![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
eLaw Journal: Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law |
Author: | Kam C Wong BA, JD, MA, PhD Associate Professor, University of Wisconsin (Oshkosh) Department of Public Affairs |
Issue: | Volume 11, Number 3 (September 2004) |
A primary problem of comparative jurisprudence is, therefore, to seek out jural postulates of different legal systems and to determine how they find expression in juridicial institutions of the societies under consideration. Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man (1968)[1]
|
Confucian Ethics |
Legal Rule |
Scope |
Comprehensive |
Limited |
Subject |
Person |
Actions |
Purpose |
Perfection |
Correction |
Nature |
Open-ended/Ever-evolving |
Close-ended/Fixed |
Focus |
Internal process |
External behaviour |
Standard |
Maximum effort/Constant effort |
Minimum |
Regulatory agent |
Self |
Others |
Assessment |
Holistic |
Decree act |
Sanction |
Psychological |
Physical |
|
Legal-control |
Self-control |
Jurisdiction |
Limited |
Unlimited |
Enforcement target |
Selective |
Non-discriminate |
Enforcement mode |
External |
Internal |
Enforcement focus |
Form |
Substance |
Enforcement reach |
Conduct |
Thought (motive, intent, state of mind) |
Sanction |
Physical or material |
Psychological |
Error |
Some |
None |
Effectiveness |
Sometimes |
All the time |
[1] E.Adamson Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man (N.Y.: Atheneum, 1968), p. 15.
[2] “For Confucius the term li, which basically means “rites,” embraces all the traditional forms which provided an objective standard of conduct. Thus, while li may in given instances refer to “rites,” “ceremonial,” or “rules of conduct,” it has the general meaning of “good form” or “decorum.” See Wm. Theodore De Bary, Wing- tsit Chan, and Burton Watson, Sources of Chinese Tradition Vol. I (N.Y.: Columbia University, 1960), p. 28. (Sources of Chinese Tradition)
[3] “Ren” is commonly translated as “benevolence, kindheartedness, humnaity.” The Pinyin Chinese-English Dictionary (Hong Kong: The Commercial Press, 1979), p. 573R. (PYCED) “Ren” is what a person should seek in life. It is perfect virtue. Analect XV: 8.
[4] See “’Fa’ zai Han Fei sixiang zhong de yiyi” (The meaning of ‘Law’ in Han Fei’s thinking.) In Wang Yaopo, Yufa xixiang lunji (Compendium on Confucians and Legalists thought) (Taipei: Shibao chubanshe, 1983), pp. 168-186.
[5] For a historical account of the debate between “fajia” and “rujia” resulting in their ultimate union beginning with the Han dynasty (206 BC – 220 AD), see Qu Tongzhu, Zhongguo falu yu zhongguo shehui (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1981), pp. 328-346. (Zhongguo falu yu zhongguo shehui)
[6] See “Sun Kuan de falu sxiang” (The legal thought of Sun Kuan) in Liu Hai-nian and Yang Yi-fang, Zhongguo gudai falu-shi zhishi (Knowledge in Chinese legal history) (Helungjian remin chubanshe, 1984), p. 69-75. (Zhongguo gudai falu-shi zhishi)
[7] For literature on Confucianization of the law, see “Zhonghua faxi tedian tanyuan” (The research into the origin of the characteristics of the Chinese legal system,) in Zhang Jinfan, Zhongguo falu shi lun (Discourse on Chinese legal history) (Beijing: Falu chubanshe, 1983), pp.11-25; “Zhonghua faxi de xingcheng ji qi tedian” (The formation and characteristics of Chinese legal system) in Zhongguo gudai falu-shi zhishi, Op. Cit., note 6, supra, pp. 6-24, 12-13; Chen Gu-yuan, Zhongguo fazhi shi (Chinese Legal System History) (Beijing: Zhongguo shuju, 1988), pp. 53-61; Qian Daqun & Xia Jinwen, Tang lu yu Zhongguo xianxing xingfa bijiao lun (A Comparative Study of Tang Lu and the Current Criminal Law in China (Nanjing: Jiangsu renmin chubanshe, 1990), pp. 31-42.
