Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
PRINCIPLES FOR SUBSTITUTED DECISION-MAKING ABOUT WITHDRAWING OR WITHHOLDING LIFE-SUSTAINING MEASURES IN QUEENSLAND: A CASE FOR LEGISLATIVE REFORM
MICHELLE HOWARD[*]
I INTRODUCTION
In Queensland, the Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld)
(GAA) and the Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) (PAA)
(collectively referred to as the guardianship regime) comprise a scheme to
facilitate substitute decision-making by and for adults
with impaired
capacity,[1] including decision-making
about withdrawing or withholding life-sustaining measures (WWLSM).
A
substitute decision-maker, who will most commonly be a family member or close
friend,[2] making a decision about
WWLSM must apply[3] (if the decision
is made under the GAA), or comply
with[4] (if the decision is made under
the PAA), the General
Principles[5] (GPs) and the Health
Care Principle[6] (HCP)(collectively
referred to as the Principles). The factors in the GPs must be applied or
complied with when a decision is made
under the scheme, whether it is a decision
about financial or personal (including health) matters. The HCP must be applied
or complied
with in relation to health decisions, and is non-specific to
life-sustaining measures.
This paper examines whether the Principles are
adequate to effectively guide decision-making about
WWLSM.[7] This examination considers
the Queensland regime for decision-making about WWLSM, relevant aspects of the
common law, the Principles,
application of the Principles by the Guardianship
and Administration Tribunal (GAAT or the Tribunal), and by a fictitious lay
decision-maker
through a case study, and analysis of issues arising from the
application of the Principles.
The case study considered is as
follows:
Rowena, a woman, aged 45, had an hypoxic brain injury following a cardiac
arrest during routine surgery nine months ago. She can breathe
independently,
but receives artificial nutrition and hydration (ANH) through a Percutaneous
Endoscopic Gastrostomy (PEG). Six months
after the cardiac arrest, she was
diagnosed as in a Post-Coma Unresponsive (previously referred to as vegetative)
state[8] and her health providers
recommend WWLSM, namely ANH. The health providers have told her husband, Mark,
that continuation of ANH
would be inconsistent with good medical practice (GMP).
Mark is her statutory health attorney by virtue of the operation of the
Queensland
guardianship regime, and able to make the decision about whether
Rowena’s ANH is stopped. Shortly before Rowena’s heart
attack
occurred, she told her family that she believed that medical science would be
able to cure virtually all conditions within
5 years, and she would want all
treatment available to keep her alive.
The paper concludes that the
Principles are not adequate as guidance for decision-making about WWLSM.
Legislative reform is
recommended.[9]
II QUEENSLAND REGIME
Assessment of the adequacy of the Principles to guide decision-making is
informed by understanding the context in which they operate.
For this reason,
brief consideration is given to other relevant provisions of the guardianship
regime.
A Overview of Legislative
Scheme
The purpose of the GAA is to strike a balance between the right of an
adult with impaired capacity to the greatest possible degree of autonomy and the
right
to adequate protection and support for
decision-making.[10]
The GAA acknowledges that the adult’s right to make
decisions is fundamental to dignity and should be interfered with to the least
possible
extent.[11]
1 General
Provisions about Health Care
The GAA provides for an offence
of carrying out health care without
authority.[12] Essentially, consent
is necessary for all health care for an adult with impaired capacity, unless the
GAA or another Act provides otherwise, or it is authorized by the Supreme
Court.
The GAA specifies an order of priority for dealing with
health matters under the Act where an adult has impaired capacity and consent is
required.[13] The decision can only
be made in accordance with the first applicable option in the priority
list.[14] The list specifies the
order of priority as follows: first, in accordance with a direction in an
adult’s advance health directive
(AHD);[15] second, where the
Guardianship and Administration Tribunal (GAAT or the Tribunal) has appointed a
guardian for the matter or made
an order about the matter, by the guardian or
under the order;[16] third, where
the adult made an enduring document/s appointing an attorney for the matter, by
the attorney appointed by the most recent
enduring
document;[17] and last, by the
statutory health attorney (SHA).[18]
A person, who will usually be a spouse, unpaid carer or close friend or
relative, becomes a SHA for an adult with impaired decision-making
capacity by
virtue of the operation of the
PAA.[19] Where there is
disagreement about a health matter for an adult between guardians, attorneys or
eligible statutory health attorneys,
the Adult Guardian can mediate, and if
unresolved, may exercise power for the health
matter.[20A]
In most cases,
the decision-maker will be a lay decision-maker who has been appointed as
attorney for health matters or is SHA under
the PAA. As referred to
earlier, the Principles must be applied or complied with by the
decision-maker.[20]
2 Specific
Provisions for Decisions about WWLSM
Health care is defined to
include WWLSM for an adult if commencing or continuing the life-sustaining
measure (LSM) would be inconsistent
with GMP.
[21]
The guardianship regime
provides for WWLSM without consent in an acute emergency in limited
circumstances where the decision must
be taken immediately in accordance with
GMP.[22] It does not apply where the
health provider knows the adult
objects,[23] and does not apply to
ANH.[24]
Where a decision
about WWLSM is made by a substitute decision-maker under the regime for health
decision-making, consent cannot operate
unless the health provider for the adult
considers commencement or continuation of the LSM would be inconsistent with
GMP.[25]
A LSM is health care
intended to sustain or prolong life that supplants or maintains vital body
functions which are unable to operate
independently, and include cardiopulmonary
resuscitation (CPR), assisted ventilation, and
ANH.[26]
III COMMON LAW
It is necessary to consider the common law, as a step in establishing the
adequacy of the Principles to effectively guide decision-making
about WWLSM as
it has been relied upon in decision-making under the legislative regime. To
establish the context, it should be noted
that the right to autonomy or
self-determination is fundamental to health
law.[27] Patient consent renders the
giving of health care lawful.[28A] A
competent patient may refuse treatment, even life-saving
treatment.[28] An
‘incompetent’ (this is the commonly employed terminology in the
common law literature) patient has the same
right.[29] However, there is no
recognized common law right to compel a health provider to provide treatment
which the health provider does
not consider clinically
indicated.[30A]
A The Position of the Incompetent Person
A binding anticipatory directive refusing treatment may be given in advance
of loss of capacity.[30] Where there
is no valid advance directive, appropriate medical treatment may be given to an
incompetent patient as a matter of necessity
where it is in the patient’s
best interests.[31] Similarly,
life-sustaining treatment may be withheld or withdrawn in the patient’s
best interests. In the seminal case of Airedale NHS Trust v
Bland,[32] (Bland’s Case)
the House of Lords considered that artificial nutrition and hydration (ANH)
could lawfully be withdrawn from a patient in a persistent
vegetative state
(PVS) because the treatment was considered futile, and a responsible body of
medical opinion was to the effect that
continued existence in PVS was not a
benefit to the patient. It was not considered in the best interests of
Anthony Bland for treatment to continue. Reference was made to considerations
other
than medical opinion, but it is difficult to see how they were factored
into the assessment of best
interests.[33]
The best
interests test has been applied in cases where declarations have been sought as
to the lawfulness of discontinuing life-sustaining
measures, including in
Bland’s Case and Auckland Area Health Board v Attorney
General,[34] and where the
decision is made in the parens patriae jurisdiction, including, Re
G[35] and Messiha v
South East
Health.[36]
Numerous
United Kingdom cases about WWLSM have been decided since Bland’s Case
and have articulated numerous non-medical factors as relevant, as well as
medical opinion.[37] Recently, the
English Court of Appeal has stated that best interests includes every possible
consideration, including medical, emotional
and other
matters.[38]
At common law,
there has been one Australian decision allowing withdraw life-sustaining
treatment for an incompetent
person.[39] The decision of the New
South Wales Supreme Court in Messiha v South East
Health[40] does not provide
detailed consideration of relevant law. Essentially, doctors decided to
terminate life-sustaining measures. The adult’s
family opposed this and
applied in the parens patriae jurisdiction for an order to prevent the
withdrawal. The Court considered best
interests the applicable test. It
considered it would be an unusual case where the Court would act against
unanimous medical views:
this was said to be acceptance of the fact that a
decision about appropriate treatment is principally a matter of medical
opinion.[41]
Despite apparent
increasing emphasis on non-medical considerations, the factors to be taken into
account other than medical opinion
lack specificity. Courts adopting the test
have criticized it as a basis for
decision-making.[42] Academics have
criticized it for paternalism and medicalisation of life-ending
decision-making.[43] An eminent
jurist has criticised the best interests test, in the context of
decision-making about sterilisation, as creating an unexaminable discretion
in
the hands of the decision-maker, exercise of which is dependent on the value
system of the decision-maker, and which provides
no hierarchy of values and no
legal principle.[44]
IV THE PRINCIPLES
A Preliminary Description and
Analysis of Principles
The text of the Principles in the GAA is reproduced in Appendix
One.[45]
Some of the
Principles are general statements of rights applicable to all adults. For
example, GPs 1, 2, 3, 4, and 11 and HCP 12(4)
express general rights.
