You are here:
AustLII >>
Databases >>
eLaw Journal: Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law >>
2001 >>
[2001] MurdochUeJlLaw 27
Database Search
| Name Search
| Recent Articles
| Noteup
| LawCite
| Help
Sengchanh, Virakone --- "Refugees - Two Lifetimes in One" [2001] MurdochUeJlLaw 27; (2001) 8(4) Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law
It
has been over twenty years since my grandfather escaped with his wife,
their children and their children's children across the
Mekong River.
In fear of his life and the livelihood of his family, my grandfather
left everything he had owned and built. No laughter,
no noise from
pattering footsteps across the rice fields, sliding silently onto
canoes, pushing across the rushing Kong, awakening
in a graveyard,
endless walk for help, imprisonment, then refugee camp - we escaped in
secret, under the cloak of night and found
refuge in Thailand. The
doors of Australia were eventually opened to us and here we have made
our home.
I asked my grandfather about the experience.
He smiled. I have gathered bits and pieces from whispered conversations
of aunts who
remember but do not retell the story. They smile. Even the
most vivid present day reminder of our escape - my one legged second
cousin
- can smile at his good fortune.
Their faces are
not etched with the lines of a haunted history. They are the struggle
lines engraved upon the faces of those refugees
who are given a chance
to rebuild their lives again in another country - those that live two
lifetimes in one.
With faith in every forward footstep
many refugee families have similar experiences to my own. Having made
their way or presently
passing their way from one life to another,
common to the refugee tale is the agony of being uprooted from home and
the hope through
survival.
Listen to the voices of these refugees. They are the voices of ordinary men and women under extraordinary circumstances.
Refugees
in this 'born again' experience are a peculiarity. For if we could
capture their stories, we could in a moment in time, look
reverently
backwards and faithfully forward. If these stories could be captured I
am sure it would inspire and rekindle the spirit
deep within us all - a
spirit that prays for courage, hope and acceptance. It is this
'refugee' spirit that we need - it challenges
us to be and do better.
Unfortunately,
we can only feel a glimpse of this 'refugee spirit' in the Australian
treatment of those people seeking refugee status
and consequent
permanent residency. Part I of this paper highlights the unsatisfactory
nature of the Australian position regarding
incorporation of
international treaties concerning refugees. In particular my focus is
on the policy that Australia is now denying
citizenship to those who
arrive without a valid visa or passport after the 20th of October 1999.
An asylum seeker in this respect
is not eligible for permanent
residence and can only be granted a three-year Temporary Protection
Visa (TPV - Visa Subclass 785).
I argue that this new policy measure is
contrary to the spirit of our international obligations. I seek to show
how the practices
of the new policy disempower and patronize refugees.
It offers them artificial choices and perpetuates the loss of control
and social
dislocation. Part II looks at the
implications of citizenship and non-citizen rights from two angles.
Firstly as a basis for democratic theory
and judicial review and
secondly as a footing for exclusion of non-citizens, of which refugees
are a significant sub-set. The location
and construction of the refugee
is a product of particular visions of the democracy, state and
citizenship. My argument is that there
is a need to incorporate a view
of citizenship, which is concerned with the rights of individuals
within the community, no matter
what their formal citizenship status.
Only then may we see different and effective answers evolve in refugee
law. Australia
acceded to the two principal conventions, which govern international
refugee law matters: the 1951 Convention relating to
the status of
Refugees (the Convention) and its 1967 Protocol[1].
The Convention sets out the rights of refugees and the standards for
their treatment in the countries that receive them. In particular,
Article 33 of the Convention provides for the principle of
non-refoulement - No " state shall expel or return
('refouler') a refugee in any manner whatsoever to the frontiers of
territories where his life or
freedom would be threatened on account of
his race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social
group or political opinion."
It is important to note
that there is a legal distinction between refoulement and asylum. The
Convention primarily offers protection
from refoulement and an interim
regime of protection pending a durable solution. While signatory
countries are required not to directly
or indirectly return a refugee
to their country of origin or other places of persecution, they are not
required to provide permanent
residence to meet that obligation.