[8] Ch’u provided the first “systematic” study in English language from classical materials on the Confucianization of the law. Ch’u Tung-tsu, Law and Society in Traditional China, (Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes-Sorbonne, Sixieme Section: Sciences Economiques et Sociales, Le Monde d’outre-Mer, Passe et Present, Premiere Serie, Etudes IV), Mouton, Paris and The Hague, 1961). (Law and Society in Traditional China)
[9] The original research also covers “Judicial Procedure Rules” as applied to cultured vs. non-cultured.
[10] For example, see Derk Bodde, "Age, Youth, and Infirmity in the Law of Ch'in China" 121 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 437-470 (1973) (Derk Bode). See also Wang Yaopo, Yufa xixiang lunji (Compendium on Confucians thought) (Taipei: Shibao chubanshe, 1983), pp.150-152 and Qu Tongzhu Zhongguo falu yu zhongguo shehui (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1981, pp. 197-220. (Zhongguo falu yu zhongguo shehui)
[11] See Tom Fisher, “Loyalist Alternatives in the Early Ch'ing,” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies, Vol. 44, No. 1. (Jun., 1984), pp. 83-122; Jennifer W. Jay, “Memoirs and Official Accounts: The Historiography of the Song Loyalists,” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies, Vol. 50, No. 2. (Dec., 1990), pp. 589-612.
[12] Ku Chieh-Kang; L. Carrington Goodrich, “A Study of Literary Persecution During The Ming,” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies, Vol. 3, No. 3/4. (Dec., 1938), pp. 254-311.
[13] Lawrence D. Kessler, “Chinese Scholars and The Early Manchu State.” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies, Vol. 31. (1971), pp. 179-200.
[14] Jonathan D. Spence, Treason by the Book (Viking Penguin, 2002).
[15] Unless otherwise specified I will be using less cultured, non-cultured, and no cultured interchangeably.
[16] An expansive normative system is one that covers many aspects of a person’s conduct. It describes the scope of applicable norm. A restrictive normative system is one that set forth a limited range of acceptable conducts. It describes the limitations and specificity of the applicable norm. A demanding normative system is one which has a low tolerance for lack of performance. It describes the standard and expectation of the applicable norm.
[17] In 1772, in the 37th year of Qianlong’s rein, the emperor ordered the collection of all Chinese books and literature in the country to be included in Ssu-k’u Ch’uan Shu (The four set of complete books) - a national depository of literary books. The effort to collect books also invited censorship by collecting officials. Censorship leading to prosecution for speech crime became official policy on August 31, 1774 when the Emperor issued an edict to that effect. For historical context, see Luther C. Goodrich, The Literary Inquisition of Chin-lung (N.Y.: Paragon Book Reprint Corp., 1966). (The Literary Inquisition of Chin-lung ) For cases of literary inquisitions by other Qing Emperors see Wan Wenwu, Qingshi Wenxianzhi (Taiwan Commercial Press, 1969).
[18] The quotations came from The Four Books:The Great Learning, The Doctrine of the Mean, Analects, The Works of Confucius. See The Four Books (James Legge, trans.) (Taiwan: Culture Book, 1981). (Hereinafter The Four Books.)
[19] Censorship has a long history in China. As early as the ninth century the great scholar Han Yu has called for the elimination of Buddhism and Taoism to promote the development of Confucianism. The Literary Inquisition of Ch’ien-lung. Op. Cit., note 12, supra.
[20] Ch’ing Tai Wen Tzu Yue Tang (Ch’ing dynasty literary inquisition files) (Shanghai Book Store, 1986), 2 volumes.
[21] San Zao Shi An (Jiangsu guangling guji keyin she, 1993). 3 Volumes. The series contained other cases not pertinent to this research. The series also contained 4 more cases than the Ch’ing dynasty literary inquisition files.