Application of some of the Principles may suggest that a decision be made in a
particular way in a specific
fact situation which has arisen, but of themselves
are imprecise in meaning. For example, GPs 5, 6, 8, 9, 10 and HCP 12(1). Some
suggest a process to be adopted for decision-making, namely GP 7 and HCP 12(2)
and 12(5). It is possible that application of different
principles will suggest
different outcomes in any given situation. There is no prescribed priority or
hierarchy to suggest some principles
are more important than others or any
procedure to resolve conflict arising when application of different principles
suggests different
outcomes.
Not all of the Principles appear to be
relevant to decisions about WWLSM. Those that appear most obviously of likely
relevance are
GP 1, 2, 3, 7, 9, 10 and HCP (1)-(4).
B Relevant History
When analysing the adequacy of the Principles to effectively guide
decision-making, it is useful to briefly consider some historical
matters.
1 Explanatory Notes and Parliamentary Debate
The
explanatory notes to the PAA and GAA do not explain the manner in
which Parliament intended the Principles to be applied generally. However, the
second reading speech[46] to the
PAA, suggests that application of the principle of substituted
judgment[47] requires that an
attorney should where possible make the decision the adult would have made if
able.[48] Of course, under the
PAA, there was no provision for WWLSM by a substitute decision-maker; and
in respect of the GAA, no reference was made to application of the
principles for decisions about WWLSM. At the time the GAA was enacted,
the proposed regime was different from the current regime: in the absence of an
AHD, GAAT alone had power to decide
about
WWLSM.[49] The Attorney-General
suggested that broad principles were integral and appropriate to give statutory
recognition to rights of people
with a decision-making disability whilst
shielding against abuse and
exploitation.[50]
Subsequently, the Guardianship and Administration Act and Other Acts
Amendment Act 2001(Qld) was passed. The purpose was to overcome the
requirement that all decisions about withdrawing and withholding of
life-sustaining
measures be made by GAAT, where there was no
AHD.[51] It provided for a guardian
or attorney (including a SHA) to consent to WWLSM. WWLSM was no longer
‘special health care,’
but ‘health care.’ It provided
for amendment to the HCP so that health care decisions could authorize health
care which
was, in all the circumstances, in the adult’s best
interests.[52]
Concerns were
raised[53] that inclusion of a best
interests criterion adopted the common law as set out in Bland’s
Case. The Attorney-General amended the Explanatory Notes to delete reference
to Bland’s Case and stated
The purpose of the amendment is
to ensure that the phrase ‘in all the circumstances in the best interests
of the adult’
is not read as an endorsement of all the interpretations
that the phrase ‘best interests’ was given in the case of Bland.
In
other words we are not adopting the interpretation of ‘best
interests’ that was canvassed by the court in the English
case of Bland.
Rather, the phrase ‘in relation to withholding or withdrawing
life-sustaining measures’ reflects the proposition
that when death is
inevitable, regardless of the treatment administered, the administration of
futile measures that only secure a
precarious and burdensome prolongation of
life may not be in the best interests of the
adult.[54]
The Act
was passed. Despite the amendment to the explanatory notes, Bland’s
Case was part of the common law. As will be explored in the next section,
the Tribunal has relied upon the common law meaning of best interests
in cases
concerning the withdrawing or withholding of life-sustaining measures.
V APPLICATION OF THE PRINCIPLES
A GAAT Decisions
about WWLSM
Only two relevant cases, Re
MC,[55] and Re
HG,[56] have been decided since
the 2001 amendments commenced operation.
Re HG, is a recent GAAT
decision, in which consent was given for WWLSM. The adult was diagnosed as in a
locked-in syndrome following a stroke.
It was thought he probably retained his
pre-stroke cognition (which was impaired as a result of other medical
conditions). Although
not all of them were applied, the approach taken to the
application of the Principles is significantly more detailed than in earlier
GAAT decisions, as discussed below. More attention is given to explication of
the application of the Principles. It applied GP 2,
3, 7(4), 10 and HCP 12 (1).
In respect of GP 2, GAAT identified that the adult had the right to refuse
medical treatment.[57] In applying
GP 3, an explanation is provided for the interpretation
adopted.[58] There is a clear
statement that the Tribunal is exercising power under the HCP 12 (1)(b), in the
adult’s best interests, as
that term is understood as it evolves at common
law.[59] It briefly reviewed the
common law and the current wide interpretation of relevant factors, and then
articulated factors it considered
relevant to determining best
interests.[60] There is no
substantive explanation[61] as to
the basis for ignoring some Principles.
In Re MC, the adult was
diagnosed as in PVS. GAAT consented to WWLSM, namely
ANH.[62] The decision appears to
accord some priority to best interests and least restrictive of rights
principles over other
principles.[63]
The Tribunal
noted its obligations to apply the
Principles.[64] Reliance was placed
upon Bland’s Case, the Auckland Area Health Board v
Attorney General,[65] and
Re G,[66] in relation to best
interests.[67] Discussion about
those cases centred on statements that it was not in a patient’s best
interests for futile treatment which
was of no benefit to a patient to be
continued. GAAT also stated that, when determining best interests, consideration
was given to
medical opinion; (a substituted judgment about) the views of the
adult; and views of the family,[68]
and that GAAT was not satisfied it was in MC’s best interests for ANH to
continue. It is not clear how the non-medical matters
were identified as
relevant, how they should be, or were, taken into account and weighed to reach
the conclusion, in this case, that
it was not in MC’s best interests for
ANH to continue.
Discussion then moved to application of other principles. Ongoing ANH was not
considered the option least restrictive of the adult’s
rights, as GAAT
considered a patient had a right to receive ordinary treatment, (as opposed to
extraordinary treatment, including
futile treatment), and a right to refuse
treatment.[69] In relation to the
GPs; only GP 3[70] and GP
7(4),[71] were applied. In relation
to GP 3, it was considered that MC’s right to respect for human worth and
dignity was not accorded
by continuing futile treatment. Applying GP 7(4),
reliance was placed upon evidence that MC was a private person who would not
have
consented to the treatment.[72]
Notably, HCP 12(2) was applied. [73]
As a matter of statutory interpretation, HCP 12(2) seems
irrelevant.[74] The support of the
attorney for health matters (a son of the adult) and palliative care experts for
withdrawing of ANH was separately
noted towards the end of the reasons for
decision.[75] GAAT did not indicate
under which principle it considered these matters relevant. It seems they would
already have been considered
under best
interests.[76]
No
explanation was given for according priority to some principles over
others,[77] nor about how factors
(other than medical opinion) relevant to best interests were identified and
taken into account. There was no
explanation for failure to apply some
principles at all. In respect of the best interests
criterion, it is possible that application of the other principles was intended
to be the consideration
of best interests. With the exception of the application
of GP 3, they appear to broadly equate to the matters said to be relevant
to
best interests. Such an approach is arguably supported by the reference in HCP
12(1)(b)(ii) to in all the circumstances in the adult’s best
interests.[78]
If this was the process GAAT embarked upon, it did not clearly articulate
it; in any event, the finding that continued treatment was
not in MC’s
best interests preceded consideration of the other
principles.[79]
It is suggested that the Tribunal’s selection of principles applied
and interpretation of them was subjective and alternative
constructs were
equally feasible. For example, human worth and dignity was considered to be
compromised by futile medical
treatment.[80] Equally, GP 3 could
be interpreted to indicate that the adult’s human worth and dignity is to
be recognized and respected irrespective
of the level of disability
present.[81] HCP 12(4), recognizing
a right to refuse treatment, appears to have been interpreted to mean that
treatment would be
refused.[82]
Re
RWG[83] involved an adult with a
brain stem injury. An order was made by GAAT to WWLSM, namely CPR. Application
to withhold antibiotics in
the future in the event of sepsis was refused,
because it was speculative.[84]
Although a best interests consideration did not form part of the HCP at
this time, GAAT applied the common
law.[85] GAAT stated that it was
required to apply the GPs, the HCP (to the extent it was applicable to WWLSM
decisions)[86] and the common
law.[87] GAAT considered that the
GPs, (especially the adult’s same human rights, and right to be respected
for his human worth and
dignity) and the HCP (taking into account the views of
the adult, the health care provider and the SHA), and the common law principles
as set out in Bland’s Case, lead to the conclusion that CPR would
not be of any benefit to the adult, and therefore not in his best
interests.[88]
The best
interests test was applied. GAAT seems to have considered that any treatment
which was of no therapeutic benefit was not
in the adult’s best
interests,[89] suggesting that only
medical opinion was considered relevant to a determination of best interests.
Although GAAT identified the need
to apply the
GPs,[90] it did so selectively
without reference to why some GPs were ignored. Reference was made to
adults’ same human rights (although,
no relevant rights were identified)
and right to respect for human worth or dignity. However, no meaningful effect
is given to these
principles.[91]
Lastly, in Re TM,[92]
the adult had Alzheimer’s Disease. Oral feeding was no longer considered
safe and recommendations were made for it to cease.
GAAT consented to WWLSM,
namely ANH.
GAAT found that the adult was in the terminal phase of
illness and that as a matter of substituted judgment, would not have wanted
ANH,
which could compromise her dying. It applied Bland’s Case
recognizing best interests as the appropriate test for
decision-making. The Tribunal was not satisfied the PEG would provide a
therapeutic benefit and therefore was not in the adult’s best
interests.[93] Again, it appears
that medical opinion only was thought relevant to best interests assessment.