While
there is general agreement at the international level that temporary
protection has a valid place in the refugee protection
framework[2]
Australia has been overly restrictive in its interpretation and
application of this key element of the Convention. By denying permanent
residency to a class of refugees - those who arrive in Australia
without a valid visa or passport after the 20th of October 1999
-
Australia is fulfilling the 'letter of the law' - that a State is not
required to provide permanent residence to meet the Convention
obligation. But such practice is violating the spirit of the entire
Refugee Convention because the practice will have a profound
and
lasting negative impact on the present and future lives of the refugees
concerned. What are these negative impacts? Temporary
protection has been used to meet emergency refugee influxes in many
countries. Through its use, governments can initially
avoid having to
undertake individual screening, which is both time-consuming and
costly. Thus most temporary protection schemes offer
refuge to everyone
fleeing an area of generalized conflict or human rights abuse. While
this approach works as a coping mechanism
for mass influxes from civil
wars, in the Australian case it is being applied to people who have
been and can be individually determined.
Moreover, it presumes that the
conflict will be short-lived and that asylum-seekers may be returned
directly the conflict is over.
If the conflict is not short-lived, the
question of refugee status pursuant to the Convention and durable
solutions cannot be avoided
forever. We have to eventually find a
solution. The assumption that people can return as soon as formal
hostilities are concluded
is also incorrect. Given that reconstruction
is required and that, in the case of the dismemberment of a State into
new polities
with new nationality rules, many asylum-seekers cannot
return to the place from whence they came[3] Article
31 of the Convention provides that the State shall not impose
penalties, on account of their 'illegal entry, on refugees coming
directly from a territory where their life or freedom was threatened'
but eligibility for a 785 Temporary Protection Visa, as opposed
to the
more generous 866 Permanent Residence Protection visa, is determined
solely on method of arrival. The new measures consequently
create two
tiers of refugee status. On the one hand there are the
people who were legally in Australia at the time they made their
application. They are granted permanent
residence, which provides
certainty about the future and access to the full range of benefits
afforded to other permanent residents.
On the other
hand there are those people who, for one reason or another, are not
able to use regular migration channels. They also
have a claim for
refugee status no less credible than those of the first group but can
only be granted only temporary residence.
These people subject to
temporary protection become "B" status or "humanitarian" refugees
because they are simply not granted all
the needed social rights. The
three-year Temporary Protection Visa has certain entitlements, which
does give its recipients access
to welfare, education and work[4]
but these are barely minimal and is arguably contrary to Australia's
obligations under the Refugee Convention which seeks to protect
such
vulnerable groups. The following will explain how this is so. In
1998 the Refugee Resettlement Advisory Council (RRAC) found that former
detainees have settlement needs additional to those of
refugees who had
not been detained. It was recommended that former detainees be
considered an especially vulnerable group whose needs
should be
addressed by service providers. This recommendation was adopted by DIMA
in the early drafts of the Integrated Humanitarian
Settlement Strategy.
With the introduction of the temporary protection visas, all of this
has gone out the window. Not only are released
detainees no longer
considered a special target group, they are no longer eligible for even
the base level of services other refugees
are entitled to. The
new visas make it impossible for refugees to access a wide range of
services, which are essential to recovery. Refugees under
this
protection will experience problems with securing accommodation because
of their temporary status (discrimination by real estate
agents and
ineligibility for public housing) and because they are not eligible for
bond assistance. The Refugee Council has already
received reports that
Afghans granted the new temporary visas are sleeping in tents in the
streets of Perth because they are unable
to obtain or afford proper
accommodation[5]
Further, their ineligibility for Adult Migrant English Program courses
will mean that those with limited English are likely to remain
without
functional communication skills, plus they will not be eligible for the
Job Network services so will have a much harder time
finding employment[6] Once
a person has been granted a temporary protection visa (TPV) it is a
requirement that he/she apply for a permanent protection
visa (subclass
866) in order to be eligible for Medicare. As no assistance is being
provided at this time for TPV holders to lodge
this application, the
significance of doing so might be lost, or an incomplete application
submitted which is summarily rejected,
and the refugee might find
him/herself without access to medical services. If this were to be the
case, it would arguably be a breach
of Article 23 of the Convention,
which requires that a refugee have access to the same level of public
relief as nationals.[7] One
of the few settlement services that TPV holders will be eligible for is
the Early Intervention Case Management. This program is
intended to
assess entrants' needs and then refer them to appropriate programs.