[22] According to one source there were about 10 cases of speech crime in each of the Kangxi (1662 - 1722) and Yongzheng period (1722- 1735). There were however over 130 cases during the Qianlong period (1736-1795). Zhou Zongqi, The uncovering of wrongful Qing literary crimes (Zhongguo youyi chubanshe, 1992), p. 11. According to another source, there were only 84 cases of literary inquisition cases with names during the whole of Qing empire, being 2 cases in the Shunzhi period, 2 cases in the Kangxi (1662 - 1722) period, 4 cases in the Yongzheng period (1722-- 1735) and 74 in Qianlong period. See Zhongguo gudai falu-shi zhishi Op. Cit., note 6, supra,, p. 398 citing Liu Zhi-cheng, Zhongguo er-qian nian (China 2000 years). There is no easy way to reconcile the two since the method of classification is not made available.
[23] Paul S. Ropp, “Vehicle of Dissent in Late Imperial Chinese Culture”in La societe civile face a l’Etat (Ecole Francaise D’extreme-Orient, 1994), pp. 117-157.
[24] A speech could be found objectionable for a number of reason leading to speech crime prosecutions: (1) Was it anti-dynastic or rebellious? Many books, poems and plays written between 1590 and 1660 were overtly ani-Manchu. (2) Did it insult previous dynasties which were ancestral to the Ch’ing? (3) Did it concern the northern and northwestern frontiers and military or naval defense? Geographic works were scrutinized for sensitive military information. (4) Did it contain heterodox opinion on the Confucian canon? (5) Did it give a biased, or, in Manchu eyes, unfavorable account of any incident or series of events in the Chinese-Manchu period of conflicts of the seventeenth century? (6) Was the style unliterary? (7) Did it concern such political parties as the Tung-lin and Fu-she that flourished at the end of Ming? See The Literary Inquisition of Ch’ien-lung, Op. Cit., note 12, supra, pp. 42-52. For an investigation into what kinds of books were considered “offensive”, see also Wu Zhefu, Qingdai jinhui shemu yanjiu (A research into prohibited and burned books in the Qing dynasty (Guoli zhengzhi daishe zhongguo wenxue yanjiuzhuo 1969) ref Z 1019 W9.
[25] For an overview of the ideological basis of class structure see T’ung-Tsu Chu, “Chinese Class Structure and Its Ideology,” in John K. Fairbank (ed.), Chinese Thought and Institutions (The University of Chicago Press, 1957), pp. 235-250. For a more detailed discussion, see Ping-Ti Ho, The Ladder of Success in Imperial China (N.Y.: John Wiley & Sons, 1964).
[26] See Derk Bodde, op. cit., note 9, supra., p. 437.
[27] See Law and Society in Traditional China, p. 230, n. 11. (Li is the institutionalization of proper behavior to all things in life as reflecting the principles governing the larger cosmic order.)
[28] See Zhongguo falu yu zhongguo shehui, op. cit, supra, note 9.
[29] See Legge, Texts of Confucianism, III, 90.
[30] See generally note 9, supra. See also Chung-li Chang, The Chinese Gentry (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1955).
[31] Article 4 to the Great Qing Code provided: “In all cases where members of the pa-i commit offenses, (prepare a memorial setting out the circumstances) send it sealed to the Emperor and await a rescript. It is not permitted to decide to bring (the alleged offender) in for interrogation without authority....When the consideration is concluded (then the basis for the offense that was considered) are to be set forth in a report (to the Emperor). The final decision in the case will be received from the Emperor.” See also Article 8: “In all cases where high or low officials commit offenses ... the superior officials having jurisdiction will send a memorial under seal with a statement of facts, requesting rescript.”
[32] Article 7 to the Great Qing Code provided for a redemption schedule for public offenses committed by officials. Article 8 to the Great Qing Code provided a redemption table for private offenses committed by officials. For example, Article 8 provided:
Punishment |
Redemption |
10 strokes |
2 months salary |
20 strokes |
3 months salary |
..... |
..... |
90 strokes heavy |
Reduction of four ranks |
100 strokes heavy |
Dismissal |
[33] These were titles given to students passing various stages of the imperial examination, which ultimately qualify them of appointment to office. Chin-shih were metropolitan graduates. Chu-jen were provincial graduates. Kung-sheng were senior licentiates. Chien-shien were students of Imperial Academy. Sheng yuan were qualified students. See Ping-ti Ho, The Ladder of Success in Imperial China (Columbia University Press, 1962).