Once again, GAAT merely acknowledged
the statements in the GPs, especially the
adult’s right to respect for her human worth and dignity, and recognized
that she
had the same rights as other members of
society.[94] The Tribunal was not
satisfied the provision of the PEG was the option least restrictive of the
adult’s rights, and considered
it least restrictive to allow the adult not
to receive it and to be allowed to
die.[95]
Other principles
were taken into account, GP 7(4) and HCP 12(2) in relation to the adults
wishes.[96] In accordance with HCP
12(4), it was noted that an adult has the right to refuse
treatment[97] and the Tribunal
recognized that she would not want this
treatment.[98] Also, in accordance
with HCP 12(5) which is applicable only to special health care decisions, the
Tribunal accepted the views of
the SHAs, namely her children (who did not
consider the treatment for her benefit) and the adult’s health providers,
in this
case the nursing home, but was persuaded by the views of the adult and
her SHAs over the nursing
home.[99]
Again, GAAT
selectively applied the Principles. It undertook no meaningful application of GP
2 and 3. In assessing the option least
restrictive of an adult’s rights,
no rights are identified except perhaps a ‘right’ to
die,[100] despite the fact that at
least the right to refuse treatment was identified as generally relevant to the
decision having regard to
the wishes of the adult as
found.[101]
It is
suggested that the apparent shortcomings in the application of the Principles in
GAAT decisions are demonstrative of the Tribunal’s
struggle to make sense
of how the Principles are to be applied in cases about WWLSM, and indicative of
some of the difficulties which
may arise when a lay decision-maker attempts to
do so. It is of particular significance that the common law is heavily relied
upon
in relation to the meaning of ‘best interests’ and that little
attention is given to identifying the ‘rights’
of the adult which
are relevant to the application of a number of the Principles. A lay
decision-maker will have no knowledge of
the common law and limited
understanding of legal rights. Accordingly, it is suggested that a lay
decision-maker will find the Principles
even more difficult to apply than the
Tribunal.
B Application of Principles: Case Study
As observed earlier, the decision-maker will most often be a close friend
or relative of the adult. In this part, it is intended to
test application of
the Principles against the case study set out in the Introduction of this
article, with a view to considering
difficulties which may arise for lay
decision-makers.
For the purposes of the case study, Mark is not a
lawyer, an ethicist or a philosopher. He has no knowledge of common law cases,
nor
any knowledge of GAAT cases about WWLSM. It is assumed that Mark has been
given a copy of a fact-sheet listing the
Principles.[102]
1 Application
of the Principles
Consideration will be given to the difficulties a
lay-decision-maker, in Mark’s position might encounter as the Principles
are
applied.
1 GP 1: presumption of capacity. This principle could
confuse Mark. Despite the presumption, his wife does not have capacity. How he
could apply this principle is
not apparent.
2 GP 2: recognition of
the adult’s human rights. Mark likely has no knowledge of the range of
rights which this principle seeks to encompass. How rights to be taken into
account
are to be identified is not apparent.
3 GP 3: right to
respect for human worth and dignity. The general tenor of the Principles
strongly indicates that a person with impaired capacity does not have less right
to respect
for his or her human worth and dignity, than a person without
impaired capacity. This principle could mean that the human worth of
the person
with impaired capacity is no less than before the impairment. In the
alternative, in the context of WWLSM, it may mean
matters which the adult,
before loss of capacity, considered invasions to personal dignity, should be
taken into account.[103] Mark may
subjectively consider that dignity is lost because of loss of capacity. It is
not apparent whether the decision-maker is
entitled to take his or her own views
into account.
4 GP 4-6: valued member of society; participation in
community life; & encouragement of self-reliance. An adult for whom
consent is sought to WWLSM will presumably have overwhelming disabilities and no
longer be able to perform social
roles, participate in community life or be
self-reliant. It is difficult to formulate relevant application of these
principles to
a decision to WWLSM.
5 GP 7: maximum participation,
minimal limitation & substituted judgment. The adult had not anticipated
precisely the medical circumstances in which she now finds herself. However, she
did express clear
wishes to be kept alive in any circumstances. A substitute
decision-maker in Mark’s position might likely consider that, as
an
exercise of substituted judgment, Rowena would not consent to withdrawing ANH.
6 GP 8: maintenance of the adult’s existing supportive
relationships. To maintain existing supportive relationships, consent for
WWLSM cannot be given. This principle may appear to suggest that consent
cannot
be given for WWLSM in any circumstances where there are supportive
relationships. However, the decision-maker will be aware
that it can be given.
7 GP 9: maintenance of cultural environment and values. The
importance of maintaining cultural environment appears
irrelevant.[104] The importance of
maintaining values is relevant. Mark will be aware of the adult’s
religious views and other values. It appears
that she values highly
medical/scientific advancement and this may suggest to Mark that LSM should be
continued.
8 GP 10: appropriate to circumstances. The adult has
experienced a catastrophic medical event and requires significant medical
treatment to live. Her substitute decision-maker
may be unclear whether this GP
means that he should make a decision which meets her current medical needs to
survive, or whether
it means he should accept her characteristics are such that
she should not continue to receive treatment because the doctors believe
she
cannot recover.
9 GP 11: confidentiality. In the context of a
decision about WWLSM, it is suggested this principle appears irrelevant
and cannot be meaningfully interpreted in any way by a lay
decision-maker.
10 HCP (1)(a) the power should be exercised in a way
that is least restrictive of the adult’s rights. Mark may consider
that if he consents, Rowena will have no rights: she will be deceased. But he
will likely be uncertain what rights
she has that are relevant. He may
ultimately take irrelevant
considerations[105] into account;
fail to take relevant
considerations[106] into account;
or consider the principle raises interpretation issues which he cannot be
expected to resolve.
11 HCP (1)(b)(i) necessary and appropriate to
maintain or promote health or wellbeing or,(ii) in all the circumstances, in the
adult’s
best interests. A decision-maker might consider that not
consenting to withdrawal of ANH maintains the health or wellbeing of Rowena as
far as possible
and that this Principle suggests that WWLSM may not be indicated
in any circumstances under this limb of the principle. A lay decision-maker
could be confused by its inclusion in principles intended to guide decisions
about WWLSM.
Since the decision-maker will be aware that consent can be
given to WWLSM, the other option of best interests will likely be considered.
The meaning of best interests is imprecise. Considerations relevant to a
determination are not specified. There is no indication
whether the
determination is to be made from the perspective of the adult, the health
provider or the decision-maker. A decision-maker
may consider it means that
WWLSM which does not maintain health and well-being (and is therefore not
covered by HCP 12(1)(b)(i)),
can be given when it seems the ‘right
thing’. Mark might reason that the doctors think that LSM should cease; it
seems
right from the medical point of view. Another possibility may be to tally
up the answers the principles suggest, and calculate best
interests according to
the number supporting withdrawing ANH as opposed to those which suggest
otherwise.
Ultimately, a decision must be made. A decision-maker, such
as Mark, will likely decide that he must make his own value judgment about
his
wife’s best interests: this is the best he can do. Based on his values
about life, he may conclude that that it cannot
be in Rowena’s best
interests for LSM to be continued.
12 HCP (2) & (3) when
considering appropriateness, must take into account, the views/wishes of the
adult and the information given
by the health provider. It is suggested that
‘appropriateness’ is referred to in HCP 12(1)(b)(i) about
maintaining a person’s health or
well-being, and as a matter of statutory
construction is not applicable to the best interests assessment. However, a lay
decision-maker
is likely unfamiliar with principles of statutory interpretation
and may consider the principle is relevant to a determination of
best interests.
13 HCP (4) the adult’s right to refuse health care. A lay
decision-maker such as Mark may accept that Rowena has the right to refuse
health care. However, in Rowena’s case, Mark
would likely accept on the
basis of her previous comments, that as a matter of substituted judgment the
adult would not refuse further
ANH.
After a tortuous exercise, a lay
decision-maker would likely be left with the impression that some principles
suggest WWLSM, and some
suggest otherwise. The meaning of some of the principles
is unclear or requires specialist knowledge that the decision-maker could
not be
expected to have, and therefore cannot be meaningfully applied or complied
with.
VI ANALYSIS OF ISSUES ABOUT APPLICATION OF PRINCIPLES
Consideration of the application of the Principles by GAAT and the fictitious
lay decision-maker in the case study have facilitated
identification of issues
relevant to analysing the adequacy of the Principles to effectively guide
substitute decision-making about
WWLSM.
A Difficulties Associated with Application of Broad Range of Non-Prioritized Principles
The Principles are broadly drafted. This affects their adequacy to
effectively guide decision-making about WWLSM in several ways.
1 Some
of the principles seem irrelevant to a decision about WWLSM.
The
presumption of capacity enshrined in GP 1 is
rebuttable.[107] This is
meaningful to lawyers, GAAT and the Supreme Court. The legal concept of a
rebuttable presumption is not one necessarily,
or likely, known by lay
decision-makers. A lay decision-maker, stricken with grief may be quite confused
by the inclusion of a principle
presuming the adult to have capacity. Of course,
it is relevant for a decision-maker to be aware that an adult who has capacity
can
decide for themself whether to refuse LSM.
GPs 4, 5 and 6 appear
irrelevant, since the decision will be requested in circumstances where an adult
can no longer perform social
roles, participate in community life and achieve
maximum self-reliance. GAAT has not applied these principles to decisions about
WWLSM. It is difficult to envisage a situation in which a decision-maker could
do so.
