom Lord Chancellor’s
“Advisory
Committee on Legal Education and Conduct”
(“ACLEC”) 1996 report calls explicitly for renewed emphasis in law
schools
on legal values and contextual knowledge.55
These are described generally by Halpin and Palmer56 as
addressing the “deeper significance that the discipline of law is regarded
as having for society.”57
There also is, of
course, no consistency in the use of the terms “values” and
“ethics.” Halpin and Palmer
for example, speak of
[l]egal [v]alues [conveying] two separate categories. One covers values that
are identified with the law – a commitment to the
rule of law, to justice,
and fairness. . . . The other covers lawyers’
professional ethics in the wide sense – encompassing high
ethical standards, professional skills, responsibility to the client,
equality of opportunity, and access to justice.58 (emphasis added)
This
passage describes “values” only in terms of professional life and
activity – as if there is some separation
between professional and
personal values. It is echoed strongly by MacCrate in his description of four
“professional values”59 which he links to
certain defined responsibilities: they, in turn, bear a close resemblance to
Halpin and Palmer’s second category
of “legal
values.”60 Nor are these hazy intersections
assisted much by those who look more closely at the “values” issues.
In regard to the ACLEC’s “First
Report,”61 Sheinman notes that
[w]hen it talks about ethics and values . . . [it] fails to
distinguish between the morality underlying particular laws, the morality
of
citizens, and the morality of lawyers . . . 62
His point, however,
does not take us very far because he is disinclined to explore these
distinctions insofar as they may be useful
in improving lawyers’
behaviour. Sheinman appears, however, to agree with the MacCrate emphasis upon
the “professional”
in ethics. Using the term “ethics”
rather than “values,” Sheinman takes a very different stance to
Eschete.
He cites, by way of comparison with Eschete, various scenarios where
lawyers could morally choose to behave differently in their
personal lives from
their professional lives. Leaving to one side the psychological and emotional
complications for the lawyer engaging
in this dual life, Sheinman recognises
that there is a debate about the morality of this
approach,63 but he holds to his view that
if we are to produce lawyers with robust ethical standards, then it is not
personal ethics, but professional ethics [that] we ought
to be teaching
them.64
It is not clear to me why he makes this
choice, but Sheinman does not appear to see any crucial behavioural link between
the “personal”
and the “professional.” He does briefly
suggest that a “survey” would be useful (except for the fact that
experience tells us that lawyers attitudes are
variable)65 and moves on to call for more discourse and
a “set of fully articulated underlying
principles.”66 While Sheinman’s important
purpose is to call for a profound reinvestigation of the basis of legal
ethics,67 his analysis does, I believe, suffer from a
reluctance to recognise the professional/personal interaction.
It is difficult to separate legal values and professional values from
many definitions of professional ethics or legal ethics. As
a result, for the
purposes of this article I will define the latter two terms in the common
proscriptive manner as the
rules which govern lawyers’ behaviour by virtue of the fact that
they are lawyers.68 (emphasis in the
original)
It is somewhat disappointing (some would also say premature) to
give up the nobility of the word “ethics” to the reduced
significance of a set of rules. In my opinion, however, the change is entrenched
among many practitioners and, thus, may as well
be acknowledged. If this were
agreed, at least the confusion between ethics and values as concepts would be
reduced.
The survey that I conducted places a deliberate emphasis upon values
as distinct from ethics. Values are said to underlie our behaviour
and are
assumed, therefore, to have great influence over us; they are rarely discussed
with any precision, however.69 Values have been
variously defined,70 and it is important to distinguish
between different types of values. Personal values71
(for example, honesty) can be distinguished from economic, aesthetic, and even
recreational values. Personal values may overlap fundamental
moral values. Thus,
honesty intersects with the moral values of truth and justice but is not
identical with these concepts.
In this research, I have focused upon
personal values because, in my opinion, survey respondents would be able to
identify more closely
the questions asked about values. Ethics, in my opinion,
have been discussed to the point where they are now, regrettably, confused
with
specific rules of conduct. While ethical behaviour has been understood as a
“positive,”72 ethics is now more often
associated with a negative “do not.”73
Thus, exhortations to lawyers to behave ethically might therefore fail to
improve lawyers’ behaviour – in the same way,
I believe, that a
parent who routinely criticises a child has less impact on the child’s
behaviour than the parent who praises.
The parenting analogy may be trite and
perhaps patronising, but my hope is, nevertheless, that a discussion about
values (as a “positive”74) will in some way
lead to a deeper examination of motives.
Values, as distinct from ethics as I
have defined them, are, nevertheless, also likely to lose their educational
impact if they are
defined narrowly in the MacCrate sense as professional
values. To define the values which lawyers need in terms of the professional
role alone suggests that personal values can differ or be ignored. This is
dangerous because many personal values such as honesty
are fundamental to
lawyering.
MacCrate is not alone here at what I believe to be a dead end.
The progressive Clinical Legal Education Association in the United
States
continues to talk only of professional values.75 I
suggest that only by personalising values, appreciating that they compete
and operate at several levels, will they retain their potency. Thus, in this
survey, I considered
it desirable to, in effect, force upon respondents choices
between personal and professional obligations in order to minimise (merely)
“intellectual” responses and, at the same time, maximise the chances
that the answers given would be predictive of actual
behaviour. In my opinion,
it is no good for example, emphasising to a law student (or newly admitted
lawyer) that there is a professional
value to promote justice and fairness in
the legal system76 if, at the same time, there is no
attempt to explore what this really implies for honesty
and/or77 integrity at the personal level.
Instinctively, students who become personally involved in a well-run
(live client) experiential learning process know that this sort of discord is to
be explored rather than simply
swallowed.78 As
Hutchinson says,
The challenge is to integrate the demands of a professional role with the
dictates of a professional morality and be able to construct
important bridges
between the two so that they can each support and fructify each other: one feeds
off the other.79
Thus, for example, the value of striving to support the
Rule of Law80 through the right to adequate
representation (as a guarantee of impartiality in a democracy) is difficult to
attain without first
reinforcing the personal values of courage and
perseverance.
Personal values are not one-dimensional. Differing values
constantly compete for dominance; they tend to be ranked in their impact
upon us
and can be a mixture of both “bad” and “good.” One
useful categorisation81 divides personal values into
foundational values (addressing basic needs for survival), focus values (daily
concerns for identity,
work, and self worth), and future values (at the
aspirational or noble end of behaviour). Under pressure, we tend to regress
towards
personal values that help us survive. If survival is assured, the
potential emerges for growth towards the aspirational
values.82 It is these higher level personal values to
which law students and lawyers can often aspire, and not just because their
basic needs
have been met through, for example, the accidents of birth,
ethnicity, or class. Students with and without privileged backgrounds
are often
zealous in their efforts to “do justice.” Of course, it is not easy
to “allow” students (in the
facilitative sense) to recognise that
the practice of aspirational values combined with the provision of
competent service is linked to the achievement of their basic and everyday
needs
(since quality/best practice approaches often attract respect and the referral
of new clients83), but the potential is there for law
teachers to exploit.
Hutchinson sees the context for this opportunity:
Mindful that ethical training is primarily concerned with learning about
oneself, students need to confront ethical dilemmas in concrete
circumstances in
order to begin to discover (or construct), question, and articulate their own
moral views before they struggle with
the complex demands of a professional
ethic. . . . A pervasive difficulty in achieving this is that
legal ethics is more about responsibilities
than rights and, therefore, does not
sit easily or well with much of the legal education that lawyers
receive.84
Experiential teaching and learning
methodologies – particularly those where law students assume
responsibility for assisting
real clients – can ignite the moral
imagination of our future lawyers. They provide students with an opportunity to
behave
in legal practice in a morally aware manner.85
If the need for major improvement in lawyers’ values awareness can be
quantitatively demonstrated, a fundamental change in legal
education is more
than a possibility. That demonstration is the purpose of this article. There are
measurable differences in values
among lawyers and law students. These
differences may not all be statistical significant, or yet capable of
international application.
Nevertheless, the values exposed in the survey which
follows come out of a carefully designed methodology.
WHY MONASH LAW GRADUATES?
I decided that a useful pilot process for a large international comparative
survey could be undertaken with former Monash law students.
The Monash alumni
lists, which are maintained by the University, provided a convenient and
relatively low cost access route to the
addresses of students who graduated over
the past two decades. Unlike graduates from many other Australian law schools,
approximately
one-third of these respondents would likely have completed an
undergraduate clinical experience and, thus, could help determine whether
there
is any significant connection between clinical experience and values
awareness.
Monash University has for 21 years provided an extensive
live-client clinical experience. Since 1990, it has attempted to give some
of
its clinical students the opportunity to work systemically on socio-legal
issues86 that arise in that programme. Anecdotal
student reaction to the systemic exposure has often been very positive. Although
the emphasis
of the entire programme has favoured the functional clinical norm
– reflecting the traditional professional emphasis upon competence
in the
context of practical skills – in recent years this has expanded to include
an ethical sensitivity in keeping with growing
community pressure for greater
accountability among lawyers.87
It has,
accordingly, become important to ascertain whether there is as yet any
observable effect of the clinical process on the development
of law
students’ values. If, for instance, some connection of this sort could be
demonstrated, law school deans, admitting
authorities, and regulators would have
available, for the first time, a reliable way to inculcate, via the
clinical process, ethics in that part of legal education which seems to so
readily excite student interest.
Methodology
This survey obliquely measures lawyers’ values;
its conclusions are based upon the responses from former law students to survey
questions. Rather than directly ask lawyers about their values, which seems
naive and may be treated dismissively by some respondents,
I decided to use the
psychological and educational device of the hypothetical situation, adding a
personal dimension to each scenario
to further reduce the level of abstraction
and assist in actual values identification. Since the scenarios were also
reasonably commonplace,
I reasoned that a degree of personal identification with
the lawyer’s dilemma that is raised in each scenario would emerge.
I
considered it unlikely that respondents would reply with sufficient thought to a
telephone survey. I believed that a lengthy explanation
of the survey, which
advised potential respondents about how their information would be used, had to
precede the questionnaire if
it was to be conducted ethically. I believed that
respondents would not easily comprehend the approach of the questionnaire or
feel
like cooperating with the necessary time that a verbal explanation would
require – even if survey funds permitted such contact
and the inevitable
telephone reminder calls. Nor did I think that focus group interview
methods88 were appropriate for a pilot process that
would seek maximum quantitative information, in order to pave the way for
subsequent, more
extensive research.