[34] The elaborate legal process in favor of the officials, gentry, and scholars has grave sociological implications. As demonstrated by accounts of retired officials, officials were reluctant to take action against officials, gentry, and scholars for fear of courting the displeasure of the Emperor. Huang, Liu-hung. (1984) A Complete Book Concerning Happiness and Benevolence (ed. and trans. Djang Chu.) University of Arizona Press.(Unprincipled members of the gentry often abused their special privileges. The magistrate must deal with them with tact and be prepared to compromise.) p. 186.
[35] Ching Lu li, 27, 31a-32a.
[36] Sources of Chinese Tradition, op. cit., note 2, supra, p. 114.
[37] Id., p. 115.
[38] The Master here refers to Confucius.
[39] The Analects, Book XV, Chapter 7.
[40] The Analects, Book IV, Chapter 5:3.
[41] 3.285.1 to 3.312.11
[42] 3.285.12 to 3.286.1
[43] Unless otherwise stated all the italic or italic or underlined sentences in the quoted text are supplied by the author in order to show the relevant points under discussion.
[44] In historical time, Socrates, Jesus, and later Saint Joan of Arch was variously persecuted for speaking their mind and were all considered as heretics afflicted with devilish character. See Alan A. Stone and Sue Smart Stone, The Abnormal Personality Through Literature (Prentice Hall, 1966), p. 1. See also “The myth of Mental Illness,” in Studies in Abnormal Behavior (Chicago: Rand McNally Co., 1971), pp. 28-29.
[45] 3.121 to 3.222
[46] PYCED 434R.
[47] 3.143.3-7
[48] The Analects, Book IV, Chapter 16.
[49] 3.142.9-10.
[50] 3.142.1
[51] PYCED 524L.
[52] “Yun Jia Quan nianpu wangxing jizai yu” (Decree on Yun Jia Quan making inappropriate entry in the geneology) (3.166.10 to 3.168.2).
[53] The Analects, Book IV, Chapter 5
[54] 1.245.1 to 1.302.13
[55] In traditional China, the imagery of animalism was used to describe offenders who were deemed totally lacking in human qualities. It is common even today to hear people refer to those who has blatantly disregard social, moral, and legal norms as “not even to be compared with animal.” More specifically, in the Chinese language, petty criminals are described as “filch like rats and snatch like dogs” (“shueqie-goutou”) PYCED p. 637L. The Chinese are not alone in describing criminals as animal. Ceasare Lombroso, Crime, Its Causes and Remedies (Montclair, N.J.: Patterson Smith, 1968). (Criminals suffered from atavistic anomalies, i.e., they were throwbacks to a more primitive time when people were savages.)
[56] 1.262.12-14. Still later, his house was described as “shu xue” or rats den (HYDCD 12:1467L) See “Hu Bao Quan dao ren hou zai yan cha Hu Zhong Zao jian shu zhe.” (Memorial of Hu Zhong Zao on repeated search of Hu Zhong Zao’s home on assume of office). 1.262.9 to 1.265.6.
[57] 3.229.1 to 3.232.4
[58] 3.234.12-14
[59] In this regard, Aristotle and Confucian shared similar ideas. Aristotle observed that justice as virute was “that kind of state of character which makes people disposed to do what is just and makes them acts justly and wish for what is just.” Nichomachean Ethics. Vol V, I, 1129a. Cited in Edwin W. Patterson, Jurisprudence (N.Y.: Brooklyn, Foundation Press, 1953), p. 31.
[60] In traditional China and still is true today, moral accounting is considered as dualistic in nature. Moral accounting is divided into two separate but integral parts – moral agency and moral responsibility. While moral agency rests with the individual (e.g., “xiu shen” or “self-cultivate”) but moral responsibility is shared by the collective the individual belonged, i.e., family, clan, community, state. This way of structuring moral accountability is directly opposite to the western liberal political-economical-ethical ideal of atomistic individualism.