GP 8 may appear relevant to a decision-maker. However, there is
not an obligation to continue LSM indefinitely to maintain existing
supportive
relationships. It appears that GP 8 cannot be relevant to a decision about
WWLSM. GAAT has not applied GP 8 in decision-making
about WWLSM. Although it has
not articulated a basis for this, most likely it has considered it
irrelevant.
GP 11 requiring an adult’s right to confidentiality to
be recognized and taken into account has no apparent relevance to a decision
about WWLSM.[108] It is likely to
cause confusion for a lay decision-maker attempting to diligently apply the
principles.
HCP 12(1)(b)(i) provides for the exercise of power if
necessary or appropriate to maintain or promote health or wellbeing. Before
the
2001 amendments to the GAA, GAAT, when considering WWLSM, inventively
suggested that this meant treatment should not be given if it was futile in
medical terms,
and applied the common law best interests test. It is suggested
that the shortcomings of this principle in the context of decisions
about WWLSM
were recognized and legislative changes made, at least in part, to avoid the
legal fiction of holding out a decision
WWLSM as a decision ‘necessary and
appropriate to maintain health and wellbeing’. It is suggested that it has
no place
as a part of the guidance provided to decision-makers in relation to
decision-making about WWLSM. In Re
HG,[109] and
ReMC,[110] GAAT considered
this principle irrelevant, stating that the HCP in WWLSM cases required it to
make a decision in the best interests
of the adult.
As earlier
articulated, HCP 2 is suggested to be relevant to deciding whether exercise of
power is appropriate, which is relevant to HCP 12(1)(b)(i). The 2001
amendments did not alter the ambit of 12(2) beyond relevance to deciding whether
an
exercise of power was appropriate. A decision-maker could be forgiven for
thinking that appropriateness might refer to appropriateness
of any health care
decision. Indeed, in Re
MC,[111] GAAT appears to have
applied the principle.[112]
HCP 12(5) is relevant to decisions about special health care. It appears
in the Principles in the GAA, but not the PAA. The decision about
WWLSM is health care if commencement or continuation would be inconsistent with
GMP, not special health care.[113]
The case study considered a SHA who makes a decision under the PAA.
Hopefully, a SHA would not be referred to this Principle. A guardian making a
decision under the GAA would note its inclusion in the Principles
provided to him or her. This is likely to confuse a lay decision-maker, who will
not know
what special health matters are, and may think that because of its
life-ending consequences, that consenting to WWLSM must be
special.
2 Difficulties with Interpretation of Principles in the
Context of WWLSM
GP 2 requires recognition of human rights regardless
of capacity. In relation to WWLSM, it is suggested that the intended application
of this principle is unclear and likely to confuse a lay decision-maker who is
unlikely to have any detailed concept of human and
civil rights against which to
identify possible relevant rights. To a lawyer who has a detailed knowledge of
rights, consideration
of different individual rights may nevertheless suggest
different outcomes. In Re
RWG,[114] and Re
TM,[115] GAAT merely
acknowledged that the adults had the same basic human rights as all adults: it
did not identify any particular rights
said to be relevant to application of GP
2. In Re MC,[116] the
principle was not considered at all. It appeared that even GAAT had been unable
to give this apparently fundamental principle
meaning in this context. More
recently in Re HG,[117]
more attention was paid to application of the principle: the only right
identified as relevant was the right to refuse
treatment.[118]
GP 3
refers to recognition of the adult’s right to be respected for his or her
human worth and dignity. Interpretation in a
manner which suggests life as a
disabled person (as a result of illness or accident) holds less worth or dignity
arguably devalues
the lives of those who are disabled. In Re
MC,[119] GAAT took the view
that human worth and dignity was lost by provision of futile treatment that did
not allow the adult to die naturally.
Lack of clarity, leaves it for
decision-makers to determine subjectively what is meant and how to apply the
principle.
GP 7(3) and GP 7(4) require that the adult’s views and
wishes be sought, and where appropriate, the principle of substituted
judgment
be used to work out what the adult’s views and wishes would be. A
substitute decision-maker must take those views
and wishes into account. GP
7(1), (2) and (3) focus on an adult’s right to participate in the
decision-making process as far
as possible. It is clear that the adult’s
views about the particular decision to be made are relevant. It is not clear,
but
possible, that there is a requirement to consider the adult’s views
and wishes, actual or substituted, when applying the principles.
For example,
the identification of relevant rights under GP 2 in a WWLSM case could be
undertaken as an exercise of substituted judgment.
If this was the requirement,
some subjectivity on the part of the decision-maker could be eliminated. It is
suggested that the perspective
from which the principles are applied is a
significant issue and it will be separately considered further.
GP 9
requires that the importance of maintaining an adult’s cultural and
linguistic environment and values be taken into account.
Most people have some
values, which may be culturally related, relevant to decisions about life and
death and accordingly relevant
to WWLSM, whether they be religious, spiritual,
agnostic, atheist, existentialist or scientific. Dilemmas arise about how such
values
might impact upon a life-ending decision. An adult may be atheist and
wish to be kept alive as long as possible, because they do
not think there is
existence after death. Despite spiritual beliefs, an adult may wish to receive
all possible treatment because
of other values. It is noted that in Re
TM, [120] despite
hearing some evidence about the adult’s religious beliefs, the Tribunal
did not make findings of fact about values and
did not apply GP 9.
HCP
12(1)(a) [as well as GP 7(3)(c)] requires that power be exercised in the way
least restrictive of an adult’s rights. Once
again, identification of
relevant rights is problematic. GAAT has applied the Principle in such a way as
to support a decision to
WWLSM. In Re
MC,[121] GAAT considered the
right to refuse medical treatment and the right to receive ordinary medical
treatment, (as opposed to extraordinary
treatment), when determining the option
least restrictive of an adult’s rights under HCP 12(1)(a). In Re
TM,[122] it appears to
consider a right to die.[123]
HCP 12(1)(b)(ii) requires that power must be exercised, in all the
circumstances, in the adult’s best interests. There are no
minimum
considerations prescribed to guide a best interests assessment. It is suggested
that prescription of a best interests consideration
to guide decision-making
about WWLSM is especially problematic. For present purposes, it is noted that
the inclusion of best interests
in the HCP invites GAAT to apply an arguably
unsatisfactory body of common law for its interpretation and application; and
lacks
clarity as a stand alone concept for lay decision-makers. Because of the
significance of this issue, the difficulties associated
with ‘best
interests’ will be separately considered.
3 Application of some
principles suggests a different outcome to application of other principles
As the case study demonstrates, application of some Principles may
suggest a decision should be made to WWLSM, and application of
others may
suggest otherwise. There is no mechanism for resolving a less than unanimous
outcome. Should the decision-maker tally
up those for and against, and the one
with the greatest numbers prevails? Should the decision-maker decide to allocate
greater weight
to some Principles than others, as GAAT did in Re
MC,[124] in pronouncing that
the Principles meant that the decision must be the least restrictive of the
adult’s rights and in the circumstances
in the adult’s best
interests? There is no justification apparent in the Principles themselves for
adopting any of the possible
approaches, since a decision-maker’s
obligation is to apply[125] or
comply with[126] the Principles.
Accordingly, a decision-maker must subjectively overcome the lack of mechanism
for resolving conflict in suggested
outcomes.
4 Comment
It
is suggested that Principles resulting in conflicting possible interpretations,
apparent irrelevancies, and conflict between suggested
outcomes without a
mechanism for resolution, cannot be considered to constitute effective guidance
for decision-making.
B Difficulties Associated with Autonomy and
Perspective
Self-determination of adults with impaired decision-making capacity to
the greatest extent possible is highly valued. It is reflected
in the purpose
and acknowledgments to the GAA.
As the case study demonstrates,
subjective beliefs of the decision-maker may override the wishes of the adult in
decision-making about
WWLSM, since the adult’s wishes are only one factor
to be considered in making the decision. White and
Willmott[127] noted that factors
to be considered in a health decision are wider than the adult’s wishes,
and some may conflict with those
wishes.
To accord self-determination,
it is possible that, as far as practicable, the Principles were intended to be
applied from the point
of view of the adult. However, a requirement to do so is
not clearly stated. GP 7(3) and (4) require that, to the greatest extent
practicable, views and wishes of an adult, or a substituted judgment made about
them, be taken into account. Having regard to the
value placed on autonomy, this
is arguably relevant to application of the Principles, rather than merely the
particular decision
to be
made.[128] Some Principles
probably cannot be applied from the perspective of the adult, for example, GP 1
and GP 7(1) and (5). Others could.
If the application was undertaken in this
way, then for example, in regard to GP 2, the adult’s views about human
rights considered
important could assist to identify the human rights which are
relevant to the decision. A particular adult may highly value their
right to
refuse medical treatment, and may have done so regularly throughout their life,
preferring to rely on natural remedies,
or accept the course of illness as part
of the human state. This would appear to be an appropriate basis for a
decision-maker to
determine that the right to refuse health care is an important
and relevant right to this particular
adult.[129] Another adult may have
a history of accepting all possible treatments for their illnesses, and like
Rowena, wish to continue doing
so despite incapacity. For this adult, perhaps
the right to refuse treatment is not a right which is valued. It does not appear
that
GAAT has considered that application of the Principles requires this
approach when deciding WWLSM cases. A lay decision-maker is
unlikely to be
prompted to consider this possibility.