Workers are already expressing frustration and confusion
because once
they have identified the TPV entrants' needs, there is nowhere to refer
them to. This has significant implications for
the staff as well as the
entrants. The limitation on eligibility for DIMA funded settlement
services, and the pressure being put
on ethno-specific groups not to
assist subclass 785 visa holders, will result in the new entrants
finding it very difficult to get
assistance from regular sources. They
will thus have to turn to other service providers, in particular the
mainstream charities,
and compete directly with the needy in the
Australian community for the limited resources. This will generate
negative community
attitudes towards refugees[8] because they will be stigmatized as a burden to society. At
the October 1999 meeting of the Executive Committee of the United
Nations High Commissioner for Refugees, Australia was one of
the
countries that passed, by consensus, a Conclusion on the Protection of
the Refugee's Family. Here it was re-emphasised that the
family is the
natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to
protection by the society and the state. Moreover
there is the
underlying need for the refugee family to be protected by measures
which ensure respect for the principle of family
unity, including those
to reunify family members separated as a result of refugee flight. Possibly
the most profound limitation on those with temporary visas is that
which precludes family reunion. Under the new provisions,
a man coming
to Australia to seek protection and granted a temporary visa is likely
to be separated from his wife and children for
a period more than five
years. This is a violation of the refugee's right to be reunited with
his family. The separation is likely
to cause significant psychological
distress to the refugee and the family. It will extend the period
during which his family is in
danger. Women and dependent children
without male support are especially vulnerable in refugee camps and
also in certain countries
of origin (especially if it is known that a
member of the family has sought asylum). The
above analysis has sought to show how the practices of the new
Australian policy - the Temporary Protection Visa - can have a
negative
impact upon recipients. It can disempower and patronize refugees. It
offers them artificial choices and perpetuates the
loss of control and
social dislocation. Such practice clearly shows how the tendency of
states to interpret their own duties in light
of sovereign
self-interest contributes ' to a negative situation capable of
breaching the fundamental principle of non-refoulement.'[9] The
need for an immediate response demands that the regulatory framework
that controls the 'distribution of membership' and distribution
of
'goods and services' be reconstituted with the inclusions of elements
capable of according justice to refugees. From the standpoint
of
refugees a solution would entail the notion that - subordinate and
disadvantage groups in society have a perspective of their
own life
experience that cannot be accommodated in a regulatory framework that
relies on the application of objective criteria. Such
a framework
overtly ignores the existence of this subjectivity. This suggests that
the key element that needs to be included in the
regulatory framework
is a capacity to accommodate the subjective life experiences of
refugees.[10] As Article 33 'brings the Convention close to recognizing the subjective right of the asylum'[11]
we need to ratify and institute it with a more liberal and wider
perspective. From the standpoint of the refugee this firstly means
that
refugees should have access to a full range of needed goods and
services and opportunities. It must needs be that as 'non-citizens'
they need wider and more profound rights. Secondly, it means the
incorporation of policies that pursues and finds lasting solutions.
A
refugee has found a lasting solution when he or she is no longer in
need of international protection and when he or she has assumed
all of
the rights and responsibilities of other citizens living in the same
state. Thus refugees need a real opportunity to become
a citizen. When
governments practice policy that effectively limit membership in a
community they are in effect unjustly distributing
the primary social
good - membership in a community. 'The primary good that we distribute to one another is membership in some human community.'[12] The
extent to which the nature of legal authority is determined by the
ideological interests of dominant groups, is made apparent
by the fact
that this tendency is most pervasive in contexts where those denied the
possibility of 'individualised justice' are members
of the most
disadvantaged and subordinate groups in society. As 'non-members' of
society, they are relegated to being passive recipients
of an unjust
distribution of the 'primary social good'- membership.[13] It is important to critically review the assumptions that lead to such result.
We
understand citizenship to be relevant to our understanding of
democracy. Yet, while the democratic values associated with citizenship
are important elements for a democracy, there is also another
consequence flowing from citizenship - what do we do about
non-citizens?
How do we treat people who do not have the legal status
of citizen in our community? Moreover, how do we treat people who are
not
even resident in our community - non-citizens who seek to become
members of the community? This section of the paper
looks at citizenship from both angles - as a basis for democratic
theory and judicial review and, as a footing
for exclusion of
non-citizens, of which refugees are a significant sub-set. My argument
is that we should adopt a more liberal approach
towards the rights of a
non-citizen, one that ties non-citizen rights to humanity not to legal
status. Only then will we find a more
just, equitable and lasting
solution to the refugee problem. In
a democracy with citizen members, it is those members of the community
who decide how the community will be governed, and who will
govern.
Popular sovereignty, and the rule by the citizens, is a vital part of
the legitimacy of judicial review in liberal democracies.
Judicial
review is a mechanism for ensuring that the government and the
individuals are equal in their treatment before the law.
Just as the
individual is subject to the law, so too is the state. The rule of law
is pivotal to this understanding of democracy.