[61] Xie Ji-shi zhu-shu an (The case of Xie Ji-shi compiling books) 1.197.1 to 1.196.9
[62] Cheng-Zhu’s work referred to the “li-xing” school of thought (or the school of nature and reason) during the Song dynasty (420 to 497). The “li-xing” school was one of the three grand Chinese intellectual school of thoughts. See Zhongguo xueshi sixiang shi, Vol. 4 (A History of Chinese intellectual thoughts) (H.K.: Bo Web Chubanshe, 1979), pp. 346-364.
[63] Ding Wen-bin nici an (The case of Ding Wen-bin rebellious writings), 1.207.1 to 1. 236. 14
[64]
1.221.5.
[65]
1.221.7.
[66]
1.221.6.
[67]
1.221.6
[68]
See 1.221.5.
[69] Much like the outlaws in England past or witches within the puritan rank in New England. See K. Erison, Wayward Puritan (N.Y.: John Wiley & Sons, 1977).
[70] This was usually achieved by execution or banishment to the border.
[71] This calls to mind Becker’s insightful observation that deviance is less the nature of an act as much as it is the reaction of the people to an act. Howard Becker, Outsider (N.Y.: Free Press: 1963)
[72] 1.210.13 (DWB should be interrogated by torture so that he does not put up an excuse.) 1.215.1 (DWB claimed that he suffered torture because of god. Even if more torture were to be applied, he would not change his testimony.)
[73] 1.221.4. See also Case 12, Lin Zhi Gong niezao Zhu Ge biwen an (The case of Lin Zhi Gong fabricating Zhu Ge inscription on a tablet case ) 1.327.2 to 1.330.10.
[74]
The Analects, Book XIV, Chapter 23.
[75] In modern time and in the West, this is akin to holding people in “public trust” to higher conduct standard, e.g., judges, police officers, priests.
[76]
3.121 to 3.222
[77]
3.142.1.
[78]
3.142.13 to 14.
[79] A fiduciary is “a person having duty, created by his undertaking, to act primarily for another’s benefit in matters connected with such undertaking ... refer to a person having duties involving good faith, trust, special confidence, and candor towards another.” See Black’s Law Dictionary (abridged sixth edition) (St. Paul, Minn: West Publishing, 1991), p. 431.
[80]
3.121 to 3.222.10
[81]
3.141.2-4
[82] The Analects, Book VII, Chapter 28:2.
[83] “The gentleman seeks to enable people to succeed in what is good but does not help them in what is evil. The inferior man does the contrary.” The Analects, Book XII, Chapter 11.
[84]
2.1.1 to 2.34.3
[85]
2.14.4 to 6.
[86] In western law and jurisprudence, the relationship between knowledge and criminal responsibility is an inseparable one. The “first principle” (Herbert Packer, The Limits of Criminal Sanctions, 1968) of criminal responsibility (culpability) is knowledge. Thus, the principle of legality – “Nullum crimen sine lege; nulla pena sine lege” (“no crime without (pre-existing) law, no punishment without pre-existent law”) holds that a person cannot be held liable unless he is put on notice about an offense. See discussion in Joshua Dressler, Criminal Law (West, 1994), p. 64ff. See also ALI Model Penal Code, SECTION 2.02 GENERAL REQUIREMENTS OF CULPABILITY, (2)(b) Knowingly. A person involves knowingly with respect to a material element of an offense when: (1) if the element involves the nature of his conduct or the attendant circumstances, he is aware that his conduct is of that nature or that circumstances exist; and (ii) if the element involves a result of the conduct, he is aware that it is practically certain that his conduct will cause such a result. Finally, the M’Naghten rule excused a mentally insane person from criminal responsibility if “at the time of the committing of the act, the party accused was labouring under such a defect of reason, from disease of the mind, as not to know the nature and quality of the act he was doing, or, if he did know it, that he did not know he was doing what was wrong.” Daniel M’Naghten’s Case, House of Lord[1843] EngR 875; , 1843, 10 Cl. & F. 200, 8 Eng. Rep. 718.