It is beyond the scope of this article to explore how a requirement to apply the Principles from the adult’s subjective perspective (which may result in a refusal to consent to WWLSM) could be reconciled with the general common law position that an adult cannot compel health care, only choose between offered treatments or refuse it.[130]
If it was intended that the application of the Principles be undertaken
from the adult’s point of view where practicable, this
is not clearly
stated, although consistent with a reading of the Principles themselves and the
legislative scheme.
C Difficulties Associated with Best Interests
As noted previously, HCP 12(2) does not prescribe considerations for
determining best interests, despite the apparent relevance of
the matters
prescribed to a best interests assessment, namely the adult’s wishes and
medical information. The Tribunal has
looked to the common law for guidance
about the considerations relevant to best interests. As noted, in the past, the
Tribunal has
relied heavily upon Bland’s Case, to determine best
interests, although in Re HG it clarified that it adopted the meaning of
best interests as it has evolved at common
law.[131]
As noted, Courts
have expressed their disquiet about the unsatisfactory nature of the best
interests test, and about using the test
to determine life and death questions,
and have urged Parliaments to legislate in relation to the issue. As noted
earlier, members
of the Queensland Parliament expressed concern that insertion
of a best interests consideration into the HCP adopted Bland’s Case.
The Attorney-General amended the Explanatory Notes to delete reference to
Bland’s Case. Amendment of the Explanatory Notes did not affect the
common law. The Tribunal, when next faced with a WWLSM case, followed precedent
about the meaning of best interests, in the absence of any legislative
prescription as to considerations, and relied upon Bland’s Case.
The Tribunal clearly considered it needed guidance. In the legal decision-making
arena, it is appropriate that guidance be taken
from common law.
If
Parliament intended that the principles from Bland’s Case not be
adopted into decision-making about WWLSM, it needed to ensure that the Tribunal,
and other decision-makers, were provided
with clarity around the considerations
to take into account, so that the common law was irrelevant. It is worth stating
the obvious:
case law is evolutionary. Parliament, by leaving the prescribed
matters relevant to best interests undefined, has left GAAT and Courts
to
interpret the test in accordance with developments in the common law and may
include factors not considered by Parliament, and
which Parliament finds
undesirable, as it apparently found at least some of the principles flowing from
Bland’s Case.
In the case of lay decision-makers, it is
unlikely that the common law will guide a best interests determination. The lay
decision-maker
will most likely have no knowledge of common law. However, this
leaves the substitute-decision-maker to form his or her own subjective
opinion
about what ‘best interests’ means, and take into account as many or
as few matters as he or she considers relevant,
from whatever perspective he or
she prefers. It is suggested that most will likely strive to make what is
considered to be the ‘right’
decision. In the absence of appropriate
guidance, it is the best that can be hoped. It is not effectively guided
principled decision-making.
The guardianship regime does not allow a
decision to be made about WWLSM unless commencement or continuation of the LSM
would not
be consistent with GMP. At the very least, medical opinion will be
taken into account in some way. However, issues about life and
death are not
purely medical matters. It is argued that it is inappropriate that medical
opinion might be the only matter considered
by some decision-makers. Health law
generally, and the legislative
regime,[132A] recognize (in the
absence of emergency and minor treatment) that it is not appropriate for a
health provider to impose health care
on a person according to his or her own
clinical judgment. As discussed earlier in this article, it is for the competent
patient
to decide to consent, or not, to offered health care according to his or
her own preferences and ideas about illness, medicine, and
a myriad of other
matters as he or she thinks appropriate, and in the case of serious conditions,
life itself. GP 2 specifically
provides that all adults have the same basic
human rights regardless of capacity. If an adult has impaired capacity, a
substitute
decision-maker must decide. It appears incongruous that medical
opinion might be the only matter considered when a decision is made
about WWLSM
for a person with impaired decision-making
capacity.[132]
The
concerns Justice Brennan expressed about a best interests test guiding a
sterilization decision[133]
seem applicable in respect of the best interests test in the Queensland regime
for decision-making about WWLSM. It is suggested that
the arguments made in his
dissenting judgment provide compelling criticism of ‘best interests’
as a test generally. He
referred to the failure to identify relevant factors,
reliance on the subjective values of the decision-maker, absence of a hierarchy
of values, and lack of identifiable legal principle. These difficulties are
mirrored in this current analysis. He also expressed
concern that ‘best
interest’ results in an unexaminable discretion in the decision-maker. The
discretion is particularly
unexaminable in the hands of a lay substitute
decision-maker, upon whom there is no requirement to record any aspect of his or
her
decision-making process or provide reasons for decision. As noted earlier,
the best interests test has also been criticized by academics
on the basis of
its paternalism.
In conclusion, insertion of a best interest’s
consideration into the HCP seems generally at odds with the underpinning liberal
philosophy of the legislative regime, and the other Principles. It also lacks
any precise meaning, especially for lay decision-makers.
D Lack of Principle in Decision-making
It has been demonstrated that the generality of the Principles, results
in a high degree of reliance on the decision-maker’s
own values when
applying them. The result is lack of identifiable principle in decision-making.
Relevant factors are not clearly
identified, substantial reliance on subjective
value judgments of the decision-maker are necessary, there is no mechanism for
balancing
competing considerations, and overall no clearly identifiable legal
principle in operation. It is suggested that this lack of principle
in
decision-making demonstrates the inadequacy of the principles to fulfil the role
of effectively guiding decision-making about
WWLSM.
VII CONCLUSIONS
This article has considered whether the Principles are adequate to
effectively guide decision-making about WWLSM. Adequacy has been
explored having
regard to the analysis of relevant GAAT decisions and a case study. Difficulties
relating to application of the Principles
have been identified and analysed.
Essentially, three difficulties identified relate to prescription of a broad
range of non-prioritized
principles; in particular, some are irrelevant, some
lend themselves to difficulties of interpretation, and there is no mechanism
for
balancing of competing considerations. Another difficulty relates to lack of
clarity about the perspective from which application
of the principles is
required to be conducted. Numerous difficulties were identified with the best
interests consideration. Lastly,
lack of principle generally in decision-making
was identified.
The analysis has demonstrated that the Principles are
inadequate to effectively guide decision-making about WWLSM. It is suggested
that legislative reform is necessary.
Appendix One
GUARDIANSHIP AND ADMINISTRATION ACT 2000 - SCHEDULE
1 PRINCIPLES
PART 1 GENERAL PRINCIPLES
1 Presumption of capacity
An adult is presumed to have capacity for a matter.
2 Same human rights
(1) The right of all adults to the same basic human rights regardless of a particular adult's capacity must be recognised and taken into account.
(2) The importance of empowering an adult to exercise the adult's basic human rights must also be recognised and taken into account.
3 Individual value
An adult's right to respect for his or her human worth and dignity as an individual must be recognised and taken into account.
4 Valued role as member of society
(1) An adult's right to be a valued member of society must be recognised and taken into account.
(2) Accordingly, the importance of encouraging and supporting an adult to perform social roles valued in society must be taken into account.
5 Participation in community life
The importance of encouraging and supporting an adult to live a life in the general community, and to take part in activities enjoyed by the general community, must be taken into account.
6 Encouragement of self-reliance
The importance of encouraging and supporting an adult to achieve the adult's maximum physical, social, emotional and intellectual potential, and to become as self-reliant as practicable, must be taken into account.
7 Maximum participation, minimal limitations and substituted judgment
(1) An adult's right to participate, to the greatest extent practicable, in decisions affecting the adult's life, including the development of policies, programs and services for people with impaired capacity for a matter, must be recognised and taken into account.
(2) Also, the importance of preserving, to the greatest extent practicable, an adult's right to make his or her own decisions must be taken into account.
(3) So, for example--
(a) the adult must be given any necessary support,
and access to information, to enable the adult to participate in decisions
affecting
the adult's life; and
(b) to the greatest extent practicable, for
exercising power for a matter for the adult, the adult's views and wishes are to
be sought
and taken into account; and
(c) a person or other entity in
performing a function or exercising a power under this Act must do so in the way
least restrictive
of the adult's rights.
(4) Also, the principle of substituted judgment must be used so that if, from the adult's previous actions, it is reasonably practicable to work out what the adult's views and wishes would be, a person or other entity in performing a function or exercising a power under this Act must take into account what the person or other entity considers would be the adult's views and wishes.
(5) However, a person or other entity in performing a function or exercising a power under this Act must do so in a way consistent with the adult's proper care and protection.
(6) Views and wishes may be expressed orally, in writing or in another way, including, for example, by conduct.
8 Maintenance of existing supportive relationships
The importance of maintaining an adult's existing supportive relationships must be taken into account.
9 Maintenance of environment and values
(1) The importance of maintaining an adult's cultural and linguistic environment, and set of values (including any religious beliefs), must be taken into account.
(2) For an adult who is a member of an Aboriginal community or a Torres Strait Islander, this means the importance of maintaining the adult's Aboriginal or Torres Strait Islander cultural and linguistic environment, and set of values (including Aboriginal tradition116 or Island custom117), must be taken into account.