Ronald Dworkin[14]
an American philosopher, challenges our understanding of the rule of
law. He claims that there are in fact "two very different conceptions
of the rule of law, each of which has its partisans". He identifies the
first as the "rule book" conception and the second as the
"rights"
conception. The rule book conception involves the
theory that the power of the state should never be exercised against
individual citizens except
in accordance with rules explicitly set out
in a public rule book, available to all. The rights
conception assumes that citizens have moral rights and duties with
respect to one another and political rights against
the state as a
whole. These rights are to be recognised in positive law so that the
citizen through the courts may enforce them.
The rule of law then in
this sense is the ideal of rule by an accurate public conception of
individual rights. In this sense, citizenship
is linked to humanity,
not to the formal legal status. Dworkin continues to
distinguish the two concepts, but the most important distinction for
this discussion is the different result
they suggest on the question of
whether judges should make political decisions in cases where the
rule-book does not give an answer.
The rule book conception, is part of
the legalistic, formalist framework in Australian jurisprudence which
says that judges should
decide hard cases by trying to discover what is
really in the rule book. Judges should not decide cases on their own
political beliefs,
but rather by considering what "should" be in the
rule book. The rights conception in contrast insists that the rule-book
is relevant
because people have a prima facie moral right for courts to
enforce the rules that the representative legislature has enacted, but
it denies that the rule book is the exclusive source of moral rights in
court. Dworkin claims that "[a] judge who follows the rights
conception
of the rule of law will try, in a hard case, to frame some principle
that strikes him as capturing, at the appropriate
level of abstraction,
the moral rights of the parties that are pertinent to the issues raised
by the case"[15] This
distinction is important when looking at how views of citizenship
influence the legitimacy and scope of judicial review of executive
action. One view is that the citizens have elected the people to act as
the State - so the policy judgements of those in power are
to be kept
in check by the democratic system. That is, if the citizens do not like
the government of the day's policies they can
decide not to re-elect
them at the following election. We are constantly reminded that the
judges are not there to adjudicate on
policy matters. Rather, they are
exercising a vital democratic function - of keeping a check on the
lawful exercise of governmental
power. This is a rule book conception
of citizenship. In essence this becomes a citizenship of exclusion,
because only those who
have membership voting rights can exercise this
citizenship. Non-citizens have no rights. A rights
based view of citizenship, says that the Courts do have a
responsibility over the content of the rules - that a democracy
that
values citizenship should look to the nature of those rules to see if
they offend human rights that are essential to a just
and democratic
society. These different views display different
theoretical understandings of judicial review. Refugee law is an acute
example of citizenship
representing exclusion from political influence.
The High Court has had various contexts within which to consider the
significance
of citizenship and the rights of non-citizens in
Australian refugee law. Predominantly, the status is raised in refugee
cases, but
it is also of importance in cases, which look at rights and
responsibilities, which discriminate upon the grounds of citizenship.
I
will highlight a few cases to bring attention some of the High Court's
view on citizenship. In the decisions of Chief Justice Mason in Cunliffe[16] and Gaudron J in Teoh[17] - we do find judicial support for a more liberal and open view of non-citizen rights. Chief
Justice Mason, in Cunliffe, was the only judge to embrace the idea that
non-citizens in Australia were entitled to the protection
afforded by the Constitution
and the laws of Australia. He said that non-citizens within Australia
were entitled to invoke the implied freedom of communication,
particularly - "when they are exercising that
freedom for purpose, or in the course of establishing their status as
entrants and refugees or asserting
a claim against government or
seeking the protection of the government."[18]
Justice
Gaudron in Teoh, relied on common law rights of citizenship, in
deciding whether an executive decision-maker in a migration
matter,
should have taken into account the interests of the children of a man
who was about to be deported. Gaudron J relied on the
children's
Australian citizenship. She argued - '
[C]itizenship carries with it a common law right on the part of
children and their parents to have a child's best interests taken
into
account, at least as a primary consideration, in all discretionary
decisions by governments and government agencies which directly
affect
that children's welfare, particularly decisions which affect children
as dramatically and as fundamentally as those involved
in this case'[19]
Her
Honour referred to the obligations that a State has to its citizens in
a "civilised democratic society". In this context, she
is emphasising
citizenship as an essential element to democracy. By bringing
citizenship into a matter of family relationship, she
is implying that
democracy must value families. This reflects a view of citizenship,
which is broader than the formal legal status.
It is citizenship as a
commitment to human rights. The consequences of
embracing such a vision are profound. It will allow access for refugees
to a broader and extensive range of rights
and services. It will allow
the incorporation of the subjective viewpoint of a refugee, in a
regulatory framework that eventually
determines their right to life, to
identity and to community. It will allow our vision to expand and
include. Unfortunately our history has been strewn
with instances where we have reaffirmed our right to exclude - our
entire immigration system
is based upon it - and citizenship is
essential to that exclusion. The Lim[20]
case emphasises that Refugee law, in particular, is an area of policy
that is essential to the identity and content of the community.