[87]
The Analects, Book XIV, Chapter 9
[88] In American tort law, an expert is held to a higher standard of care commensurate with his expertise and knowledge in the field. Morris, “Custom and Negligence” 42 Columbia Law Review 1147, 1164-5 (1942).
[89]
2.371.1. to 2.384.9
[90]
2.382.7-8
[91]
2.374.6-7.
[92]
2.373.1
[93] “The leaving virtue without proper cultivation ... not being able to move towards righteousness of which a knowledge is gained ...these are things which occasion me solicitude. ” The Analects, Book VII, Chapter 3.
[94]
2.373.3-4
[95]
3.21.1. to 3.55.4
[96]
3.23.9
[97]
3.24.6
[98]
3.22.12
[99]
3.22.13
[100] One fact may have argued against the absoluteness of such a rule. In this case, DSD was given some money by an official to publish the materials. DSD’s involvement in the publication process made him factually more knowledgeable and legally more culpable.
[101] The Doctrine of the Mean Chapter XIV: 2.
[102]
Analects Book XIV. Chapter 28.
[103]
Analects Book XIV. Chapter 27.
[104]
See Ci Yuan, 433 “shoufen.”
[105]
See Ci Yuan 435 for “anfen.”
[106]
PYCED, p. 202
[107] “HARMONY is the universal path which they all should pursue.” The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter I:4.
[108] “While there are no stirrings of pleasure, anger, sorrow, or joy, the mind may be said to be in the state of EQUILIBRIUM.” The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter I:4.
[109] The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter I.
[110] The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter I:1.
[111] For the cultured person, the most fundamental duty was to defend and promote the status quo. Any signs of discontent or any effort to change the system by the cultured were severely dealt with. The cultured person, being more educated, were by implication more thoughtful, observant and articulate. As a prominent class they were social and community leaders. The combination of the two spelled potential problems for the emperor who was intending on maintaining the status quo and peaceful rule. This critical analysis of the political function of Confucian rule was most strongly advocated by the PRC scholars, see Wu Shu Chen (ed.) Chinese Traditional Legal Culture (Bejing: Beijing University Press, 1990), p. 61. Another more neutral social functional analysis is possible, i.e., Confucian culture was conducive to the maintenance of a self-supporting agricultural community. Id. P.56.
[112]
2.371.1. to 2.384.9
[113]
2.382.7-8
[114]
2.81.1 to 2.83.13
[115] The memorial of Anhui governor-general (xunfu), Fu Nihan (FNH) Anhui xunfu Fu Naihan zouzhe. 2.82. 13. to 2.84.1.
[116]
2.82.3 to 5
[117]
3.103.1. to 3.120.15
[118]
3.109.6-10
[119]
3.57.1. to 3.55.10
[120]
3.59.3- 4
[121] The concept of bao is a central idea under the Confucian global idea of “ren. See Sources of Chinese Tradition, Vol. I, p.26. For a seminal discussion of the concept of “bao” see ‘Bao – zhongguo shehui guanshi de yige jiqu” (“Bao – the foundation of relationships in the Chinese society” in The Committee on Chinese Thought (ed.) Studies in Chinese Thought (Taipei: Jin Lian chubanshe, 1981), pp. 349-373.
[122] The theoretical foundation for bao as a “moral system of indirect reciprocity” was provided by Richard D. Alexander who postulated that the “beneficent individual” (in this case the emperor) in extending benefits to others (in this case the cultured) is necessary engaging in a utilitarian calculus, i.e., what can he gain, through direct or indirect “reciprocity,” by acting benevolently act. See Richard D. Alexander, The Biology of Moral System (N.Y.: Aldine De Gruyter, 1987), pp. 93-94.
[123]
Analects XIV: 36.