While technically I could have selected
a random sample from the entire Monash graduate population over the relevant
period, this
would have involved extensive and costly tracing of
“missing” graduates.89 For a pilot survey,
the costs/benefits favoured a large sample size generated by simple reliance on
the alumni lists. In this survey,
I hoped that, in addition to preliminary
findings on general values and the possible “clinical link,” I would
obtain
useful design information for future large-scale random sampling, if
adequate funding were to become available. Within the survey
as a whole, several
indicators referred to below suggest that the sampling decision was
reasonable.
Question Design and Delivery
At the heart of the survey instrument is the
structure of the eleven individual questions. These were based on scenarios that
I designed
with deliberately personal implications arising from common
experience of practice. By this I mean that I believed that respondents
would
find it difficult to respond to the hypothetical from just a
“professional” perspective. I included varied fields
of practice
– commercial, family, and criminal – to cater for different
professional experiences. The initial drafts
were trialed with a group of 30
hand-picked practitioners and academic lawyers in order to minimise obvious
ambiguity. I chose this
trial group because I knew them to be insightful and by
nature inclined to approach the task of refining the scenarios thoughtfully.
After their initial comments were used to modify and refine the questions, a
consultant survey designer90 assessed each question,
the practitioners’ comments, and the overall survey approach to validate,
vary, or reject the text
of each question. While no scenarios were specifically
rejected, the number of questions were reduced to minimise repetition as a
result of the consultant’s input. In some cases, the consultant’s
report recommended that the scenarios be simplified
in order to make choices
more straightforward; however, I decided in some instances to retain multiple
issues within individual questions
in order to reflect the reality encountered
by practitioners, even at the cost of possible confusion of the respondents.
This decision
was taken in the knowledge that the target population is
sophisticated and could be regarded as skilled in balancing competing loyalties
and pressures. Questions were worded to ensure that the principal actor in each
scenario could be male or female in order to minimise
variability in response
due to gender.
Approximately 38% of all respondents had completed a course in
Clinical Legal Education during their degree. This percentage is similar
to the
participation rate of all students in the clinical programme at Monash. Since
one objective of this study was the identification
of values in graduates with
clinical experience compared to those with none, adequate representation of
clinically experienced graduates
in the sample was crucial, and it was achieved.
The similarity of these percentages supports the view that the sample is likely
to
be representative of the population for the specified period.
At the
completion of spreadsheet coding, which converted text responses to pre-defined
numerical codes, I determined basic frequency
distributions (ie bar graphs
showing the raw numbers of responses in each category of answer) using the pivot
table and graph functions
of MS Excel. Statistical analysis using
Statistical Package for the Social Sciences (SPSS) Software was also
performed. Although the sample, as discussed above, was not random, I believed
that the characteristics of the sample were
sufficiently robust for this
analysis to be of use.
Statistical Methods and Tests
In this section I describe the techniques and methods
that I used to generate and analyse the information that I received from the
respondents. As noted above, 30 participants helped to refine the draft
questionnaire. Four thousand (4000) questionnaires were dispatched
to law
students who graduated in the period 1980 to 1998. This number was selected on
pragmatic grounds; it represented a balance
between the cost of the distribution
and reliability of alumni contact details. Seven-hundred-and-three (703)
responses were received
in the period of three months, and of these, 644 were
considered valid in all respects: therefore, for this group, all questions
were
sufficiently completed to warrant coding in an initial spreadsheet. Fifty nine
(59) respondents omitted some answers or submitted
answers that could not be
coded with certainty – not apparently in any pattern – to various
questions. Where respondents
among this second group had completed clear answers
to questions, those answers were coded into the spreadsheet. These differences
account for the slight variability in the number of valid responses to different
questions, as is apparent below. The ratio of 59
incomplete responses to 703
total responses meant that there was a consequential 8.4% overall error in total
responses. I stress,
however, that the responses coded and reported in this
article were assessed for completeness before coding in relation to each
question
analysed.
It might be speculated that those who chose to respond
were sufficiently interested in the issues and that the very large group which
did not respond could contain a higher proportion of individuals with
“bad” or apathetic approaches to moral issues and,
perhaps, ethical
decision making. If this were true, the reliability of this survey would be
questionable. However, I do not think
this conclusion is valid as will be seen
below. There is, on nearly every question, a profound variation in responses
between what
might be described as “good” and “bad”
approaches to values choices.
In order to check for accuracy and internal
consistency in responses, that is to limit the opportunity of respondents to
give answers
that the respondents themselves might assume were
“desirable” in some way, I asked all respondents to complete a
standard
Rokeach Values Survey (“RVS”).91
This instrument is well known in sociological
research.92 It asks respondents to answer a standard
set of apparently unrelated questions about personal values. I inserted it in
the survey
document as a “Part B” questionnaire after the
“Part A” legal scenarios.93 Answers to
“Part B” values questions could be coded in such a way as to
indicate the underlying preferences of respondents
for particular contrasting
values. The nominated RVS values categories are either
“Instrumental” (that is, of “day-to-day”
relevance) or
“Terminal” (that is, of “ultimate” or long-term
significance). The distinction between the
two categories is made to cover both
the immediate and long-term preferences of respondents.
As can be seen in the
footnote below, the layout of the list of RVS values is not apparently
subdivided in any way and gives no immediate
clue to respondents as to any
so-called “desirable” set of choices, in order that the recorded
choices actually reflect
the views of respondents. In fact, in the footnote,
“Instrumental” values appear in column one and
“Terminal”
values appear in column two. Unless respondents are
familiar with an RVS, they would not likely be able to predict which values
might
be “required.”
It is common in RVS analysis to encounter
all respondents giving priority to the same values for the first three or
four choices so that, for example, “ambitious”
might receive 1047 as
a sum of responses, followed by “logical” at 967,
“independent” at 832, and so on in
descending levels of magnitude.
Often, it is only at, say, the fourth or lower level of magnitude, where
differences in values become
evident. Thus, in the analysis below of whether
lawyers would choose a pro bono opportunity or work towards their
promotion by putting in longer billable hours, the first three values chosen for
both groups of
respondents in the “Instrumental” category were the
same. However, the fourth most important value for the group choosing
pro
bono was “helpful,” while “logical” was chosen by
the group which preferred extra work for the employer.
The “Part
B” instructions ask for RVS choices to be made in the context of
respondents “approach to the practice
of law. . . .”
This instruction allows the sum of responses to “Part B” RVS values
choices to be connected to the
sum of responses to the “Part A”
legal scenarios. After RVS values choices are coded and preferences divided
among the
available options, it is possible to gauge if the responses to
“Part A” legal scenarios are likely to be valid, that
is, accurate
and internally consistent with one another.
As a general result, from
“Part B” respondents in fact gave most weight to
“honesty” (Instrumental) and “self
respect” (Terminal)
ranging down to those considered least important – in comparative terms
– “self control”
and “equality” respectively. As
will be seen below when answers to individual Part A legal scenarios are
considered,
analysis and comparison between responses to Parts A and B of the
whole survey indicated a high level of accuracy and internal consistency
among
respondents.
Three specific tests of statistical relationship were used in
the analyses. Pearson’s Chi Squared Test of Association
(λ) is a standard descriptive statistic.
It was used extensively in the analyses to determine if a hypothesised
relationship between
two factors, for example, between gender and an interest in
doing “good (legal) works,” existed or not.
λ shows the strength of association
between two variables. The lower the λ
value, the smaller the association and vice versa. A high level of association
does not necessarily confirm a causative relationship between the two
variables (in either direction), but it is indicative of some causative
effect.
A UnivarateF analysis was performed in some questions to measure the
connection between variables. The UnivariateF test has a similar
purpose to
λ and was used to provide additional
support for any likely correlations. It is a variety of the Multivariate
Analysis of Variance
(“MANOVA”) mathematical procedure and measures
mean (average) differences between test results to determine the strength
of
their relationship to one another.
A correlation matrix was also used in
some analyses. This technique allows correlations between more than two
variables to be compared
in a table, indicating which relationships are
significantly related.
RESULTS
Basic Statistics
Three-hundred-and-forty-four (50.66%) females and 335 males (49.34%) completed the survey sufficiently to allow coding of responses. This balance in gender responses is important because, although the sample was not random and was, in effect, self-selecting, it mirrors the general population. The reasonable inference from the size and make-up of the sample is that it is a reasonable predictor of population responses, subject to the issue of the age of respondents. The age distribution, segmented by gender, was instructive: [see Figure 1].
Figure 1: All respondents –Segmented by Age and Gender – Males Dominant with Age
As may be observed, most respondents fell within a 25-45 year old age range.
Most of these were in the younger range of 25-35 years.
Males tend to dominate
in the sample in the older groups, perhaps as a function of the reputed
“glass ceiling” which
appears to operate in
law94 or perhaps because women in these age groups are
likely to be concentrating on families. It is also possible that the sample is
skewed
against older respondents because Alumni records are more likely to be
accurate for more recent graduates. As a result, the frequency
distributions for
the older age groups do not, in this pilot,95 contain
enough responses to assess whether their patterns of response differ markedly
from younger graduates. It is, however, fairly
clear that responses from
respondents in the younger age groups are adequate to measure their impact for
the population in those
groups.
Graphic representations of
respondents’ gender, segmented by occupation, ethnicity, year of
graduation, and parents’ occupations,
indicate that respondents as a group
were dominated by solicitors who considered themselves “Australian.”
The term “Australian,”
while imprecise because of the tendency for
respondents from families where parents were born overseas to identify with more
than
one background in varying circumstances, was a categorisation that could
not be excluded. Female solicitors (197) overall slightly
outnumbered their male
counterparts (183) – especially among recent graduates – however,
male barristers (49) easily
outnumbered females (14). Most respondents (399) had
parents with professional, teaching, or business – what might be
considered
as “middle class” – backgrounds, compared to the
total of 679. All in all, the profiles of respondents –
relatively
“comfortable,” – practicing lawyers – are unsurprising
and are consistent with anecdotal information
and demographic snapshots of
Victorian lawyers.96
In the subsequent analyses of
“yes/no” choices in relation to individual questions, it is most
interesting that the values
of self-control and equality are consistently
more or less important for particular choices. This is to be expected if
respondents are answering the survey questions in an internally
consistent
manner. Thus, for example, in the question designed to discover how many
graduates thought lawyers’ pro bono activities important, those who
answered “yes” often gave a higher weighting to the RVS value of
“equality”
in preference to “self-control.” Repetition
of similar patterns across different questions provides a key validator
indicating
that respondents in the sample were answering questions carefully.