It
decides which person will be members of the community - it decides
which people become citizens, who in turn will influence the
outcome of
further policy. In the Lim case we find that the High Court's
understanding of the status of non-citizenship is a legitimate
basis
for exclusion and not contrary to the Parliament's power as prescribed
by the Constitution. The case concerned the Federal government's power to legislate in migration matters. Changes had been made to the Migration Act 1958
which in effect "designated" certain persons to be kept in custody, and
only to be released from that custody if they were to be
removed from
Australia. These designated persons were 'non-citizens'[21]
and were in this instance people seeking refugee status in Australia.
The issue turned on whether the legislation was constitutionally
valid
and whether a non-citizen would be able to challenge the decision of
the Commonwealth Officer in the same manner as an Australian
citizen,
pursuant the Constitution. The Court initially found
that if the non-citizens were detained without such a statutory
authority, the non-citizen would be able
to challenge the decision of
the Commonwealth Officer in the same manner as an Australian citizen,
pursuant the Constitution. So the case turned on the constitutional
validity of the legislation. Was it valid? The Court
first resorted to international law in its decision. In the early 20th
century the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council
said similar things
to the case of Musgrove v Toy[22]
- "One of the rights possessed by the supreme power in every State is
the right to refuse to permit an alien to enter that State".
The Court
recognised that this principle had been the basis for many earlier High
Court decisions. Consequently the Court recognised
the Parliament can
enact a statutory provision to empower detention of non-citizens. It
was the executive power of the State that
gave rise to its power to
detain in the exercise of that executive power. Therefore, this
legislation which discriminated upon the
grounds of citizenship was
valid. Interestingly enough part of the legislation
section was held to be invalid. This was the breach of separation of
powers in the section,
which dictated that the Courts could not review
an executive decision. Paradoxically citizenship essentially appears in
this context
also in that the Court reaffirmed that decision-makers can
not be above the law - even in exercising their executive power of
detention.
And in order to ensure that they are acting according to
law, it means that the Court must review their decisions. But the
practical
reality of citizenship as exclusion was of significant
consequence to the applicants in this case - the citizenship of
judicial review
did not protect them from exclusion. Citizenship
is not always discussed in terms of refugee and exclusion. The question
of citizenship is fundamental in looking at the
relationship between
the individual and the State. The development of implied rights in the Australian Constitution
also raises the question of whose rights? Do non-citizens have the
protection of implied constitutional rights? This question was
raised
in obiter discussion in the Cunliffe[23] case. This was a migration law case but of a different nature[24] The Migration Act 1958
was amended to include a section imposing restrictions on the giving of
'immigration assistance'. Only registered agents can legally
provide
immigration assistance, with harsh penalties applying for breach of
that section. Cunliffe, a solicitor, challenged the Act.
The
relevant challenge involved the question of free speech. The plaintiff
argued, amongst other things, that the law was invalid
because it
contravened the implied constitutional guarantee of freedom of
communication. The plaintiff argued that this implied freedom
was not
limited to communications for the purposes of the political processes
in a representative democracy, but applied generally
to all people of
the Commonwealth in their communications with the Commonwealth
Government. It was held that the legislation was wholly valid with respect to aliens within section 51(xix) of the Commonwealth Constitution.
The registration imposed by the Act upon the giving of immigration
assistance to aliens or the making of immigration representations
on
their behalf did not interfere with any freedom of communication
implied by the Constitution. In the discussion about
implied rights, some of the judges addressed the question of whether an
implied freedom, such as the one claimed,
could be claimed by
non-citizens. Brennan and Deane JJ[25]
sought to distinguish a non-citizen's right to the protection of the
law, from the right to invoke the Constitutional protection
of free
speech. This distinction means that there are different legal
consequences flowing from citizenship. Justice Brennan
grounded this distinction in the notion of representative democracy.
Aliens "have no constitutional right to participate
in or to be
consulted on matters of government in this country" and the
"Constitution contains no implications that the freedom is available to
aliens who are applying for or who have applied for visas. Nor is there
any basis for implying that aliens have a constitutional right."
Moreover he stated - "[I]f the Constitution
implied a right of access to government or to the repositories of
statutory power...it would be a citizen's right."