10 Appropriate to circumstances
Power for a matter should be exercised by a guardian or administrator for an adult in a way that is appropriate to the adult's characteristics and needs.
11 Confidentiality
An adult's right to confidentiality of information about the adult must be recognised and taken into account.
PART 2 HEALTH CARE PRINCIPLE
12 Health care principle
(1) The health care principle means power for a health matter, or special
health matter, for an adult should be exercised by a guardian,
the adult
guardian, the tribunal, or for a matter relating to prescribed special health
care, another entity--
(a) in the way least restrictive of the adult's
rights; and
(b) only if the exercise of power--
(i) is necessary and
appropriate to maintain or promote the adult's health or wellbeing; or
(ii)
is, in all the circumstances, in the adult's best interests.
Example of
exercising power in the way least restrictive of the adult's rights--
If there is a choice between a more or less intrusive way of meeting
an identified need, the less intrusive way should be adopted.
(2) In deciding whether the exercise of a power is appropriate, the guardian,
the adult guardian, tribunal or other entity must, to
the greatest extent
practicable--
(a) seek the adult's views and wishes and take them into
account; and
(b) take the information given by the adult's health
provider118 into account.
(3) The adult's views and wishes may be expressed--
(a) orally; or
(b) in writing, for example, in an advance health directive; or
(c) in
another way, including, for example, by conduct.
(4) The health care principle does not affect any right an adult has to refuse health care.
(5) In deciding whether to consent to special health care for an adult, the
tribunal or other entity must, to the greatest extent
practicable, seek the
views of the following person and take them into account--
(a) a guardian
appointed by the tribunal for the adult;
(b) if there is no guardian
mentioned in paragraph (a), an attorney for a health matter appointed by the
adult;
(c) if there is no guardian or attorney mentioned in paragraph (a) or
(b), the statutory health attorney for the adult.
[*] LLB (QIT), LLM (Public Law) (QUT); Public Advocate,
Queensland
[1]Guardianship
and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) ss 7-8; Powers of Attorney Act 1998
(Qld) ss 5-6A.
[2]
Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66; Powers of
Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) ss 62,
63.
[3] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
11.
[4] Powers of Attorney Act
1998 (Qld) s 76.
[5]
Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) sch 1 ss 1-11;
Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) sch 1 ss
1-11.
[6] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) sch 1 s 12; Powers of Attorney Act
1998 (Qld) sch 1 s 12.
[7]
This examination followed consideration of an Issues Paper by Ben White and
Lindy Willmott, ‘Rethinking Life-sustaining measures:
Questions for
Queensland’ (2005) Queensland University of
Technology.
[8] The
terminology of post-coma unresponsive state is now being adopted in Australia,
rather than persistent or permanent vegetative
state. See for example, National
Health and Medical Research Council, ‘Post-Coma Unresponsiveness
(Vegetative State): A Clinical
Framework for Diagnosis An Information
Paper’ (2004) Commonwealth of Australia.
[9] In October 2005, the
Attorney-General and Minister for Justice referred the guardianship legislation
to the Queensland Law Reform
Commission (QLRC) for review. The review is being
conducted in two parts:
1. the confidentiality provisions of the guardianship
laws
2. Queensland’s guardianship laws more generally.
Reform can be
considered in the guardianship review.
[10] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
6.
[11] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
5.
[12] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 79 makes it an offence to carry out
health care unless Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) or
another Act provides for it to be given without consent; consent is given under
the Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) or another Act; or it
is authorized by the Supreme Court of Queensland in its parens patriae
jurisdiction. Consent is not required
under the Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) in limited circumstances: in relation to
urgent health care: s 63; in relation to WWLSM in an acute emergency: s 63A; and
in relation to minor and uncontroversial health care: s 64. In limited
circumstances, treatment without consent is authorized under other legislation
including the Mental Health Act 2000 (Qld).
[13] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
66.
[14] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66
(1).
[15] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66
(2).
[16] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66
(3).
[17] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66
(4).
[18] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66 (5). Note that the statutory health
attorney regime is provided for in the Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld)
ss 62, 63.
[19] Powers of
Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) s 63: 63 Who is the statutory health attorney
(1) For a health matter, an adult's statutory health attorney is the
first, in listed order, of the following people who is readily
available and
culturally appropriate to exercise power for the matter—
(a) a
spouse of the adult if the relationship between the adult and the spouse is
close and continuing;
(b) a person who is 18 years or more and who
has the care of the adult and is not a paid carer for the adult;
(c)
a person who is 18 years or more and who is a close friend or relation of the
adult and is not a paid carer for the adult.
(2) If no-one listed in
subsection (1) is readily available and culturally appropriate to exercise power
for a matter, the adult guardian
is the adult's statutory health attorney for
the matter.
(3) Without limiting who is a person who has the care of
the adult, for this section, a person has the care of an adult if the person--
(a) provides domestic services and support to the adult; or
(b) arranges for the adult to be provided with domestic services and
support.
(4) If an adult resides in an institution (for example, a
hospital, nursing home, group home, boarding-house or hostel) at which the
adult
is cared for by another person, the adult--
(a) is not, merely
because of this fact, to be regarded as being in the care of the other person;
and
(b) remains in the care of the person in whose care the adult was
immediately before residing in the institution.
[20A] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
42.
[20] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 11; Powers of Attorney Act 1998
(Qld) s 76. For the purposes of this article, it is assumed that
there is no significant difference between the requirement to
‘apply’
the Principles as opposed to ‘comply with’ them.
[21] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) sch 2, s 5(2); Powers of Attorney
Act 1998 (Qld) sch 2 s 5(2). Note also, GMP is GMP in Australia for the
medical profession, in accordance with recognized medical standards and
practices and
recognized ethical standards: Guardianship and Administration
Act 2000 (Qld) sch 2, s 5B and Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld)
sch 2 s 5B.
[22]
Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
63A(1).
[23] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
63A(2).
[24] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
63A(4).
[25] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66A. Note also, exercise of power for a
health matter will not be effective to give consent if the health provider is
aware that the adult
objects to the health care, unless the adult has no real
understanding of what it involves and why its needed, and it is likely to
cause
the adult no distress or temporary distress is outweighed by the benefit to the
adult: Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 67. This
exception applies to decisions about WWLSM. Note that Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 67(3), specifically excludes the operation
of the exception in s 67(2), where an adult objects, in relation to health care
for the removal of tissue for donation and participation in special medical
research,
experimental health care, or approved clinical research, but not other
types of health care.
It is noteworthy that similar to the common law position, under the
guardianship regime, an AHD can be made by an adult while competent.
Under an
AHD, a direction to WWLSM can only operate in limited circumstances: Powers
of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) s 36, s 36(2). Essentially, it can operate
only where the adult has an incurable/irreversible terminal condition and is
expected to die within one
year; where the adult is in a persistent vegetative
state; where the adult is permanently unconscious; where the adult’s
injury
or illness is so severe that there is no reasonable prospect the adult
will recover to the extent that LSM will not be required to
sustain life: s
36(2)(a). Additionally, for a direction to operate about WW of ANH, the LSM must
be contrary to GMP: s 36(2)(b). In all cases, there must be no reasonable
prospect that the adult will regain capacity for health matters: s 36(2)(c).
These circumstances are narrower recognition of autonomy than the common law
allows. Because of amendments to the guardianship regime
in 2001 which are
discussed in Part IV of this article (and by virtue of which WWLSM became
‘health care’, despite the specific provision in Powers of
Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) s 36(2) (b) and Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66A [which does not refer to Guardianship
and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 66 (2)], it now appears that for a
direction in an AHD to be effective to WWLSM commencement or continuation of the
LSM must be inconsistent
with good medical practice as a result of the
definition of health care.
[26] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) sch 2, s 5A; Powers of Attorney Act 1998
(Qld) sch 2 s 5A.
[27] Re F (Mental Patient:
Sterilisation) [1991] UKHL 1; [1990] 2 AC 1, 72 E; Airedale NHS Trust v. Bland
[1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789, 864C; Re A (Children) [2000] Lloyd’s Rep. Med 425,
494. See also, discussion about the history of development of autonomy as a
central idea in medical
law, for example, D Morgan and K Veitch, ‘Being Ms
B:B, Autonomy and the Nature of Legal Regulation’ [2004] Sydney Law
Review 6.
[28A] Treatment without consent
may leave a health provider liable in criminal and civil law: Sec, Dept of
Health & Community Services v JWB (‘Marion’s Case’)
[1992] HCA 15; (1992) 106 ALR 385, 392 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ).
[28] Competent patients decide
for themselves whether to accept or refuse recommended medical treatment, not
their doctors. The right
of a competent person to refuse treatment has been
recognized in a variety of jurisdictions including the United States
(Schloendorff v. Society of New York Hospital 105 NE 92 (NY) 1914);
Canada (Nancy B v. Hotel-Dieu de Quebec (1992) 86 DLR (4th)
385); Ciarlariello v. Schactr (1993) 100 DLR (4th) 609 (SCC);
Malette v. Schulman (1990) 67 DLR (4th) 321); New Zealand (s
11 Bill of Rights; Re G [1997] 2 NZLR 201; Auckland Area Health Board
v. Attorney General [1993] 1 NZLR 235); and the United Kingdom (Re B
(Adult refusal of medical treatment) [2002] EWHC 429; [2002] 2 All ER 449; Re C (Adult
refusal of medical treatment) [1994] 1 All ER 81; Airedale NHS Trust v.