Frequency Distributions and Tests of Significance of Answers to Each Question
In the following description of results, answers to
separate questions are analysed and the main findings stated for ease of
understanding
in relation to that question alone. Further, questions which could
be expected to produce answers which may bear upon one another
are dealt with
immediately afterwards in this article rather than in the order that the
questions were asked. Not all questions are
reproduced here for reasons of space
and because some tend only to confirm broadly similar information. Frequency
distributions performed
for responses to specific questions are available from
the author. A summary of findings and of conclusions drawn from those findings
appears at the end of this paper.
Demographic information of the sort
represented in the graph above was available for cross-tabulation against
answers to all questions;
however, as will be seen in relation to the answers to
Question 1 (“Q1”) below, such information is of minimal use because
the number of responses in sub-categories are, in most cases, too small to
permit extrapolation to the population (that is, to all Monash law
graduates). Accordingly, while answers to Q1 are canvassed extensively to
illustrate this point, in succeeding questions
only a selection of all
distributions calculated are discussed in order to save space and avoid
restatement of similar information.
I consider those chosen for reproduction
here to provide useful insights.
The text of the chosen questions, which were
preceded by a set of instructions,97 are set out as
they appeared in the survey document and are followed by individual analysis.
“Corporate” or “Justice” priorities
Question 1 – “Corporate” or “Justice” priorities
You are a solicitor working in a large commercial law firm. The Public Interest Law Clearing House (PILCH) approaches you to work on a prominent test case about women who kill in self- defence. Your interest in this area is well known. The work would be pro bono and very high profile for you personally but of little interest to your firm. The matter requires a lot of time and work. Your senior partner however wants you to increase your billable hours for the firm. The firm does not usually do any pro bono work but there is no actual policy against it. Your time is currently so limited you could only realistically do one or the other.
Would you agree to work on the PILCH case? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Business Efficacy (Firm’s Profit)
0 1 2 3 4 Employer Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4 Access to Justice
0 1 2 3 4 Professional Ambition
0 1 2 3 4 Employment Security
Response to Q1
There was a slight preference among respondents for “extra work for the firm” (52.2%), thus respondents declined the pro bono request [see Fig. 2]. As the sample size is reasonable in the younger age groups, it is safe to conclude that, in respect of this scenario, younger Monash graduates in law are fairly equally distributed between those who care to some extent about the public good and those who may not care as much. While it could be thought that they might also care equally about both had they a job with some security, it can be argued that the sample size is large enough to contain respondents from both categories and to balance out the differences that might be caused by this factor.
Figure 2: Slight Preference of Respondents to Do Extra
Work for Firm and to Decline Pro Bono Request
This result also appears to indicate that there is
significant hesitation, possibly even a lack of sufficient interest, in working
for the public good. Given that the scenario balances the cost/benefit of the
pro bono opportunity in such a way as to identify employer reluctance
without confirming it, this decision points towards a substantial values
“gap” or difference. The implicit, though largely
anecdotal,98 assumption that Australian lawyers hold
homogeneous values is, therefore, not supported by this evidence.
However,
it may be thought that if about half of all respondents are interested in the
public good, Monash alumni (at least) have
“good”
values.99 This is, it seems, the view taken by the Law
Institute of Victoria (“LIV”), which considers that there is a
substantial
pro bono commitment by the Victorian profession as a whole.
In the only other recent survey published of Victorian legal practitioners in
relation to this issue, a study by a research division of LIV indicated that
53.2% of the 32% who responded to the survey (2684 responses
to 8500
questionnaires) handled one or more pro bono matters in the previous 12
months.100 To the extent that this result of the LIV
survey is consistent with a central prediction of this survey – that there
is a link
between values and “justice” behaviour – it seems
likely that, in future, parallel investigations of lawyers’
behaviour
– ideally by collaborating law societies – will be useful to test
for the existence of a causal relationship
between values and actions.
Interestingly, however, the LIV finding was qualified by the statement that
30% of the respondents declined to answer the question.
The discrepancy in
results between this investigation and that of the LIV is perhaps, in part,
explained by the response failure:
most other questions put by the LIV –
concerned with areas of legal practice, remuneration, hours of work, and other
matters
associated with awareness of professional services to members –
were answered fully.101 It is difficult to see why a
respondent to the LIV survey would not be willing, even confidentially, to
record his/her participation
in pro bono activity. It is fruitless to
speculate too much, but, since a 30% nil response may well be composed of
persons who had no pro bono activity, the LIV survey may be significantly
over-recording actual pro bono participation. Accordingly, the responses
in this study may be closer to the reality of actual pro bono
participation.
Another note of discordance between the two surveys concerned
the gender split in relation to pro bono activity. While the LIV
cautiously observed102 that more males than females
were engaged in pro bono work, the study that surveyed only Monash
graduates reached the opposite conclusion [see Figure 3].
Figure 3: More Females than Males Would Participate
in Pro
Bono Activity
In this question, Pearson’s Chi Squared Test of Association
(χ2) expressed in standard statistical notation
for this association as: χ2(1) = 28.10, p =
.0000001 – showed a highly significant association between gender and
whether an individual would choose to
do PILCH work. The correlation here is
sufficiently strong to assert that females indicate that they are far more
likely assume pro bono work. The relationship between gender and the
decision taken is evident throughout this study and, in the light of the LIV
findings,
is clearly an issue that would benefit from further study.
It is
interesting that in the Monash survey of those who did have a background with
clinical experience, a slight majority indicated
that they would have chosen to
do pro bono work. In itself, this is unlikely to be significant. However,
the difference in decisions indicated by the respondents emerges when
the
numbers who had no such background are examined [see Figure 4]. In the group of
graduates without any clinical exposure, a larger
number chose “extra work
for the firm.” Taken together, the differing responses recorded for the
two groups point to
some relationship; however, the result is not statistically
significant (χ2(1) = 1.67, p = .20) to demonstrate
a relationship between a clinical education experience and a decision to
undertake public interest
work. This relationship also requires further detailed
exploration.
Figure 4: Minor Positive Relationship between Clinical Experience and “Yes” Decision re PILCH Work
In assigning relative importance to particular “legal” values as
decision motivators, all respondents behaved consistently
regardless of gender.
“Access to Justice” was important for those who selected pro
bono activity as their priority, and “Employment Security” was
most important for those who chose extra work for the firm.
The only obvious
variable was the decision itself to opt for public interest work or not. When
the responses for “marital status”
and the existence of children are
added to the analysis, it is notable that, while married respondents are
slightly more inclined
to choose extra work for the firm rather than pro
bono activity, the existence of children appears to have no effect on the
decision indicated.
A higher number of respondents among those who opted for
“extra work for the firm” had parents whose occupations fell
into
business categories. Otherwise, the primary decision had little statistical
association with parents’ occupations (χ
2(1) = 10.88, p = 0.14). Professional, academic, and business backgrounds
were dominant in both cases.
A comparison of ethnicity and parents’
occupations was not conclusive, presumably because the number of responses from
non-dominant
cultures is again too small (χ2(1) =
.21, p = 0.65). Correspondingly, it is clear that respondents have very
pronounced Anglo-Saxon or Anglo-Celt heritages. Occupational
grouping did not
appear to make any difference to the size of the “yes” and
“no” camps, with solicitors accounting
for over half of all
occupations in each category.
Reference has already been made to the Rokeach
Values Survey and to its crucial role in validating respondents’ answers
in the
section on methodology above. In this question, as in the survey as a
whole, a comparison of responses between the scenarios and
the RVS values
reveals a pattern which is consistent with the
“Yes”/“No” choices made by respondents [see
Figure 5].
Thus, the three most important RVS values to all respondents, whether they were
in favour of Public Interest Law Clearing
House (PILCH) work or not, were
identical. Importantly, this observation is true for both Instrumental as well
as Terminal values
in the RVS. Among the “Instrumental” values
group, the first three most important values to both “yes” and
“no” respondents were “honest,”
“responsible,” and “capable,” and in the
“Terminal”
values group, the first three most important values were
“self respect,” “happiness,” and a “sense
of
accomplishment.” Thereafter, the relative importance of different values
to both groups began to diverge, indicating where
the real values difference may
be.
As illustrated in the figure below, in the “Instrumental”
category the fourth most important value for the pro bono group was
“helpful,” while “logical” was chosen by the group that
preferred to do extra work for the employer.
Among those who said
“yes” to pro bono work in the “Terminal” group,
the fourth most important value was “inner harmony” to be contrasted
with “family
security” for those who chose “extra work for the
firm.” These results tend to confirm that the “Yes/“No”
choices made by respondents to this question are valid and reflect personal
values underlying professional choices.
Q1: Key Instrumental and Terminal Values
[Rokeach Values
Survey]
Finally, a correlation matrix was developed to display statistically
significant associations between motivating “professional”
values
and RVS values. The use of the correlation matrix supported the primary
correlations, indicating that individuals who weight
“employment
security” as a motivating value in a decision about whether to take on
PILCH work will also be likely to
value “business efficacy” and
“employment loyalty” as important. “Family security” and
“a
comfortable life” correlate with their approach to the practice
of law. Similarly, “professional ambition” correlates
with
“pleasure,” “social recognition,” and “a
comfortable life” for these individuals.
The next scenario focuses on
an issue that has a very high level of professional recognition, irrespective of
clinical experience.
It highlights the importance of the use of the hypothetical
situation as an exploratory tool.
Denial of Legal Aid
Question 8 – Denial of Legal Aid
You are a Victoria Legal Aid solicitor handling criminal matters. You have just received a file to defend charges of child sexual abuse where the victim is the only witness. Your client denies the allegations. The alleged victim is 14 years old. Your application for aid is rejected and you are told informally the managing director of Victoria Legal Aid wants to change the grant guidelines to exclude any grant of aid for a matter that would involve the cross examination of an alleged child victim in a sex abuse case. You suspect the change is due to bad press attacking such cross- examinations.