The
crucial point here is that the centrality of citizenship is the right
to participate in, or to be consulted in government. If
you do not have
the right to vote, then you do not have the right to rely on the
Constitutional protection of free speech in trying
to invalidate a law.
Justice Deane accepted that non-citizens could rely on
the ordinary law, and included in this some of the Constitution's
guarantees,
directives and prohibitions but declared that a non-citizen
- "stands outside the people of the Commonwealth
whose freedom of political communication and discussion is a necessary
incident of
the Constitution's doctrine of representative democracy.
That being so the incident does not operate to directly confer rights
or
immunities upon an alien. Any benefit to an alien must be indirect
in the sense that it flows from the freedom or immunity of those
who
are citizens."
Justice Deane noted that
the effect of his distinction might be of no practical consequence,
however, the significance is extreme
in determining the rights that
flow from citizenship. Therefore, exclusion becomes more pronounced,
for it is not only a question
of a right of entry, but also of access
to rights within the country. This view of citizenship being integrally
related to the democratic
system of voting is significant in the
assessment of judicial review. The Cunliffe case is
important in that it frames the meaning of citizenship. Citizenship is
about democratic participation in government
and society. Citizens are
those who have the right to vote. Citizens have the right to
participate in, and influence our democratic
system. Citizenship in
this sense is in contrast to subjectivity. Citizens are meant to be
equal in their relationship with the State.
Subjects are indeed that -
subject to the power of the State. In Nicholson J's judgement in the Full Federal Court decision of Wu Yu Fang v The Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs[26]
the question of rights of persons who had arrived unlawfully in
Australia, were reviewed. Were they entitled to be told that they
had
certain rights? Should procedural fairness apply to them? RD Nicholson
J stated: "This is a case in which the Parliament
has negated the possibility of common law concepts of procedural
fairness applying in favour
of the non-citizen applicants. While [this]
executive conduct does not accord with internationally expressed goals
relating to conduct
in relation to refugees, the conditions for
application of international law, as prescribed by Australian domestic
law, are not present
to enable international law to control that
conduct. Furthermore, such conduct was supported by the enactments of
the Australian
Parliament, which, to that extent, evinces an intention
in relation to non-citizens to negate the application of those
internationally
commended basic procedural requirements. The result is
that the non-citizen applicants are unassisted by either Australian
domestic
law or by international law."
Citizenship
is definitely at play here, in both contexts. Parliament, expressing
the will of its citizens, has chosen to restrict
the rights of
non-citizens. Parliament will be accountable to the people at the next
election; but of course they are accountable
only to the citizens. And
here, the Court states that it is bound by Parliament's express intent,
illustrating a rule book view of
judicial review, whereby it looks at
the rules, and while recognising those rules are not conducive with
principles protecting the
rights of refugees, they are acceptable. In
this sense we see citizenship as exclusion. Non-citizens are excluded
from the democratic
process, and have no means of influencing
Australia's conduct toward them. The Court's reliance on a formalist
view of judicial review,
in accepting Parliament's power to offend
rights also conforms to a narrow view of citizenship. The case of Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Wu Shan Liang[27]
is a further illustration and reinforcement of citizenship as democracy
with a rule book conception of judicial review. The High
Court
criticised the over-zealous review by the Federal Court, and identified
a change in law, through the use of different wording
in the
legislation, to explain this result. The section 'The proper role of a
reviewing court' in the joint judgement of Brennan
CJ, Toohey, McHugh
and Gummow JJ reaffirms democracy essentially as majority rule,
resulting in the Courts not being entitled to
interfere with
administrative injustice. The High Court in Liang is affirming a
narrow, rule-based view of democracy. Despite the
attempts by the lower
Courts to introduce a rights based review of the legislation, and the
action of the executive, the Court stated
quite definitively, that it
is bound by Parliament's clear intention[28] Am
I expecting judges to decide or influence refugee policy? Am I
suggesting that the courts be in the position of overriding, if
only
temporarily, important decisions or policies of representatives of
elected governments? Would not that be undemocratic? Surely
citizenship
is meant to be about exclusion - and why be concerned about the
differential treatment that citizenship propounds? All I am suggesting is a reevaluation of our assumptions, by society, the courts, DIMA, the Migration Act,
RRT and so forth. What is required is for a more liberal interpretation
of established principles. Indeed, a view that citizenship
leads to a
one-dimensional view of our parliamentary democracy should be resisted.
