![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
![]() |
A DISCUSSION OF ‘REGRET’ AS A
MODEL FOR ETHICAL DISCOURSE GENERALLY AND IN THE CONTEXT OF THE PROVISION OF
LIFE SUSTAINING
MEASURES IN QUEENSLAND
(OR:
‘WHY ARE THERE NO ETHICAL CHILD
PRODIGIES?’) [1]
MARK W.
SAYERS [*]
The child prodigy has long been standard fare for human interest television
shows: 5 year olds that play Mozart sonatas; 6 year olds
that have memorized all
the biographical details of every American president; and one memorable prodigy
I particularly recall who,
as a 4 year old, could recite in either chronological
or alphabetical order all the Oscar winners for best male lead. But there is
one
notable omission from the pantheon of prodigies: to date there has not been an 8
year old prodigy purporting to be a bioethicist.
As with chimpanzees and
parrots, it may be possible to train children to play pianos and recite litanies
but a child prodigy whose
speciality is ethics is something we may never live to
see. Of course, we all look forward to that great day when a precocious child
takes to the television screen and recites the provisions of the Guardianship
and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) as amended and consolidated with
ancillary regulations, but would we want to appoint that child a substituted
decision-maker
under the Act? In short, in the event of our own incapacity and
lack of any agent duly appointed by ourselves, would we want such
a child to
make a decision about refusing us life-sustaining measures or withdrawing such
measures from us?
Perhaps one reason why the juvenile ethical prodigy is
unprecedented (if not actually impossible) is because the skill or art that
is
ethical decision-making requires something more of the decision-maker than the
mere ability to identify the relevant heuristic
framework, mode of discourse or
(as is the case with statutory substituted decision-making) spectrum of
statutory criteria relevant
to end of life decisions such as to refuse or
withdraw life-sustaining measures. Perhaps experience and maturity, the bitter
tears
of frustration or regret which often flow from confronting our limitations
in a world containing many harsh realities, are an equally
necessary if albeit
also insufficient criterion for ethical decision-making?
This last
question as to the role of experience, maturity, frustration and regret in
ethical decision-making generally has specific
relevance to decisions touching
on the refusal or withdrawal of life-sustaining measures by a substituted
decision-maker. Due to
the likely finality of its consequences, the comity or
fellow-feeling between the decision-maker and the impaired individual for
whom
the decision is taken, and the ever increasing range of medical possibilities in
the area, it is difficult to conceive of a
more poignant and challenging ethical
decision. The poignancy and challenge arises if only because of the many
speculative, ‘what
if’ and ‘if only’ type questions that
arise in these scenarios which clash against the blunt, intransigent physical
facts of the scenario. It is understandable in just such a scenario for the
substituted decision-maker and/or many of the people
in the constellation of
individuals affected by the decision, to seek some measure of comfort and
reassurance that the decision (whatever
it may have been) was ultimately morally
as well as legally correct.
The argument presented in this paper is that
it may be the case that a certain measure of discomfort and lack of assurance is
both
an unavoidable concomitant of decisions made in this scenario as well as a
hallmark of a properly conducted, ethical decision. According
to this argument,
when involved in substituted decision-making in these scenarios, if we seek the
composure and the confidence, the
sense that we are unassailably right, that is
commonplace amongst child prodigies then it is possible that we have
misconstrued ethical
decision-making in general and the responsibilities of
substituted ethical decision-making in particular.
Due to my professional
and personal experiences working within hospital chaplaincy and ethics advisory
groups, I have a keen interest
in the area of substituted decision-making
especially in the context of end of life decisions regarding the refusal or
withdrawal
of life-sustaining measures (colloquially if inaccurately lumped
under the umbrella of euthanasia issues). Some excellent work in
respect of the
Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld) has recently been done by
way of a discussion about proposed law reforms on this topic in Queensland where
I practice and, accordingly,
aspects of the paper outlining those proposed
reforms provide the starting point (but only the starting point) for the
discussion
in this article. However, whilst the starting point for the
discussion is particular to Queensland, the questions and discussion
which
follow in this article are hopefully of more general application.
Of
particular importance to the argument in this article is how to advance the law
reform discussion on this topic by reference to
the insights gained from the
particular understanding of ethics proposed here: namely, that if experience,
maturity, frustration
and even regret (as narrowly understood in this context
and explained in more detail in the course of the article) are possible
hallmarks
attesting to the integrity of, for instance, ethical substituted
decision-making, then how can that phenomenon be accommodated in
the law
covering that subject?
Hence, several short points arise from my initial
observation about the absence of ethical child prodigies and those several short
points are the subject of discussion in this article, to wit:
- What do we learn from the
observation that there are no ethical child prodigies?