Would you argue in writing within VLA against
this change in policy? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Employer Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4 Professional Ambition
0 1 2 3 4 Client’s Interests
0 1 2 3 4 Access to Justice
0 1 2 3 4 Employment Security
Response to Q8
In this question respondents were presented with a
relatively simple choice that centered around the availability of legal aid in
the community. It was to be expected that most would choose to retain aid
because, in the Victorian context, its availability has
been steadily reduced in
recent years, and this has produced much criticism in the legal profession.
Thus, among the “retain
aid” majority,
UnivariateF103 tests place “access to
justice” and the “client’s interests” as the principal
motivating values.
It was considered possible, however, that the subsidiary
issue of sensitivity to victims of sexual assault might counter the legal
aid
emphasis, particularly if women were strongly represented in the sample. Of
considerable interest is that, although female respondent
numbers were well
represented, females were in the majority among the, admittedly, small
number of those who would deny legal aid. As may be observed below, these
respondents placed reliance
upon “access to justice” as their
motivating value. UnivariateF analysis confirms “access to justice”
as
the value that motivates women to deny aid, while men were principally
motivated by “professional ambition.” Pearson’s
Chi Squared
Test of Association analysis confirms a significant association between gender
and choice, with males being more likely
to indicate that they would retain aid
(χ2(1) = 11.26, p = .0008).
This result may
indicate a definitional and, in fact, a political issue with the terminology in
this question. Nevertheless, the corresponding
chart for those who would allow
aid indicates that women in that group were also clear that “access to
justice” was quite
important to their decision. In fact, among both males
and females who would retain aid, “access to justice” was their
prime motivator. In this question there appears to be little impact attributable
to clinical experience; this could be due to the
considerable profile which
legal aid has as an issue generally.
Comparison with the RVS values
responses shows a high level of agreement among those who would retain aid and
those who would deny
it. “Instrumental” values were identified as
the first five most important categories, while the first seven were identical
in the “Terminal” values sub-category. In the
“Instrumental” group, the divergence emerged at the sixth most
important value. Those who would retain legal aid chose
“broadminded” while those who would deny it settled upon
“self-control.”
In the “Terminal” group,
“equality” was preferred (at the eighth level of magnitude) by those
who choose
to retain aid while “true friendship” was chosen by those
respondents who would deny aid. Again, it would seem that uniform
personal
values among the “Yes”/“No” groups are the norm in
relation to this question, and divergence is
along expected lines.
The level
of consistency in the responses supports the contention that respondents are
identifying sufficiently with the scenarios
to give some confidence in the
results. Question construction (and, therefore, the precise situation in which
respondents find themselves)
is likely to be a crucial ingredient in exposing
differences in values.
While the values of those who chose to deny aid may
be considered atypical, responses to the next question indicated that there can
be no easy conclusion that the clear majority of respondents who chose to retain
legal aid might therefore be considered to have
“higher” values.
Concealment of Defalcation
Question 3 – Concealment of Defalcation
You are the Senior Partner in the firm of AMBD. Your son is the junior partner in the firm. You discover your son has a minor gambling problem and has taken money from the firm’s trust account to cover his debts. Fortunately you discover the problem in its very early stages. Your son is now undergoing counselling for his gambling addiction and appears to be recovering. The amount missing from the trust account is relatively small and you are certain could be reimbursed without attracting any attention.
Would you report the matter to the Legal Practice
Board or Victorian Lawyers RPA? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Personal Obedience to the Law
0 1 2 3 4 Parental Loyalty
Response to Q3
Despite an explicit obligation on all practitioners under the section 189 of the Legal Practice Act 1996 (Vic) to report a suspected defalcation, a clear majority of respondents (mostly males – see Figure 6) would remain silent. Although this is speculation, their response may be because of what appear to be good prospects for secrecy and their desire to protect their child rather than report the deficiency to the Legal Practice Board [see Figure 7].
Figure 6: Males More Likely than Females to Remain Silent than Report Deficiency in Son’s Trust Account
Figure 7: 3:2 Preference to Suppress Information on Trust Account Deficiency when Child would be Prosecuted
UnivariateF tests confirm what I had expected: that
“personal obedience to the law” is more important than
“parental
loyalty” among the minority who would report, and,
vice versa, among the majority who would remain silent. Interestingly,
Pearson’s Chi Squared Test of
Association analysis shows that gender is
not significant in the decision to report (χ2(1) =
2.91, p = .09). Among those who would keep silent, “spouse/parental
loyalty” and “personal happiness”
rated highly. Where
“silence” was preferred, it did not matter whether the respondents
were parents themselves. Among
those who have clinical experience, there appear
to be more respondents who would report a deficiency than remain silent.
However,
based on the insignificant results for any clinical effect in the other
questions, the small differences for this question in the
number of responses
for those with or without clinical backgrounds are unlikely to be statistically
significant. Accordingly and
in order to save on the costs of calculation, I did
not think it likely that a significant clinical effect would emerge and did not
organise a statistical analysis of this result. My general conclusion remains
that clinical experience is unlikely to be significant
in this sample.
RVS
responses differed slightly from previous questions insofar as
“Terminal” values are concerned. While “Instrumental”
values coincide for both groups to five levels of importance (with
“honesty” at the top of the list and diverging with
the
“Yes-Report” group selecting “broadminded” and the
“No-Be Silent” group selecting “self-control”
at the
sixth level) divergence in the “Terminal” values group occurred much
earlier. The second most important value to those who would report was
“a sense of accomplishment,” but for those who would keep silent,
it
was “happiness.” Respondents early divergence on
“Terminal” values suggest strong views were held by the
respondents,
yet both groups placed “honesty” at the top of their
“Instrumental” list.
The unsurprising but centrally disturbing
implication here is that most respondents see no necessary contradiction between
the primacy
of honesty as a value and a failure to report a suspected offence,
if it concerns “their own.” A correlation matrix was
consistent with
this interpretation, matching “personal obedience to the law” in a
decision to report the deficiency
with “honesty” and
“responsibility.”
The next scenario was inserted to provide some
comparison with the trust account dilemma and is similarly instructive.
Concealment of Criminality
Question 7 – Concealment of Criminality
You are a DPP prosecutor who has concentrated on drug trafficking cases. You have argued to many juries that every case of drug dealing harms society and must be reported and dealt with by the Police. You discover that your daughter has been selling cannabis to other students at her school. Your partner implores you not to report the matter and threatens to end your relationship (already strained by overwork) if you do.
Would you report the matter to the Police? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Personal Integrity
0 1 2 3 4 Spouse Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4
Parental Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4 Personal
Happiness
0 1 2 3 4 Personal Obedience to the
Law
Response to Q7
As in Question 3, a large majority of respondents
(criminal prosecutors) would choose to remain silent rather than report a
daughter
to police for dealing in cannabis. “Parental loyalty”
followed by “spousal loyalty” was rated as most important
for both
males and females in reaching this decision. There does not appear to have been
any statistically observable impact upon
this decision arising from clinical
experience (χ2(1) = 2.443, p = .12) or actual
status as parents; however, the relationship with gender is again important.
UnivariateF tests indicate
that there was a significant difference between
females and males on issues of “personal integrity” and
“personal
obedience to the law.” Females are more likely to place
greater importance on these values than males in relation to a decision
to
report and are, in fact, in the statistically significant sense also more likely
to report than males (χ2(1) = 4.29, p = .04).
Also, within the minority of all respondents who would report their daughter to
police, women were in the majority.
For them the most important motivating value
was “personal integrity” followed by “personal obedience to
the law.”
Of further (and, perhaps, considerable) interest is the response
that females in this group rated “personal obedience to the
law”
more highly than “parental loyalty,” in contrast to males, who did
not clearly distinguish between the two.
RVS responses were identical for the
first three values in the “Instrumental” list, again placing
“honesty”
first but diverging with “helpful” for those
who would report and “logical” for those who would keep silent.
In
the “Terminal” list, the pro-reporting group chose “a sense of
accomplishment” as their second most important
value, while the silent
majority again strove for “happiness.”
The Choice Between “the Firm” and “a Life”
Question 5 – The choice between ‘the Firm’ and ‘a Life’.
You are a junior solicitor working for a large city firm. The long working hours are causing a lot of pressure at home with your partner and children. This issue has been the topic of many recent conversations at home. The firm’s managing practitioner asks you to show commitment on a file. This would involve even longer hours than usual with many late nights for at least the next month. The managing practitioner has intimated that if you perform well in this task it could lead to a promotion. Working longer hours would cause a serious argument at home and be very detrimental to your relationship with your partner and children.
Would you take on the extra hours? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Business Efficacy (Firm’s
Profit)
0 1 2 3 4 Employer Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4
Professional Ambition
0 1 2 3 4 Spouse
Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4 Parental Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4
Personal Happiness
Response to Q5
In support of the possibility that “loyalty to
the family” rates more highly with respondents than notions of personal
honesty and integrity – evidenced in the reluctance of parents to report
their children for crimes – respondents chose
to maintain their home
relationships (494) in preference to furthering their careers (181) by a large
majority. Males and females
were almost equally attached to the value of
“spousal loyalty” in their decision to give priority to home
relationships.
Although males valued “professional ambition” (314)
over “employer loyalty” (231) among the minority who
choose to put
in extra hours at work, the differences were not major.
All respondents who
would work extra hours valued “business efficacy,” “employer
loyalty,” and “professional
ambition” highly at statistically
significant levels for UnivariateF.104 Also
significant, as indicated in the footnoted table below, were “spousal
loyalty,” “parental loyalty,”
and “personal
happiness” for those who gave priority to their home life. Male and female
respondents with children were
overwhelmingly married as opposed to living in de
facto relationships; however, married females who chose to work extra hours had
substantially fewer children than married males who made the same choice. It is
clear that, whether or not respondents had children,
this family priority
remains.
Figure 8: Most Would Not Act Further for Friend in Family Law Dispute when Injustice Suspected to His Former Wife and Children
There was no obvious effect of clinical experience in this area of
decision-making, and gender was not a significant influence
(χ2(1) = 3.90, p = .05).
RVS responses for
“Instrumental” values diverged on the third choice with home-focused
respondents preferring “capable”/“responsible,”
and the
paid workers selecting “logical.” In the “Terminal”
values group, those who would give priority to
home relationships diverged at
the second most important value and selected “happiness,” while paid
workers chose “a
sense of accomplishment.”