The very fact that we are discussing the "return"
of the Court to
deferential approaches to judicial review, is reflective of the fact
that there are broader notions of democracy
and legitimate exercise of
power. As discussed above, there are differing theoretical perspectives
on the role of judicial review,
one of which is a human rights based
view of citizenship. Citizenship is essential to our
understanding of refugee law and to judicial review. However, the
Courts have been incorporating in
their reasoning a view of citizenship
as exclusion. This is not new in Australia. But we are presently in the
threshold of a new
century, where international principles should be
having a greater impact on domestic legislation, and where human rights
should
not only be exclusive to formal citizens within nation-state. If
we incorporated a view of citizenship, which was concerned with the
rights of individuals within the community, no matter what
their formal
citizenship status, then we may see different answers evolve when the
Courts review government legislation on refugee
law. We
are living in a time when the thrust of political and economic thinking
and practice is bereft of commitment to social justice.
My call in this
essay has been to question and challenge the underlying assumptions,
concepts, practices and voices that continually
oppress and separate
marginilised groups in our society. We must seriously assess the path
we are treading, we must ask basic questions
about the sort of society
in which we wish to live, and to the extent to which our social and
legal institutions deliver that society.
We need to
listen and hear the voices of the oppressed. For an exact explanation
for the refugee situation and of refugee law, which
does not take into
account the witness and voices of victims, is nothing more than an
eviscerated abstraction. Failure to consider
seriously the subjective
element in the construction of explanations of oppression makes it
difficult to give credence to the primacy
of any ideology and
theoretical explanation and suggests that the experience of oppression
cannot be encompassed in a theory of theories
which do not give the
oppressed a voice. We need to lift our sights to embrace a vision that
will give everyone an opportunity to
be part of our community. My
grandfather passed away late last year. Before his death I had the
honour and privilege to pronounce a religious blessing upon
him. My
heart swelled with gratitude and love for a man that was able to carry
his family on his back. I am thankful for the legacy
he has left me. I
am thankful for him bringing me to Australia. I am thankful for
Australia accepting me and giving me citizenship.
May we continually
have the courage to open our minds and hearts to those in need. Ronald Dworkin (1985), A Matter of Principle, 11
Pierre-Michel
Fontaine, The Relevance of the 1951 Geneva Convention Relating to the
Status of Refugees (1994), Australian International
Law Journal,
pp69-79
Goodwin-Gill G.S, The Refugee in International Law
(Oxford Clarendon Press, 1983 at 55), as Extracted in Hyndman Patricia,
"Australian
Immigration Law and Procedures Pertaining to the Admission
of Refugees", McGill Law Journal, Volume 33 1988, p716, at 720
Ami Madhuri Kalmath, "Refugee Law in Australia" (1993), Law 511 Research Assignment, Macquarie University
Stewart
Motha, "Discretionary Decision Making and Refugees: A Sociological
exploration of transformations in the nature of Legal Authority"(1993),
Law 511 Research Assignment, Macquarie University
Refugee Council of Australia position paper - see http://www.refugeecouncil.org.au/position01032000.htm
Kim
Rubenstein , `Citizenship as Democratic Participation and Exclusion:
The High Court`s approach to judicial review and refugees.`
Paper
presented at Retreating from the Refugee Convention, Darwin, February
1997
Justice Ronald Sackville, 'The Limits of Judicial Review
of Executive Action -some comparisons between Australia and the United
States.'
Savitri Taylor, "Informational Deficiencies Affecting
Refugee Status Determinations: Sources and Solutions", 1994, University
of Tasmania
Law Review, Volume 13, No 1, pp43-101
Savitri
Taylor, "Marginalising the International Law Claims of On-Shore Asylum
seekers in Pursuit of Immigration Control and Foreign
Policy
Objectives", [1994], Sydney Law Review, Volume 16, pp32-71
Chu Kheng Lim v Minister for Immigration (1992) 176 CLR 1
Cunliffe and Another v. The Commonwealth of Australia [1994] HCA 44; (1994) 182 CLR 272
Wu Yu Fang v The Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1996) 135 ALR 583.
Minister of State for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Ah Hin Teoh(1995) [1995] HCA 20; 128 ALR 353
Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Wu Shan Liang (1996) 136 ALR 481
Musgrove v Chen Teong Toy [1891] AC 272 at 283.
[1]
Savitri Taylor, "Marginalising the International Law Claims of On-Shore
Asylum seekers in Pursuit of Immigration Control and Foreign
Policy
Objectives", [1994], Sydney Law Review, Volume 16, pp32-71. The
Protocol was drafted to remove the geographic and time limitations
of
the earlier instrument, the incorporation of which reflected the
post-World War II context in which the Convention was framed.
Otherwise, it retains the same language as that used in the Convention.