Bland [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789; Re T (Adult: refusal of medical treatment)
[1992] EWCA Civ 18; [1992] 3 WLR 782. In Australia, there has been little judicial confirmation
of the common law position. However, it appears to have been implicitly
accepted
by the High Court in Secretary, Department of Health and Family Services v.
JWB and SMB [1992] HCA 15; (1992) 106 ALR 385 (‘Marion’s Case’) 390, 392
(where the majority endorsed the principle of bodily inviolability) and by the
Queensland Supreme Court in Re Bridges [2001] Qd R 574. Ambrose J (when
declaring that an adult did not have capacity to make decisions about health
matters,) appears to have accepted a
common law right to refuse treatment.
[29] Airedale NHS Trust v.
Bland [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789. Lord Goff quoted with approval Superintendent of
Belchertown State School v Saikerwicz [1977] 370 NE 2d 417, 428 in which the
Supreme Court of Massachusetts said: To presume that the incompetent person must always be subjected to what many
rational and intelligent persons may decline is to downgrade the status of the
incompetent person by placing a lesser value on his
intrinsic human worth and
vitality.
[30A] The focus of the
cases has been on the right to choose between offered treatments and refuse
treatment: the common law does not
allow a patient to compel a heath provider to
provide treatment which the health provider does not consider clinically
appropriate,
does not serve any therapeutic purpose or is illegal: Auckland
Area Health Board v. Attorney-General [1993] 1 NZLR 235, 253-4
(Thomas J); Airedale NHS Trust v. Bland [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789, 864C (Lord
Goff) ; Re J (A Minor) (Child in Care: Medical treatment) [1993]
Fam 15; and Burke v General Medical Council [2005] EWCA Civ 1003. See
also, L Skene, Law and Medical Practice Rights, Duties, Claims and
Defences (LexisNexis Butterworths, 2nd ed, 2004) 86-7; A
Hockton, The Law of Consent to Medical Treatment (Sweet &
Maxwell, 2002) 15; L Skene, ‘Withholding and withdrawing treatment in
South Australia when patients, parents or
guardians insist that treatment must
be continued’ [2003] AdelLawRw 17; (2003) 24 Adelaide Law Review 161, 167-71.
However, a court may declare it unlawful for treatment to be ceased, thus
indirectly compelling treatment: Northridge v Central Sydney Area Health
Service [2000] NSWSC 1241 (Unreported, O’Keefe J, 17 January 2001).
[30] Re T (Adult: refusal of
medical treatment) [1992] EWCA Civ 18; [1992] 3 WLR 782. See also discussion about common law
advance directives in Lindy Willmott, Ben White & Michelle Howard,
‘Refusing Advance
Refusals: Advance Directives and Life-sustaining Medical
Treatment’ [2006] MelbULawRw 7; (2006) 30 Melbourne University Law Review 211, 215-217.
[31] Re F (Mental Patient:
Sterilisation) [1991] UKHL 1; [1990] 2 AC
1.
[32] [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC
789.
[33] For example[1992] UKHL 5; , [1993] AC
789, 872 Lord Goff referred to the patient’s wishes; 869 Lord Goff, 883-4
Lord Wilkinson-Browne referred to lack of dignity from
invasive
measures.
[34] [1993] 1 NZLR
235.
[35] [1997] 2 NZLR
201.
[36] [2004] NSWSC 1061.
[37] See, for example, Re MB
(Medical Treatment) [1997] 2 FLR 426, 439 Butler-Schloss LJ considered best
interests is not limited to best medical interests; Re A (Male Sterilisation)
[2001] 1 FLR 549, 555 Butler-Schloss P considered best interests includes
medical, emotional and all welfare issues; In re S (Adult Patient:
Sterilisation) [2001] Fam 15, 30 Thorpe J considered best interests includes
welfare considerations far wider than
medical.
[38] Wyatt v
Portsmouth Hospital NHS [2005] EWCA Civ 277; [2005] All ER (D) 107 (Oct).
This approach has been subsequently endorsed. See for example, An NHS
Trust v MB (a child) [2006] EWHC 507 (Fam) (15 March 2006) and Re K (a
minor) [2006] EWHC 1007 (Fam) (9 May
2006).
[39] However,
Northridge v Central Sydney Area Health Service [2000] NSWSC 1241; (2000) 50 NSWLR 549
involved an application in the parens patriae jurisdiction to compel treatment
in circumstances where treating health providers intended
to WWLSM.
[40] [2004] NSWSC
1061(Unreported, Howie J, 11 November 2004). For critical comment about this
decision, see B White and L Willmott, ‘Futility, Finances and Families:
decisions to withdraw
life-sustaining medical treatment’ (2004) 13(4)
Australian Health Law Bulletin 37; and T Bowen and A Saxton, ‘New
developments in the law-withholding and withdrawal of medical treatment’
(2006) 14(5) Australian Health Law Bulletin
57.
[41] Messiha v South
East Health [2004] NSWSC 1061(Unreported, Howie J, 11 November 2004) 6.
[42] Airedale NHS Trust v
Bland [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789. Lords Goff and Wilkinson-Browne suggest that parliament
should decide the broad issues raised by the case. R (On the Application of
Burke) v General Medical Council [2004] EWHC 1879 (Admin) (Unreported, Munby
J, 30 July 2004) Munby J considered that although best interests is the test, it
is a poor basis for decision-making
in this grave and difficult area.
[43] JK Mason, RA McCall Smith
and GT Laurie, Law and Medical Ethics (LexisNexis, 6th ed,
2002) 518, 522 refer to the paternalism of best interests as a concept, and the
medicalisation of the approach
to termination of treatment; Hockton, above ni
30A, 107 suggests that in Bland’s Case, their Lordships generally
appear to broadly equate the tests of best interests and the Bolam
principle (the latter was established in negligence cases, and is to the effect
that a doctor must act in accordance with a competent
and responsible body of
medical opinion: Bolam v Friern Hospital Management Committee [1957] 1
WLR 582. Cf J Keown, ‘Restoring Moral and Intellectual Shape to the Law
After Bland’ (1997) 113 The Law Quarterly Review 481, and
‘Beyond Bland: a critique of the BMA guidance on withdrawing and
withholding medical treatment’ (2000) 20 Legal Studies 66 who
focuses on problems with ethical principles articulated as relevant, namely
sanctity of life, when quality of life appears to
have been considered by some
of their Lordships as the basis for concluding that Bland had no interests in
being kept alive.
[44] Sec, Dept of Health
& Community Services v JWB (‘Marion’s Case’) [1992] HCA 15; (1992)
106 ALR 385, 418-23 (High Court of Australia, Brennan J (dissenting)). See also
Ian Freckleton and Bebe Loff, ‘Health law and human rights’
in David
Kinley (ed), Human Rights in Australian Law (1998) 267,
281.
[45] The text of the
Principles in the PAA is in similar terms. However, it includes
references to enduring documents and attorneys. The principles in the GAA
include an additional sub-section in HCP 12 (5) which is to be applied when
consent is given to special health
care.
[46] Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 8 October 1997, 3684 (Denver
Beanland, Attorney-General and Minister for
Justice).
[47] This principle is
contained in the GPs: Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) sch
1 s 7(4), Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) sch 1 s
7(4).
[48] Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 8 October 1997, 3684, 3690
(Denver Beanland, Attorney-General and Minister for
Justice).
[49] Guardianship
and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) as passed No 8, 2000: ss 65, 68; schedule
2 ss 6-7, 16.
[50] Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 11 April 2000, 785 (Matthew
Foley, Attorney-General and Minister for
Justice).
[51] Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 17 October 2001, 2908-2910
(Rodney Welford).
[52]
Explanatory Notes, Guardianship and Administration and Other Acts Amendment
Bill 2001(Qld) 6 state that the amendment acknowledges that health care
can be in a person’s best interests, but not promote or maintain
health,
for example, by not interfering with the natural processes of dying by the
futile administration of LSM. Previously, consent
could only be given for health
care which was to maintain or promote an adult’s health or well-being.
[53] For example see,
Queensland, Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 6 December 2001,
4330 (Kevin Lingard); 4332-4334 (Ronan Lee); 4334-43350 (Liz
Cunningham).
[54] Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 6 December 2001, 4335-4337
(Rodney Welford).
[55] [2003]
QGAAT 13.
[56] [2006] QGAAT
26.
[57] [2006] QGAAT 26,
[69-70].
[58] [2006] QGAAT 26,
[72-6].
[59] [2006] QGAAT 26,
[88-9].
[60] [2006] QGAAT 26,
[92-3].
[61] There is a
statement that the Principles particularly relevant to WWLSM have been
considered in L Willmott and B White, ‘Charting
a course through difficult
legislative waters: Tribunal decisions on life-sustaining measures’ (2005)
12(1) J Law Med 441; however, GAAT does not provide it’s own
rationale for applying only some of the Principles: [2006] QGAAT 26, [68].