In the following
scenarios, the effect of gender on decision-making again appears to assert
itself.
Willingness to Act on a Suspected Lie
Question 6 – Willingness to act on a suspected lie
You are a sole practitioner specialising in family law. A client approaches you to handle his divorce. You and your spouse have been long time friends of this person and you also know his wife and children reasonably well. Whilst drafting the property settlement you suspect your friend has not declared all his assets. The settlement as is will leave his wife and children with little security and they will probably experience some financial hardship. Your old friend says that his list of assets is complete. You are not convinced but you cannot realistically get more information.
Would you continue to represent your friend? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Business Efficacy (Firm’s Profit)
0 1 2 3 4
Professional Integrity
0 1 2 3 4 Client’s Interests
0
1 2 3 4 Personal Integrity
Response to Q6
In this scenario approximately two-thirds of
respondents decided to cease acting for their friend on the basis of a suspicion
(unsubstantiated
in an evidentiary sense) that an injustice was about to occur.
“Professional” and “personal integrity” were
the key
values here and were statistically significant in UnivariateF
analysis.105
“Business efficacy” and
the “client’s interest” were the statistically significant
values for those
who would cease acting. There was no clear clinical experience
effect. Among those who decided to continue to act, there was no particular
influence of gender upon the specified values. However, when examining the
gender difference among those who would cease to act,
that is the majority, most
are female. Between the sexes the values of “personal integrity” and
“professional integrity”
all but cancelled out that of the
“client’s interests.” The gender effect on the majority view
– to cease
acting for a friend – was sufficiently strong to be
significant in Pearson’s Chi Squared Test of Association analysis
(χ2(1) = 7.95, p = .005).
In the RVS
responses, perfect matches were obtained in the most important values only:
“Instrumental” – “honesty”
and
“Terminal” – “self respect.” Second place for
“Instrumental” values, in the case of
those who would cease to act,
went to “responsible,” while those who would continue to act chose
“capable.”
In the “Terminal” category, “self
accomplishment” was the second most important value for those who would
continue to act, and “happiness” was the second priority for those
who decided not to act.
As with other questions, a correlation matrix shows
that associations exist between “professional/personal integrity”
and “capability,” “helpfulness,” “honesty,”
“independence,” “responsibility,”
and “a sense of
achievement” in the approach to the practice of law. In contrast,
“business efficacy”/ “client’s
interest” correlate
with “a comfortable life” and “social recognition” in
the approach to legal practice.
Reporting of Abuse
Question 11 – Reporting of Abuse
You are acting for a mother of 3 small children in a divorce and intervention order matter. Your client has previously shown you photographs of bruises and marks on the children which she claims were inflicted by their stepfather. One of the children now has blurred vision. Your client now instructs you to stop all legal proceedings as she intends to return to the children’s father with her children. You believe the children will be at risk if this happens but you know “mandatory reporting” does not apply to lawyers.
Would you break client confidentiality and inform the Department of Human Services of your fears? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Client Confidentiality
0 1 2 3 4 Professional
Integrity
0 1 2 3 4 Civic Duty(child protection)
Response to Q11
This scenario was designed to pose a particularly difficult choice for respondents. Although a majority was in favour of breaching client confidentiality and reporting the matter, the size of the majority was not overwhelming [see Fig. 9].
Figure 9: Slight Majority in Favour of Reporting Fears of
Child Abuse (Breaching Client’s Confidentiality)
Rather than Keeping
Silent
The gender division was clear and somewhat one-sided. Males
(156) outnumbered females (125) among those staying silent/maintaining
confidentiality, and females (202) were more numerous than males (168) among
those who would report the matter. Among those who would
report, the specified
values were similar for males and females although women rated all nominated
values more highly than males.
Exactly the reverse rating was recorded for those
who preferred to remain silent, with the males valuing
“confidentiality”
ahead of “civic duty” (child
protection). In this area, the differences in motivating values are profound.
Among those
with clinical experience there was a strong preference for remaining
silent. I speculate that those with Monash clinical backgrounds
have seen more
criminal cases than other Monash graduates and are more conscious of duties of
confidentiality and a defendant’s
right to silence.
RVS responses were
consistent with the above choices. “Instrumental” values placed
those reporting as “logical”
and those keeping silent as
“helpful” at the fourth level of magnitude, while
“Terminal” values diverged
at the second level of magnitude. Those
who would report selected “happiness” and those who would keep
silent selected
“a sense of accomplishment.”
Choice between an old friendship and a new, powerful client
Question 2 – Choice between an old friendship and a new, powerful client
You are a senior associate of a small commercial law firm with a niche reputation in the area of privatisation tendering processes. Your firm has been approached by a significant corporation to help them draft their tender submission for the privatised tram network contract. Your firm would almost certainly gain an enormous amount of new work from this corporation if you were to take them on as a new client. At the same time you become aware that a long standing close friend, who has not previously been a client, is about to request and will expect your help with their tender for the same government contract. You owe a great deal to this friend at a personal level. However, in your opinion the potential new corporate client is more likely to be successful in their tender due to size and experience. The work this corporation would generate far outweighs that of your old friend. The choice is yours alone in this case as the firm expects you to take responsibility for developing this area of the practice. Thus in this situation it is of no assistance to decide solely on the basis of first come first served.
Would you act for the corporation and therefore
detrimentally affect the relationship with your
old friend? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4
Business Efficacy (Firm’s Profit)
0 1 2 3 4
Personal Integrity
0 1 2 3 4 Friendship
Loyalty
0 1 2 3 4 Personal Happiness
Responses to Q2
Twice as many respondents indicated that they would prefer to represent the corporation as a client, instead of an old friend as a client, notwithstanding the personal cost, regardless of gender (χ2(1) = 1.16, p = .69) [see Figure 10].
Figure 10: Strong Preference for Corporate Client over Friend – Minimal Effect of Gender
However, the principal (and statistically significant) motivating value in
the decision was not “business efficacy,” which
ran a close second
regardless of age or gender, but “personal integrity.” Among the
minority who preferred to maintain
the old friendship – at the possible
cost of their firm losing a continuing and potentially more lucrative new client
–
both males and females rated “personal happiness,”
“friendship,” “loyalty,” and “personal
integrity” at similar high levels compared to “business
efficacy.”
Clinical experience did not appear to be particularly
important to this decision, although some minor differentiation in decisions
is
observable.
RVS responses placed “logical” as the fourth
magnitude value in the “Instrumental” group among those who would
go
“corporate,” while “broadminded” was chosen by the
friendship minority. “A sense of accomplishment,”
at the second
level of magnitude, was selected by those in the corporate group of
“Terminal” values and “happiness”
was chosen by those
who preferred the friendship over the corporation.
A correlation matrix
shows significant associations between “personal integrity,”
“friendship/loyalty,” and
“personal happiness.” It
seems, therefore, that respondents in both camps were confident that their
decision was based
on “personal integrity.” The divergence in values
became evident at the second order of magnitude, splitting between
“business efficacy” (pro-corporate) and
“friendship/loyalty” (pro- friendship).
Willingness to “defend” rape
Question 4 – Willingness to “defend” rape
You are the Practice Manager of a small but well-known law firm. In this position you commonly have the final say on taking on new clients. Your firm has just successfully defended a string of notorious, high profile rape cases. The media has begun to refer to your firm as one that is well known and has a preference for taking on such cases. Other partners in the firm are starting to suggest this profile is having a detrimental effect on gaining and keeping clientele in the other divisions of the practice. You are approached by an old friend (first met at law school) who is now a well-known politician to represent him against a rape prosecution. This will definitely be a high profile case in the media.
Would you take on your friend as a new client? Y or N
Motivating Value Weight
0 1 2 3 4 Business Efficacy (Firm’s
Profit)
0 1 2 3 4 Access to Justice
0 1 2 3 4
Friendship Loyalty
Response to Q4
A very strong majority would defend this client and
(perhaps unsurprisingly?), gender was a major influence in this decision. Males
were statistically more likely to defend this client
(χ2(1) = 8.30, p = .004). Priority values were as
might be expected, with “access to justice” and “friendship
loyalty”
rating above “business efficacy” in that order among
those who would take on the case. In the minority that would accede
to the
partners’ wishes and decline to act, “business efficacy” came
slightly before the other values.
RVS responses were consistent, placing
“logical” alongside the “yes” case and
“helpful” alongside
the “no” case. In the
“Terminal” category, “happiness” was selected by the
“yes”
group, and “a sense of accomplishment” was
selected by the “no” group.
The correlation matrix associated
“access to justice” with “friendship/ loyalty” and
“business efficacy”
with “ambition” and “a
comfortable life.”
It is perhaps not surprising that clinical
experience has no great impact of itself in this scenario because the intense
notoriety
of the issue of rape and gender may drown out other influences.
SUMMARY AND DISCUSSION OF FINDINGS
In this section I discuss and highlight the important findings of the survey.
Summary of Findings to Question 1: “Corporate or justice priorities”
Women are identified as being more inclined than men
to choose a “justice” focus for their work, although among all
respondents,
those who choose to focus upon career are the majority.
Clinical
experience at the undergraduate level may have some effect upon values, but it
is not clearly related to a justice agenda.
Summary of Findings to Question 8: “Denial of legal aid”
Gender is important in determining the values base of lawyers, and there appears to be limited if any variation due to other factors.
Summary of Findings to Question 3: “Concealment of defalcation”
Taken as a whole, the results of this question
clearly indicate that there are definite limits to respondents’
willingness to
put honesty and obedience to the law first.
Perhaps this
ought to be no surprise that family loyalty is so strong among lawyers. It
may be that the prospect of a child going
to gaol is an (unfairly) extreme
scenario for any parent to contemplate and that the “cutoff” point
on honesty is only
reached at these and similar harrowing edges of human
stress.106 Nevertheless, and notwithstanding the
positive influence of clinical exposure, there is clearly a concern here about
the importance
of “honesty” to lawyers. Since a major objective of
legal education and perhaps the key value underlying legal practice
is
compromised, we must reassess the impact of curricula and teaching methods in
relation to this crucial value.