[124] Bao is not just a tit-for tat exchange process, though its manifestation invariable involved the exchange of material goods. Bao was mostly a return of “human compassion” (“ren qing”) or “good will”. What was exchanged was not as important as the “good feeling” of “thoughtfulness” being engendered. Bao is also functional in serving critical intergeneration exchange as well as economic re-distribution needs. Studies in Chinese Thought pp. 349-373.
[125]
2.385.1. to 2.409.10
[126]
2.399.9-11
[127]
2.357.1. to 2.369.10
[128]
2.362.11-12
[129]
2.360.11
[130]
2.360.12
[131] With some ethical theories, the primary criteria of rightness or wrongness of an act is the motive and intent of the actor. For example Immanuel Kant has observed that “to perform one’s promise when no compulsion can be applied to enforce it is a virtuous action, since the actor’s motiation is to perform an ethical duty; to perform because motivated by to external compulsion of law is to perform a juridical duty.” Patterson, p. 32.
[132] The Doctrine of the Mean. Chapter XXII.
[133] The Doctrine of the Mean. Chapter XXZV:2.
[134]
The Analects, Book II, Chapter 10.
[135]
See Case 22 at 2.65.1 to 2.72.8.
[136] See “E. Seeking revenge as a bad motive” infra.
[137]
2.65.1 to 2.72.8
[138]
2.68.7, 2.70.5
[139] Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter XIV: 3.
[140] See Wayne R. LaFave, Modern Criminal Law (St. Paul, Minn.: West, 1988), p. 105 (“motive is not relevant in substantive criminal law except as circumstantial evidence bearing on intent.”)
[141] “I am not concerned that I am not known, I seek to be worthy to be known.” Analects Book IV, Chapter 14.
[142] “The mind of the superior man is conversant with righteousness, The mind of the mean man is conversant with gain.” Analects Book IV, Chapter 16.
[143] “I will not be concerned at men’s not knowing me; I will be concerned at my own lack of ability.” Analects Book XI, Chapter 27.
[144] I thank Professor Toch for making this suggesting to me.
[145]
2.385.1. to 2.409.10
[146]
2.407.1 to 3.
[147]
2.87.1 to 2.90.2
[148] Yi can mean “yisi” which is “meaning” or “yitu” which means “motive and intent”. Here it means the later. See Ci Yuan 618.
[149]
2.88.10
[150]
Analects IV:16.
[151] Analects. Book V. Chapter 26. Confucius was lamenting that his students were not able to “nei zi song” which literally means “litigate inside oneself”. Legge has translated this as “to bring himself before the bar of his conscience.” The Four Books, p. 184, n. 26.
[152]
Analects XV:20.
[153]
Analects IV:11.
[154] Analects. Book XIII. Chapter 13. The statement was made with reference to a minister but it equally applied to a cultured person.
[155] Sources of Chinese Tradition, p. 114.
[156]
Analects. Book VII, Chapter 4:3.
[157] The Four Books, “The Text of Confucius” 4, p. 4.
[158] Erving Goffman’s suggested that when expectations and norms were broken in the public place the rule breaker and victim was forced to confront each other in a series of negotiation over how to fix the problem for the purpose of reestablishing social control or relationship between the offender and victim, a process Goffman called “Remedial Exchanges” Such a “remedial” process is very predictable and follows articulable rules. See Relations in Public , Ch. 4, pp. 95-187. There are two parts to a remedial exchange: giving an account of what happened and take responsibility for ones action, pp. 108-118 (“Two principal forms of remedial work have been considered: accounts and apologies.”).
[159] Prompt and whole hearted acceptance of responsibility “shows that what he seeks is not a change in his apportionment of rights but rather a single exception to restrictions and standards he is ready continue to accept…” Goffman, Relations in Public, p. 165.
[160]
2.91.1 to 2.109.1
[161] Wutu mans having no clear presence on mind. This goes against being a good official who is supposed to be alert and wise at all time. See Ci Yuan 1298.
[162]
2.102.2 - 4.