[62] GAAT considered that once a
matter was referred to the Tribunal for consent, s 66A (which applies to
decisions made under s 66(3)-66(5)
and which provides that consent to WWLSM can
not operate unless the health provider considers commencement or continuation
would
be inconsistent with GMP) does not apply: [2003] QGAAT 13, [49-52]. With
respect, GAATs comments that s 66A does not apply to decisions of the Tribunal
seem misplaced, since the Tribunals
decision must be made under s 66(3).
[63] [2003] QGAAT 13, [55]. See
also B White and L Willmott, ‘Will You Do As I Ask? Compliance with
Instructions about Health Care in Queensland’
(2004) 4 (87) Queensland
University of Technology Law Journal 77,
82.
[64] [2003] QGAAT 13,
[53].
[65] [1993] 1 NZLR
235.
[66] [1997] 2 NZLR
201.
[67] [2003] QGAAT 13,
[56-62].
[68] Ibid
[62].
[69] Ibid [63-64].
Although the right of the patient to receive ordinary treatment and right to
refuse health could be an application
of GP 2 and GP 2 in combination with HCP
12(4) respectively, it is not referred to as such an application.
[70] Ibid
[67].
[71] Ibid
[68].
[72] GAAT had made
findings of fact which did not include any reference to MC being a private
person, but included other matters which
could have supported this application
of the law, but which were not referred to: [2003] QGAAT 13, [46].
[73] [2003] QGAAT 13,
[68].
[74] DC Pearce and RS
Geddes, Statutory Interpretation in Australia (Butterworths, 5th ed,
2001) [4.17- 4.35] explain the syntactical presumptions applying in statutory
interpretation, including expressio uniusest exclusio alterius (express
reference to one matter indicates that other matters are excluded): [4.26].
Where legislation includes provisions about
similar matters in different terms,
there is an intention to deal with them differently. Even if this
presumption was not considered applicable, an interpretation of the plain words,
would seem to support HCP 12(2) as relevant
only to HCP 12(1)(b)(i), because it
refers to determining whether an exercise of power is appropriate.
Despite comments in the Explanatory Notes to the Guardianship and
Administration Bill 2001 (Qld), that the adult’s wishes would
still be
highly relevant to a substitute decision-makers deliberations about best
interests because of HCP 12(2), regard would not
be had to the Explanatory Notes
to provide an interpretation, unless the provision was ambiguous or obscure; or
the ordinary meaning
was manifestly absurd or unreasonable: Acts
Interpretation Act 1954 (Qld) s 14B.
[75] [2003] QGAAT 13,
[69].
[76] Ibid [62].
[77] It is acknowledged that the
apparent priority given to exercising power in the circumstances, in the
adult’s best interests,
recognizes that power for a health matter should
be exercised in accordance with HCP (1)(b). That is, only if either HCP
12(1)(b)(i) it is necessary and appropriate to maintain or promote the
adult’s health or wellbeing; or HCP 12(1)(b)(ii)
it is, in all the
circumstances, in the adult’s best interests. Reliance on best interests
suggests that GAAT considered that
consent to WWLSM is not considered health
care necessary and appropriate to maintain or promote the adult’s health
or well-being,
but may be considered in an adult’s best interests. The
principle suggests that if it does not fall within (1)(b)(i) or (ii)
then it
cannot be given. This may have been thought to accord some priority to this
principle over others. However, it is argued
that this is an inadequate basis
for according priority to the principle, since the legislation/principles do not
provide for prioritization
and GAAT was required to apply the Principles.
GAATs possible basis for according priority to the principle that exercise of
power should be least restrictive of
the adult’s rights, over other
principles, is less obvious (despite the Principles requiring exercise power in
the way least
restrictive of an adult’s rights).
[78] Re MC [2003] QGAAT
13, [70] seems suggestive of this
possibility.
[79] Ibid [62-3],
[67-9].
[80] Ibid [67].
[81] This seems to accord
broadly with the arguments of J Keown, ‘Restoring Moral and Intellectual
Shape to the Law after Bland’
(1997) 113 The Law Quarterly
Review 481, where he argues that the sanctity of life was overlooked for
quality of life interpretations in Bland’s Case. See also, L
Skene, ‘The Shiavo and Korp cases: Conceptualising end-of-life
decision-making’ (2005) 13 Journal of Law and Medicine 223, 224
where she considers possible alternate constructs in end-of life decision-making
applied in the cases which were the subject
of the article: these may be
summarized broadly as a health law construct (the person is a terminally ill
patient with no hope of
recovery who is receiving futile treatment) and a
disability construct (the person is a person with a disability whose interests
must be protected). Skene argues in favour of the health law
construct.
[82] In this matter,
it is acknowledged that the facts supported a substituted judgment that MC would
refuse the treatment (and later
one was made), but when the principle was
considered this was not discussed. See [2003] QGAAT 13, [63], [68].
[83] [2000] QGAAT
2.
[84] Ibid [79-80] Factually,
the adult’s health crisis had passed; antibiotics may or may not be a LSM
in the future depending
on the circumstances.
[85] GAAT considered that HCP
12(1) was really the same as the common law in respect of WWLSM, since treatment
to promote the health
and well-being must be read to mean that the health care
would be of some benefit to the person, and therefore, in the adult’s
best
interests: [2000] QGAAT 2, [67-9]. It considered that common law principles must
be applicable, and that this seemed to accord broadly with the Report, since
it
was not intended that the scheme include WWLSM: [2000] QGAAT 2, [50-1]. The
common law was explored and applied, including Bland’s Case: [2000]
QGAAT 2, [52-7], [60-2].
[86] At
this time, consenting to WWLSM was special health care, and it appeared that the
HCP was as a matter of strict interpretation
not applicable: Re RWG
[2000] QGAAT 2, [42-51].
[87]
[2000] QGAAT 2, [76].
[88] Ibid
[84-8].
[89] Ibid
[52-68].
[90] Ibid
[76].
[91] Ibid [84].
[92] [2002] QGAAT 1.
[93] Ibid [118-128, 138, 154-8,
163].
[94] Ibid
[160].
[95] Ibid
[164-5].
[96] Ibid
[166].
[97] Ibid
[167].
[98] Ibid
[168].
[99] Ibid [169-172].
Nursing staff considered TM’s level of alertness indicated that she was
not close to dying.
[100]
Ibid [164-5].
[101] Ibid
[167].
[102] It should be
noted that there is no requirement upon the health provider to give a
decision-maker a copy of the
principles.
[103] See also
above n 82 in relation to possible alternate
constructs.
[104] It is noted
that for adults with certain cultural backgrounds, this may be relevant to a
decision about WWLSM.
[105]
That is, considerations which do not constitute
rights.
[106] That is,
considerations which do constitute
rights.
[107] Re
Bridges [2001] Qd R
574.
[108] It is noted that
other confidentiality provisions would protect an adult’s private medical
information in circumstances when
the decision is made by GAAT or the Adult
Guardian: Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s 112, s 249; or
by an attorney: Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) s
74.
[109] [2006] QGAAT 26.
[110] [2003] QGAAT
13.
[111]
Ibid.
[112] Ibid
[68].
[113] As noted earlier
in Part IV B of this article, until 2001, WWLSM was defined as special health
care.
[114] Re RWG
[200] QGAAT 2, [84].
[115]
Re TM [2002] QGAAT 1,
[160].
[116] [2003] QGAAT 13.
[117] [2006] QGAAT
26.
[118] Ibid
[69-71].
[119] [2003] QGAAT
13, [67]. See also discussion above n
82.
[120] [2002] QGAAT 1,
[59], [80], [134-142].
[121]
[2003] QGAAT 13, [63-4].
[122] [2002] QGAAT
1.
[123] Ibid [164-5]. Later,
it considers the adults right to refuse health care in accordance with HCP 12(4)
and makes a substituted judgment
about this, but does not appear to consider it
relevant to the consideration under HCP 12(1)(a): [167-8].
[124] [2003] QGAAT 13. It is
acknowledged that although GAAT did not articulate reasons for doing so, it does
not appear to have prioritized amongst the
Principles in order to overcome the
dilemma discussed in this part.
[125] Guardianship and
Administration Act 2000 (Qld) s
11.
[126] Powers of
Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) s
76.
[127] White and Willmott,
above n 64, 82-3.
[128] Some
support for this proposition seems to flow from the second reading speech in
respect of the PAA to the effect that because of the principle of
substituted judgment which must be applied in decision-making, where possible an
attorney
should make the decision the adult would have made if able: Queensland,
Parliamentary Debates, Legislative Assembly, 8 October 1997, 3684, 3690
(Denver Beanland, Attorney-General and Minister for Justice). However, it must
be
acknowledged that at the time of these assertions, decisions about WWLSM were
not contemplated as discussed in Part IV B of this
article.
[129] For example, in
Re TM [2002] QGAAT 1, [89-91] there was evidence that the adult had
strong views about the medical profession and patient autonomy.
[130] See above n
30A.
[131] Re HG [2006]
QGAAT 26, [89].
[132A] See
above n 13.
[132] As noted in
Part III of this article, the common law has increasingly recognised that a best
interests assessment should include wide considerations.
Cf L Skene,’The
Schiavo and Korp cases: Conceptualising end-of-life decision-making’
(2005) 13 Journal of Law and Medicine 223 who suggests essentially that
only medical opinion is relevant where treatment is considered medically
futile.
[133]
Marion’s Case [1992] HCA 15; (1992) 106 ALR 385.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2006/11.html