Summary of Findings to Question 7: “Concealment of criminality”
Most lawyers would keep silent to protect their children, but women are (perhaps surprisingly) more likely than men to disclose an offence by their child. These results do not give cause for confidence that lawyers’ values are particularly “good” – unless it is considered, perhaps on very reasonable grounds, that an emphasis on “family values” (to use the cliché) is no bad thing.
Summary of Findings to Question 5: “The choice between ‘The Firm’ and ‘a life’”
These results confirm the conclusions of the last two questions: that notions of family loyalty among respondents (regardless of marital status, children, or even promotion opportunities) are dominant and will prevail if necessary over personal obedience to the law. It is, as yet, unknown where the limits to this view emerge.
Summary of Findings to Question 6: “Willingness to act on a suspected lie”
In this scenario – as in the next – the instinct to do what may be regarded as “morally right” was for females more powerful than giving a client the benefit of any strictly defined doubt. It is not to be forgotten, however, that one-third of respondents (mostly males) considered that future representation was appropriate regardless of doubt.
Summary of Findings to Question 11: “Reporting of abuse”
A small majority of respondents would report the suspected abuse and of these, the majority were women.
Summary of Findings to Question 2: “Choice between an old friendship and a new, powerful client”
While both pro-corporate and pro-friendship respondents are significantly represented in the resulting distribution, the emphasis upon corporate as opposed to personal provides a major insight into lawyers’ fundamental motivations.
Summary of Findings to Question 4: “Willingness to ‘defend’ rape”
There was a significant variation in the motivation
of males compared with females in responses for and against the decision to act
for a defendant accused of rape. Females in both groups gave greater weight than
males to “access to justice” in their
decision as compared to other
values.
These patterns suggest that, while there is considerable recognition
within the legal profession that criminal defence is an area
of great
importance, females appear to be more sensitive than males to “gender
crimes” and relate more directly to the
issue of sexual violence in terms
of access to justice.
Comparisons with the Findings of the Law Institute of Victoria
The findings for Question 1, focused upon responses as to intended behaviour, are consistent with limited results obtained from actual behavioural investigation conducted by the Law Institute of Victoria.107 As yet there are no other published behavioural studies of Victorian lawyers for comparison. Nevertheless, prediction from this survey of former Monash students to the population of lawyers from Monash and in Victoria as a whole seems reasonable to the extent of the statistical analyses performed on the sample data. A study of actual behaviour among lawyers, in comparison with the values associated with their intended behaviour, is likely to lead to significant further insights.
GENERAL FINDINGS
Beyond Victoria, prediction is difficult and is outside the scope of this enquiry, though some may believe that Victorian lawyers are reasonably representative of the rest of Australia. It is not possible at present even to speculate as to the values of lawyers outside Australia. Nevertheless, with these qualifications in mind, I am able to drawn some conclusions from the cumulative responses to the scenarios described in this survey:
CONCLUSIONS
In this article I have discussed a survey of former Monash University law
students who graduated between the years of 1980 and 1998
and have reported on
the findings. I wanted to find out what personal values were regarded by these
graduates as most important when
faced with difficult choices in their
professional lives. The reason this project is important is because it
challenges implicit
assumptions in the legal profession and among legal
educators that are commonly held about the homogeneity of (so-called
“good”)
values among lawyers. It is possible that the lack of
uniformly “good” values among students and lawyers undermines the
“ethical” practice of law by the profession as a whole, though that
possibility was not directly investigated in this
project.
It is possible
also that these assumptions about homogeneous values have been invalid for some
time: perhaps more so in recent years
with the often commented transition from
law as a “profession” to law as a “business.” Without
evidence,
however, it was unlikely that legal educators and the profession feel
the need to introduce a “values awareness” programme
for students
and new practitioners. At present, the discussion of values and any linkage
to behaviour occurs only occasionally in
legal education and almost never within
the profession, in my experience.
The survey respondents were mainly
practicing lawyers from predominantly middle class environments; however, even
within this group
there are considerable differences in underlying values. Thus,
as there does not appear to be a clear basis for the popular and often
unstated
assumption in legal education that lawyers’ values are both homogeneous
and “moral,” it is most appropriate
to reconsider – and
restructure – much of the law curriculum at fundamental levels. If it is
true that skills training
has become acceptable within undergraduate legal
education, it may be partly109 because the profession
has convinced law schools that law graduates are under-prepared for the work
force. The organised profession
(as an institution) is, however, in my opinion,
unlikely to acknowledge that new lawyers are morally “at sea” and
(perhaps)
in need of guidance. The regulatory implications of such an open
admission would be far-reaching. It is, therefore, unlikely that
the Law Council
of Australia or its constituents will ask law schools to put equal energy into a
values awareness education programme
for their students.
Nevertheless, law
schools need to embrace this issue. We legal educators cannot afford to
concentrate on the rules – or even
upon ethics – without also
recognising what lies behind lawyers’ behavioural decisions. We do need
to, respectfully,
engage students at the level of their values –
preferably in an experiential manner – if we are to encourage their moral
awareness.
There are some lawyers who have clearly passed beyond the need to
satisfy basic and everyday needs; they are in conventional terms
successful, yet
they have not developed significant respect for fairness and justice –
that is, for ethics. Longstaff speculates
that without ethics, lawyers may
become “semi-skilled tradespersons.”110 He
describes lawyers who are prepared to behave unethically for a sufficient fee as
reduce[d] . . . to a cipher “a brilliant and creative cipher
perhaps” but one who has surrendered all claims to exercise
professional
judgment on matters affecting a client’s
interest.111
My findings, preliminary as they are,
suggest that what must be a key objective of Australian legal education –
the graduation
of morally responsible lawyers – is not being achieved. It
is not just the odd one or two lawyers that may fit Longstaff’s
description. Although significant numbers of lawyers choose “just”
courses of action, that is of little comfort when
large numbers – often a
majority – would choose an unjust course of action. A paradigm shift in
legal education is now
I think essential, but that may not result from this
study alone.
To persuade legal educators to assess the need for an
(integrated) values awareness programme within law curricula, we will require
more in-depth investigation on a much larger scale to be convincing. I believe
comparisons within and between major national jurisdictions will
be necessary to create momentum because, as a generalisation, national systems
appear slow to emulate
each other – except in the business arena. There is
a case for a transnational, longitudinal study of lawyers’ values
–
in collaboration with behavioural studies by the organised legal profession
– to derive real knowledge of the values
bases that do support, or
undermine, all notions of ethics in the law.
I sense, but of course cannot
demonstrate convincingly, that there may be only a short time left in which the
legal profession –
as a general collection of people known for their
“good” values – can be safeguarded. If law students do not
explore
their own values, their understanding and acceptance of the rules
of conduct – let alone systems of ethics – are likely to be
superficial. I hope that when (not “if”) law
students are encouraged
to pursue a personal values enquiry, their willingness to identify a justice
priority in their professional
lives will emerge or be strengthened.
* Associate Professor of Law, Faculty of Law, Monash University, Melbourne, Victoria, Australia.
©2001. (2001) 12 Legal Educ Rev 209.
I wish to thank the following people for their assistance with this article: Chris Thwaites, Solicitor, Victoria Legal Aid; Josephine Palermo, Workplace Studies Unit, Victoria University, Melbourne, Australia; Nigel Duncan, Editor of The Law Teacher; and, in particular M Le Brun, Visiting Associate Professor, City University of Hong Kong, for her numerous editorial suggestions and considerable help.
1 K Economides (ed), Ethical Challenges to Legal Education and Conduct (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1998) at xxxiii.
2 http://www.abanet.org./cpr/ethics2k.html.
3 This is not a concern about methodologies to improve attitudes, for example by engaging clinical experiences, but rather it is about the first question: what is the dimension of the need, and how is it to be proved?
4 The Faculty of Law, Monash University is located near Melbourne, Victoria, Australia.
5 The Anglo-Celt heritage of the dominant older white Australian culture has, I think, always contained a strong element of confidence in the practitioners of the legal system and in their shared “good” values. This confidence may be weakening now, but if so, this change is still relatively recent.
6 A values awareness process is not in any sense exotic. It simply arouses students’ awareness of their own, often unconscious, attitudes and values. It is similar in technique to many existing educational methods (particularly in racism awareness programmes) that seek to promote self–reflection.
7 P Tremblay, Coherence and Incoherence in Values-Talk (1998) 5 Clin Law Rev 325-332. See also A Hutchinson, Legal Ethics in a Fragmented Society: Between Professional and Personal (1998) 5 Int’l J of the Leg Profession 175-192, 189. While Hutchinson refers to and rejects the assumption, it is pervasive. Thus, Robert MacCrate, author of the major US statement about fundamental skills and values of lawyers, restated in September 1998 his belief that “lawyers remain ‘united by their pursuit of certain values.’” (1998) 5 Clin Law Rev 333.
8 Such empirical studies as have occurred have focused upon ethical dilemmas – defined as such – rather than personal or professional values investigations. For example, Lamb has produced very interesting commentaries by Queensland lawyers on hypotheticals containing professional dilemmas. See D Lamb, Ethical Dilemmas: What Australian Lawyers Say About Them in S Parker & C Sampford (eds) Legal Ethics and Legal Practice: Contemporary Issues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995) at 217-234. In one comparison, Lamb cites two respondents, one of whom considered personal “morals” irrelevant to a decision and another who took the opposite view. The context of the hypothetical made it clear that the client’s autonomy to decide the issue was unchallenged (at 233). Where there is, however, a clear capacity for lawyers to choose a course of action, it is necessary, even axiomatic, for them to have some understanding of their own attitudes and motivation.
9 J Aiken, Striving to Teach Justice Fairness and Morality (1997) 4 Clin Law Rev 1.
10 Supported by an Australian Research Council Small Grant (1998) of $14,000 to the author to construct, administer, and analyse the results of the survey.
11 M Rokeach, Halgren Tests (1973), 873 Persimmon Ave, Sunnyvale, CA, USA 94087.
12 The text of this section, including footnotes, is based on the article, A Evans, The Values Priority in Quality Legal Education (1998) 32 The Law Teacher 274-286. Permission to reproduce the relevant sections has been granted by Nigel Duncan, General Editor of The Law Teacher.