[163] The Chinese then as now believe that the acknowledgement of guilt is the first step to successful reform. Every step was taken to make the offender realize his own mistake. Bao Ruo-Wang & Rudolph Chelminski, Prisoner of Mao (N.Y.: Coward, McCann & Geoghean, Inc., New York, 1973) The Chinese approach is supported by modern day scientific-psychological theory. Effective personal reform starts with seld-acknowledging of ones problem. Such is the approach taken by the AA self-help program.
[164]
1.369.2 to 1.375.11
[165]
1.381.14
[166] “Nai Xiang Xiang an ge fan ying an lu yanzhi bude guxi yu” (Emperor’s decree regarding Nai Xian Xian and others should be seriously dealt with by law.) 1.381.14 to 1.383.9 (The emperor observed that the said governor has bungled the case in the following regards: (1) He has failed to interpret NX’s writings correctly, making them sounded more serious than they actually were. (2) He has entrusted his interpretation to his subordinate when he should be doing it himself. (3) He has been indulging other parties who were implicated in the case.)
[167] “Gao Jin deng zou qing jiao bu yichu zhe” (Memorial requesting to have Gao Jin and others to be turned over to the board to be dealt with) 1.383.11 to 1.384.9
[168]
1.384.3
[169]
1.384.4
[170]
1.384.5
[171]
1.384.5
[172]
1.384.6
[173]
1.384.6-7.
[174]
1.384.7
[175] Erving Goffman has perceptive noted that: “He who fails to sustain his obligation is responsible for trying to make amends for his offense and for showing proper regard for the process of correction. They whose expectations are not sustained must show that they are not to be delineated by what the offenses express about them and at whatever cost to themselves they have a proper relation to the sanctioning system, for their failure to commit themselves to this social mechanism can reflect more harshly on them than does the original offense.” Relations in Public, p. 100.
[176]
1.207.1 to 1. 236. 14
[177]
1.222.13
[178] “Zhuang You Gong zou cha xueyuan rennei jie guo Ding Wen Bin xian shu zhe.” (Memorial of Zhuang You Gong finding accepting Ding Wen Bin submitted books in college post.) 1.224.14 to 1.225.4.
[179]
1.225.4.
[180] “Zhuang You Gong zou qing jiao bu zhizui zhe.” (Memorial of Zhuang You Gong asking to be turned over to Ministry for punishment.) 1.230.11 to 1.231.11.
[181]
1.231.7-9.
[182]
1.222.14.
[183]
1.222.14.
[184] The emperor made clear in his initial instruction appended to ZYG’s first investigative memorial (1.225.4) that he did not believe that ZYG could be trusted to carry out an objective and impartial investigation of his own self in turning over the “offensive” book, nevertheless ZYG was allowed to conduct his own search for the book.
[185]
2.220.9-13.
[186] See Legge, Texts of Confucianism, III, 90. For a discussion of the doctrine, see Zhongguo gudai falushi zhishi , 43-45. This Confucian doctrine was manifested in the following ways: (1) The “dafu” were not amenable to regular judicial process, though they were not exempted from punishment. (2) Western Zhou bronze relic showed that punishment could be redeemed with money (“shu”) and only the “dafu” could afford to be redeemed. (3) The “dafu” could be banished to the frontier instead of being put to dead. (4) The “dafu” could be allowed commit suicide instead of capital punishment. (5) The execution of the “dafu” was often executed in out of sight places to preserve the dignity of the “dafu.”
[187] The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter XVII.
[188] The Doctrine of the Mean, Chapter XII.
[189]
The Analects, Book II, Chapter 14.
[190]
The Great Learning. Chapter II:3.
[191] The Analects, Book XII, Chapter 10.
[192] The Doctrine of the Man” Chapter XXVII: 6.
[193]
The Analects, Book II, Chapter 14.
[194] The use of legal control to enforce Confucian ethics would have reduced the observed the jurisdictional differences between legal control and self-control. The close ended legal control scheme was being plied open by the open-ended ethical rules. However, legal control because of its inherent properties, i.e. limitations posed by language, tradition, and convention, could not be made to police things not properly delineated, classified, or enumerated. Self-policing has no such “artificial” limitation.
[195] See note 13, supra.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/MurdochUeJlLaw/2004/24.html