[2]
There is a well established mechanism, incorporated in the 1951 UN
Refugee Convention, which can be applied to facilitate the repatriation
of people who were recognized as refugees but who no longer need
international protection. Commonly known as the 'cessation clause',
this mechanism is based on the principle that people should enjoy
refugee status only for as long as it is absolutely necessary,
and that
such status can be withdrawn when fundamental and durable changes have
taken place in their country of origin. During the
past 20 years, UNHCR
and states have applied this principle to refugees from 15 different
countries where peace has been restored
and where democratic systems of
government have been established.
[3] Refugee Council of Australia position paper - see http://www.refugeecouncil.org.au/position01032000.htm
[4]
The TPV gives access only to Special Benefits through Centrelink for
which a range of eligibility criteria apply; no family reunion
rights
(including reunion with spouse and children); limited access to DIMA
funded settlement services; access to school education
subject to state
policy (full fees imposed for tertiary education); permission to work,
but ability to find employment influenced
by temporary nature of visa;
and no automatic right of return if the visa holder leaves the country.
[5] Refugee Council of Australia position paper - see http://www.refugeecouncil.org.au/position01032000.htm
[6] ibid
[7] ibid
[8] ibid
[9]
Goodwin-Gill G.S, The Refugee in International Law (Oxford Clarendon
Press, 1983 at 55), as Extracted in Hyndman Patricia, "Australian
Immigration Law and Procedures Pertaining to the Admission of
Refugees", McGill Law Journal, Volume 33 1988, p716, at 720
[10]
Stewart Motha, "Discretionary Decision Making and Refugees: A
Sociological exploration of transformations in the nature of legal
authority", 1993 - Law 511 Research Project, Macquarie University
[11] Pierre-Michel Fontaine, the Relevance of the 1951 Geneva Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees.
[12] Micheal Walzer, Spheres of Justice. 1983, p49
[13] op.cit, Stewart Motha
[14] Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle, 11 (1985).
[15] Ibid p33
[16] Cunliffe and Another v. The Commonwealth of Australia [1994] HCA 44; (1994) 182 CLR 272
[17] Minister of State for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Ah Hin Teoh(1995) [1995] HCA 20; 128 ALR 353
[18] Cunliffe and Another v. The Commonwealth of Australia(1994) [1994] HCA 44; 182 CLR 272
[19] Minister of State for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Ah Hin Teoh(1995) [1995] HCA 20; 128 ALR 353
[20] Chu Kheng Lim v Minister for Immigration (1992) 176 CLR 1
[21]
According to the Court they were non-citizens because ' citizens can
not be imprisoned for an administrative reason, in times of
peace, but
non-citizens can.'
[22] Musgrove v Chen Teong Toy [1891] AC 272 at 283.
[23] Cunliffe and Another v. The Commonwealth of Australia [1994] HCA 44; (1994) 182 CLR 272:
[24] Cunliffe and Another v. The Commonwealth of Australia [1994] HCA 44; (1994) 182 CLR 272.
Issue was whether implied freedom was not limited to communications for
the purposes of the political processes. The plaintiffs sued
the
Commonwealth in the High Court for a declaration that Pt 2A of the Migration Act 1958
(Cth) was invalid. Part 2A established a registration system for
persons who gave immigration assistance or who made immigration
representations. A person who
was not so registered was prohibited from
giving immigration assistance unless he or she came within certain
exceptions.
[25] Held per Brennan, Dawson, Toohey and McHugh JJ: that Pt 2A was wholly valid as a law with respect to aliens within s51(xix) of the Commonwealth Constitution.
The registration imposed by 2A upon the giving of immigration
assistance to aliens or the making of immigration representations
on
their behalf did not interfere with any freedom of communication
implied by the Constitution; per Brennan J on the ground that they did
not infringe the freedom of political discussion that is necessary to
maintain the system
of representative democracy; per Dawson J on the
ground that they were not incompatible with the requirements of the
system of representative
government with the Constitution
ordains; per Toohey J on the ground that they did not constitute an
undue restriction on the implied freedom of political communication;
and per McHugh J on the ground that the Constitution contained no guarantee of freedom of expression to which they were obnoxious.
[26] (1996) 135 ALR 583
[27] Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Wu Shan Liang (1996) 136 ALR 481
[28]
And the use of changed words was a means of showing a change in rules.
Interestingly, Justice Gaudron was not a member of the Court
for this
case. Her discussion in Teoh may suggest that she would not have been
supportive of such a rule-book approach to judicial
review.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/MdUeJlLaw/2001/27.html