13 See, for example, Lincoln Caplan in the United States who connects the malaise to a “bottom line accountability” replacing older themes of loyalty, confidentiality, and candour. L Caplan, The Profession – Identity Crisis (1994) 80 ABA J 74. Note that Richard Abel, as usual in an arresting counter, prefers to suggest that the problem is macro- economic, affecting all occupations, and that concerned lawyers are probably unable to influence the problem for the better. Abel also projects that increasing numbers of lawyers will inevitably increase pressure for “bottom line” practices to become the norm. The implication, it seems, is simply arithmetic.
14 S Daicoff, Lawyer, Know Thyself: A Review of Empirical Research on Attorney Attributes Bearing on Professionalism (1997) 46 Am Law Rev 1337.
15 (1998) 5 Int’l J of the Leg Profession 2.
16 This may be summarised for these purposes as a “vacuum of meaning” or an absence of any basic system of commonly accepted, ultimate authority.
17 WW Pue, Lawyering for a Fragmented World: Professionalism After God, 125, at 126 citing M Thatcher, The Downing Street Years (London: Harper/Collins, 1993) at 626.
18 Id, at 126-129. There is of course no shortage of overarching “objectives” in life, for example, the happiness and prosperity of the largest possible number of people (see R Solomon, Ethics and Excellence: Cooperation and Integrity in Business (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993) at 92). At this level of abstraction, however, little is said about the value choices that need to be made in pursuit of this objective. Interestingly, the goal of “happiness” is experiencing a limited renaissance. In the face of nearly two centuries of Western emphasis on material success as the way to happiness, research is now suggesting that the reverse is the case and that happiness is the precursor to success. A Lagan, Success or Happiness? (1995) 32 City Ethics 2 (newsletter of the St James Ethics Centre, Sydney). This may have been understood outside the West for millennia, but it is still not the agreed approach. I speculate that income generation probably remains the primary goal for most.
19 A McGillivray, A Moral Vacuity in Her Which is Difficult if Not Impossible to Explain: Law, Psychiatry, and the Remaking of Karla Homolka (1998) 5 Int’l J of the Leg Profession 255.
20 Id, at 271.
21 Pue supra note 17 at 135.
22 Solomon supra note 18, at 105.
23 Custom in this sense is seen as synonymous with a consistent morality or “goodness” and “right,” as opposed to “evil” and “wrong.” See the definition of “ethics” – “relating to morals.” Concise Oxford Dictionary (London: Oxford University, 1964) at 415. See also Butterworths Concise Australian Legal Dictionary: “A valid custom must be certain, reasonable, and continuous. . . .” (North Ryde: Butterworths, 1997) at 101.
24 It is, of course, useful to keep in mind that here the distinction is between the objective acceptance by society of law as rational and just (and, therefore, effective to the extent of that social acceptance) and the individual lawyer as a sometime capricious contributor to the law rather than its guarantor.
25 See notes 14-16 supra.
26 A particularly unkind example of wincing cross-examination, which involves comment at several levels, is reputedly from the Massachusetts Bar Association Journal (date unknown), reprinted in The Sunday Age, 16th May 1999:
“Q: Doctor, before you performed the autopsy, did you check for a pulse?
A: No
Q: Did you check for blood pressure? A: No
Q: Did you check for breathing? A: No
Q: So, then is it possible that the patient was alive when you began the autopsy? A: No
Q: How can you be so sure? A: Because his brain was sitting on my desk in a jar.
Q: But could the patient have still been alive nevertheless?
A: It is possible that he could have been alive and practising law somewhere.”
27 A, not unkind, comment offered by a friend in relation to this research was that it “should take about five minutes,” as if it is accepted by everyone that lawyers’ values are easily determined and uniformly doubtful.
28 See for example R Uphoff, The Allocation of Decision Making Between Defense Counsel and Criminal Defendant: An Empirical Study of Attorney-Client Decision Making (1998) 47 Univ of Kansas Law Rev 1.
29 Some writers go so far as to say that moral values (discussion of which may be considered to overlap the classical exploration of issues of ethics) are no longer taught in law schools because formal ethics codes have simply (but deliberately) displaced them from the syllabus. See for example G Beggs, Reap What You Sow: Lawyer Ethics Could Benefit from an Application of Proverbs (1996) 82 ABA J 116.
30 WH Simon, The Trouble With Legal Ethics (1991) 41 J of Leg Educ 65, at 67.
31 Hutchinson, supra note 7, at 187.
32 AT Kronman, The Lost Lawyer: Failing Ideals of the Legal Profession (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1993). Kronman’s observations focus on the American profession; however, his viewpoint is also relevant for other common law legal systems.
33 Id.
34 M Kirby, Legal Professional Ethics in Times of Change, 14 ABR LEXIS 13, and D Dawson, The Legal Services Market (1995) 5 JJA 147. These sentiments were echoed by the Chief Justice Gleeson of the High Court of Australia in a recent speech to law students which emphasised that “nobody was entitled to enter a profession simply to make money.” The Age, 8th May 1999, 5. See also A Goldsmith, Heroes or Technicians? The Moral Capacities of Tomorrow’s Lawyers (1996) 14 J Prof L Educ 1.
35 EW Myers, “Simple Truths” About Moral Education (1996) 45 Am Univ L 823. Amongst large firms, even the pro bono schemes of recent years are seen as evidence only that the firms practising such schemes are profitable rather than moral. Lincoln Caplan and Lloyd Carter seem to agree that pro bono activity has not been a big feature of firms that are struggling financially. See Caplan, supra note 13.
36 J Gibeaut, Nourishing the Profession (1997) 83 ABA J 92. Law teachers are encouraged to recover/retain their crucial function as role models to law students and to teach ethics throughout law courses. Caution is, however, necessary, in order to avoid a direct reliance on religion as the basis of these endeavours, lest perceptions of bias occur. See David Barringer, Higher Authorities (1996) 82 ABA J 69.
37 For example, R MacCrate, A Nation Under Lost Lawyers: The Legal Profession at the Close of the Twentieth Century: The Lost Lawyer Regained, The Abiding Values of the Legal Profession (1996) 100 Dickinson Law Rev 587.
38 Id, at 612.
39 American Bar Association, Legal Education and Professional Development: Report of the Task Force on Law Schools and the Profession (Chicago: American Bar Association, 1992).
40 Each of these values in turn begets a “special responsibility.” Thus, the value of competent representation begets the responsibility to clients; striving to promote justice fairness and morality begets public responsibility for the legal system; striving to improve the profession begets responsibility for it; and professional responsibility produces responsibility to one’s self. See MacCrate, supra note 37, at 616.
41 Id, at 613.
42 Id, at 619.
43 American Bar Association Section on Legal Education and Admissions to the Bar, Teaching and Learning Professionalism: Report of the Professionalism Committee (Chicago: American Bar Association, 1996).
44 American Bar Association, Report on a National Lawyer Plan on Lawyer Conduct and Professionalism: Regulatory Authority over the Legal Profession and the Judiciary: The Responsibility of State Supreme Courts (Chicago: American Bar Association, 1999).
45 ABA, supra note 44, at 32.
46 Economides, supra, note 1, at xvii-iii.
47 Economides, supra note 1, at xx.
48 See generally C Gill, Law and Ethics in Classical Thought in Economides, supra note 1, at 3-19.
49 A Eschete, Does A Lawyer’s Character Matter? in J Callahan, Ethical Issues in Professional Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988) at 394.
50 Hutchinson supra note 7, at 186.
51 Eschete supra note 49, at 396.
52 See generally, T Morawetz, Teaching Professionalism: The Issues and the Antimonies in Economides, supra note 1, at 215-233.
53 See for example, K Towers, Youngsters are Disenchanted (2000) 27 Australian Fed Rev 58. Towers notes that Sir James Gobbo, former Victorian Supreme Court Judge and then Governor of that State, and a range of other commentators have considerable misgivings about some of the attitudes that young lawyers have to legal practice.
54 In my opinion, in the lawyer disciplinary process there is perhaps the best opportunity, excluding law school and continuing professional development, to address moral stagnation in lawyers’ lives. Thus, when misconduct is “proven,” the potential emerges to tackle the rehabilitative process radically from the baseline standpoints of regret, forgiveness, and moral insight so that potential personal growth also assists subsequent professional behaviour. A glance at the public reports of legal regulators shows that most disciplinary situations do not result in the lawyer’s departure from the profession, though enforced “time out” is common. When the lawyers return to practice, much can be achieved if this process has been tackled.
55 Lord Chancellor’s Advisory Committee on Legal Education and Conduct (“ACLEC”), First Report on Legal Education & Training (London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1996) at 24-25.
56 A Halpin & P Palmer, Acquiring Values (1996) 146 New Law J 1357. Parts of the text of this section (“Defining Values”) are taken with permission from an article by the author in The Law Teacher, see note 12 supra.
57 ACLEC, supra note 55, at 1358. The urgency does not seem, however, to be a priority of the government of the United Kingdom. Behind the ACLEC call is the implicit recognition that, notwithstanding that law schools are being told to “do more with less” in a quantitative sense, they are also being asked to “do better with less” – that is, to lift quality with, in relative terms, less money. Harris and Jones in their 1996 survey of UK law schools report that over the three years from 1993 to 1996, there was a 50% increase in the number of students but only a 3% improvement in the numbers of law teachers. See P Harris & M Jones, A Survey of Law Schools in the United Kingdom (1997) 31 The Law Teacher 38, at 99. The gap between the community expectation that lawyers will act with integrity (and a heightened social awareness) on the one hand, and, on the other, the growing restrictions on their education suggest that a coherent approach to ethics in legal education is necessary.
58 Halpin & Palmer, supra, note 56.
59 MacCrate, supra note 37.
60 Halpin & Palmer, supra note 56.
61 ACLEC, supra note 55.
62 L Sheinman, Looking for Legal Ethics (1997) 4 Int’l J of the Leg Prof 139-154, at 140
63 Id, at 141.
64 Id.
65 Id, at 142.
66 Id.
67 “We cannot discern the ethics of the profession by looking at [the] rules of conduct.” Id, at 144.
68 S Bottomley & S Parker, Law in Context (Sydney: Federation Press, 1997).
69 A recent exception was the 1998 American Association of Law Schools clinical conference in Portland, Oregon, USA, which focused on the teaching of values in law schools.
70 See for example Government of Saskatchewan, Understanding the Common Essential Learnings: A Handbook for Teachers: Personal and Social Values and Skills, (Saskatchewan Education, 1987) chapter 6, www.sasked.gov.sk.ca/docs/policy/cels/el5.html, and R Jowell (ed), British Social Attitudes: The 14th Report (Aldershot, England: Ashgate, 1997).
71 Values can, of course, be either “bad” or “good” and exist in a hierarchy, ranging from basic “survival” to “aspirational.” See A Lagan, Managing through Values (1995) 20 City Ethics 1 (newsletter of the St James Ethics Centre, Sydney).
72 See note 23 supra.
73 See for example, N Moore, The Usefulness of Ethical Codes (1989) Annual Survey of Am Law 7.
74 Schneyer reminds us that the reference to “values” includes the inevitable “no values” scenario or at least the possibility that “values” can only ever mean the lowest common denominator variety, representative of the whole of society (however expressed). See T Schneyer, Moral Philosophy’s Standard Misconception of Legal Ethics (1984) Wis Law Rev 1529.
75 See submission by the (US) Clinical Legal Education Association to the Standards Review Committee of the ABA Section on Legal Education and Admission to the Bar (1998) 7 CLEA Newsletter 10/11, 40.
76 MacCrate’s 2nd “professional value,” supra note 37.
77 There are situations where honesty and moral integrity may require different actions, for example, when offering (secret) sanctuary to a political refugee from an oppressive regime.
78 In sharp contradiction is the weighty philosophical tradition that separates professional and personal roles and allows what is otherwise discordant to be reconciled at, it is argued, both the ethical and psychological level. See RA Wasserstrom, Roles and Morality in D Luban (ed) The Good Lawyer: Lawyers’ Roles and Lawyers Ethics (Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984) at 25. The problem with this reconciliation is that it tends to elevate what is really only a justification for a choice to act “professionally” (in this instance an action that would be personally offensive) to the level of an obligation to so act. It is the supposed obligation that is, in my observation, indigestible to law students immersed in a good clinical programme.
79 Hutchinson, supra note 7, at 187.
80 One of Halpin and Palmer’s values identified with the law, supra note 56.
81 A Lagan, Managing through Values (1995) 20 City Ethics 1 (newsletter of the St James Ethics Centre, Sydney).
82 Id.
83 See for example, S Rosner, Service to Clients Comes First; Lawyers Need to Make the Right Ethical Choices to Produce the Best Results (1997) 83 ABA J 108. While Rosner does not argue for the view that aspirational decision-making will make more money for the lawyer, he does make the more limited observation that if lawyers place the pursuit of money before service to clients, the results will be “bad.” The reverse approach – where clients’ interests come before lawyers’ fees – means that “everything else falls into place.” It is also true that some types of legal practice passively marginalise ethical behaviour, for example, routine conveyancing performed for high volume mortgage originators. I suggest, however, that the lawyer who aspires over the long term to ethical practice will reap the benefits in terms of reputation and, ultimately, remuneration.
84 Hutchinson, supra note 7, at 189.
85 The tentative view of the Australian Law Reform Commission (“ALRC”) is that, at present, it is the workplace, rather than law schools, that determines lawyers’ behaviour. See ALRC Issues Paper 21, Review of the Adversarial System of Litigation: Rethinking Legal Education and Training (Sydney: Australian Law Reform Commission, August 1997) para 8.22, 77. This view is supported by those who think that the commercial pressures of legal practice determine whether legal education in ethics is successful. See Myers, supra note 35, at 823. If such views could be tested – and found accurate – there would be considerably more incentive for law schools to treat their clinical programmes as “first work places” and tackle ethics education explicitly in that medium. The “good lawyer” (from Economides supra, note 1, xxvii-xxix and Part 3, 237-358) might then begin to replace Kronman’s “lost lawyer,” supra note 32.
86 AH Evans, Client Group Activism and Student Moral Development in Clinical Legal Education (1999) 10 Leg Educ Rev 179-190. See also AH Evans, Developing Socially Responsible Lawyers (1990) 15 Leg Service Bulletin 218-9.
87 Springvale Monash Legal Service (“SMLS”) in particular, where a large part of the Monash Clinical Programme is based, has published the Lawyers Practice Manual (Vic) (Sydney: Law Book Company, 1985) for some time and has included a substantial ethics section. Law students at SMLS have also worked over the years on systemic reforms to legal professional regulation in response to client caseload.
88 A focus group works by encouraging discussion amongst a small group of people who are regarded as representative of a particular population in terms of gender, ethnicity, social background, and age. Focus groups are especially useful in conjunction with questionnaire survey techniques, which (although statistically reliable) do not allow for the more subtle exploration of responses to standardised questions. Focus groups also permit a cross check of the trends (rather than the detail) in information provided by a questionnaire.
89 Alumni lists depend upon graduate information as to changes in addresses. Over time address lists can become outdated. Names must then be matched to electoral rolls and individually confirmed by telephone.
90 Josephine Palermo, Workplace Studies Unit, Victoria University, Melbourne, Victoria, Australia.
91 Rokeach supra, note 11.
92 The consultant survey commentator, Josephine Palermo, recommended the Rokeach Values Survey as a check for validity and internal consistency in responses.
93 The text of the instructions to respondents
answering Part B was as follows, “The following questionnaire contains a
broad index
value survey which will be used for comparative purposes to Part A.
Please indicate the importance to you of each of the following concepts
and values in relation to your approach to the practice of law by
circling your choice using a pen. The indicators on this scale are as follows:
0 = irrelevant, 1 = unimportant, 2 = important, 3 = very important,
4 =
extremely important.
The available RVS categories were as follows:
Ambitious 0 1 2 3 4
Broadminded 0 1 2 3 4 Capable 0 1 2 3 4 Cheerful 0 1 2 3 4 Courageous 0 1 2 3 4 Forgiving 0 1 2 3 4 Helpful 0 1 2 3 4 Honest 0 1 2 3 4 Imaginative 0 1 2 3 4 Independent 0 1 2 3 4 Intellectual 0 1 2 3 4 Logical 0 1 2 3 4 Obedient 0 1 2 3 4 Polite 0 1 2 3 4 Responsible 0 1 2 3 4 |
Self controlled0 1 2 3 4
A comfortable life 0 1 2 3 4
An exciting life 0 1 2 3 4
A sense of accomplishment 0 1 2 3 4
Equality 0 1 2 3 4
Family security 0 1 2 3 4
Freedom 0 1 2 3 4
Happiness 0 1 2 3 4
Inner harmony 0 1 2 3 4
Pleasure 0 1 2 3 4
Self respect 0 1 2 3 4
Social recognition 0 1 2 3 4
True friendship 0 1 2 3 4
Wisdom 0 1 2 3 4
|
94 See Law Institute of Victoria (“LIV”), Annual Survey of Legal Practitioners [1999] LawIJV 101; (1999) 73 (3) LIJ 52, at 52.
95 It is considered that subsequent larger scale investigations will require cross-matching of all alumni records (that is, including those for whom no current address is available) against law society records and, if there are still insufficient numbers in consequence, electoral rolls also.
96 LIV, supra note 94.
97 “INSTRUCTIONS
The format of this questionnaire requires respondents to
answer Yes or No to a single question concerning a dilemma posed in a preceding
scenario. The respondents are also asked to indicate on a scale of 0 to 4 the
relative weight given to the corresponding motivating
value in reaching their
decision. The indicators on this scale are as follows:
0 = irrelevant, 1 = unimportant, 2 = important, 3 =
very important, 4 = extremely important.
Please indicate all answers by circling your choice using a pen. The language used in the following scenarios should not be read in a technical legal sense, rather it should be interpreted in an everyday, common usage manner. Some scenarios are ambiguous in order to realistically reflect the uncertainties arising from imperfect knowledge. All the scenarios are fictitious although obviously based on general experience.”
98 In the United States at least one writer seems disconcertingly comfortable with the assumption of homogeneity for all the lawyers in that country. See Tremblay, supra note 7.
99 That observation could, however, legitimise a level of professionalism that does not aspire to a “best practice” philosophy and would justify the maintenance of an educational and regulatory status quo.
100 LIV supra note 94, at 54-55.
101 Id, at 52-57.
102 Id, at 55. The caution arose from the abovementioned 30% non- response rate to the pro bono question.
103 See generally, S Coakes & L Steed, SPSS: Analysis Without Anguish (Milton, Queensland: Wiley & Sons, 1999).
104 The following is the Table of Mean Responses for the UnivariateF analysis of those who would and would not choose to work extra hours at the expense of their home life.
|
NO
|
YES
|
||
|
Mean
|
Standard Deviation
|
Mean
|
Standard Deviation
|
Business Efficacy
|
1.47
|
.94
|
2.02
|
1.10
|
Employer Loyalty
|
1.90
|
.88
|
2.49
|
1.03
|
Professional Ambition
|
2.10
|
.85
|
3.18
|
.79
|
Spouse Loyalty
|
3.67
|
.55
|
2.73
|
.84
|
Parental Loyalty
|
3.71
|
.57
|
2.74
|
.89
|
Personal Happiness
|
3.63
|
1.41
|
2.48
|
1.10
|
105 UnivariateF mean responses to importance of motivating values in respect of the decision whether to act for a friend were:
|
NO
|
YES
|
||
|
Mean
|
Standard Deviation
|
Mean
|
Standard Deviation
|
Business Efficacy
|
1.47
|
.94
|
2.02
|
1.10
|
Employer Loyalty
|
1.90
|
.88
|
2.49
|
1.03
|
Professional Ambition
|
2.10
|
.85
|
3.18
|
.79
|
Spouse Loyalty
|
3.67
|
.55
|
2.73
|
.84
|
Parental Loyalty
|
3.71
|
.57
|
2.74
|
.89
|
Personal Happiness
|
3.63
|
1.41
|
2.48
|
1.10
|
106 Future variations to this question will substitute “nephew/niece” or even “child of best friend” in order to approach the actual limit or edge of honesty more closely.
107 LIV supra note 94.
108 “Corporate aspiration” is here used to refer to some lawyers’ desires to achieve high incomes in large firms from representing “big business”/ commercial clientele.
109 Legal educators have been concerned for some time to use skills as a vehicle (for example, at Griffith University, Newcastle University , and the University of Wollongong) to enhance undergraduate learning first and foremost.
110 S Longstaff, Ethics Drive Needed to Restore Profession’s Legitimacy (1994) 32 Law Society J 29-30.
111 Id, at 30.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/2001/11.html