- What does the general absence of
such a phenomenon tell us about
ethics?
- Guided by those insights,
what might follow by way of law reform in respect of, for instance, the
Guardianship and Administration Act 2000 (Qld)?
I WHAT DO WE LEARN FROM THE OBSERVATION THAT THERE ARE NO
ETHICAL CHILD PRODIGIES?
As was noted in the introduction to this article, the starting point for
discussion are the proposed law reforms relevant to the issue
of the refusal or
withdrawal of life-sustaining measures in respect of the current law covering
that subject in Queensland. This
starting point is adopted mostly because it is
a prominent issue in the jurisdiction where I practice. However, this starting
point
is also adopted because, with the greatest respect to all concerned,
various aspects of the Issues Paper risk overlooking some of
the potential merit
that arises from my initial observations about the peculiar character of ethical
discourse which character is
highlighted by the lack of child prodigies in the
field. A convenient way to illustrate that possibility is by reference to the
most
recent Law Reform Commission paper on the subject.
In Queensland, a
number of law reforms in respect of both the Guardianship and Administration
Act 2002 (Qld) and the Enduring Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) are
currently under consideration. A major factor in that process of law
reform is the document authored in February 2005 by Associate Professor Lindy
Willmott and Dr
Ben White, both of the Faculty of Law at the Queensland
University of Technology, entitled Rethinking Life – Sustaining
Measures: Questions for
Queensland.[2] This was an Issues
Paper prepared in collaboration with the Queensland Adult Guardian and
Palliative Care Queensland. This article
does not pretend to provide a
comprehensive response to that Issues Paper. Rather, I simply propose using some
of the building blocks
which I identify in that Issues Paper the better to
illustrate my approach to two
issues:
- The first concerns the law
reform of both euthanasia generally and the issue of whether to provide (or
continue to provide) life-sustaining
measures in
particular;[3]
and
- The second concerns one aspect
of methodology in ethical discourse.
Of these two concerns it is the
treatment of the latter issue, relevant to methodology in ethical discourse,
which is fundamental
to this article and hence provides the narrow analysis
offered here of the much wider Issues Paper. Accordingly, by way of preliminary
remarks, I need to identify the building blocks I am borrowing from the Issues
Paper. These particular building blocks are selected
because of their potential,
if too glibly or uncritically applied, to overlook the kinds of insights about
ethical decision-making
that have already been identified in this article.
The first of the building blocks that I borrow from the Issues Paper is
what, for convenience, I will term the ‘consent proposition’.
At a number of places in the Issues Paper, the working assumption is adopted
that an adult who enjoys full legal capacity has the
right to give consent to
the withdrawing or withholding of life-sustaining measures either at the time or
in futuro.[4] The justification
for that proposition is identified as a melange of statutory rights and maxims
drawn from the common
law.[5]
For present purposes,
this article does not purport to take issue with the prudence or otherwise of
this consent proposition either
as a matter of ethical theory or its accuracy as
a proposition of law. Rather, for the purposes of this article, this consent
proposition will be assumed as a given for the sake of the argument in
order to arrive at a consideration of how best to respect the statutory
right
which it underpins. This statutory right -not a right that is postulated in the
Issues Paper as a self-evident, natural or
inherent human right- this statutory
right underpinned by the consent proposition can be understood by reference to a
number of different
paradigms.
A Rawlsian–type approach to
jurisprudence and human rights might understand the consent proposition
as part of the social contract whereby a society respects and confers protection
on the full-informed
and freely-made choices of adult
citizens.[6] A Dworkinian-type
approach to jurisprudence might justify the consent proposition by
arguing that the individual’s rights to autonomy and self-actualisation
trump the interests of the broader
society.[7] A natural rights-type
approach to jurisprudence as typified by Finnis, could also arguably be adapted
to support the consent proposition.[8]
In such an adaptation, one might argue there are circumstances when it is
self-evident that the basic human good of an individual
can no longer be served
by refusing to withdraw or, alternatively, fail to withhold life-sustaining
measures.
The next step in this article is to take the consent
proposition, which is one of the building blocks borrowed here from the Issues
Paper, and join it with another building block which I will term the
‘reasoned decision-making proposition’.
The reasoned
decision-making proposition arises out of the Queensland legislation’s
statutory criteria for identifying the best
interests of a person who is the
subject of a statutory power exercised by a substituted decision-maker. In the
final analysis, those
criteria ultimately collapse into a quasi-exercise in
utilitarian calculus.[9] This is so
because the decision-making in respect of the refusal or withdrawal of
life-sustaining measures revolves around the schedules
attached to the relevant
legislation, such as the Powers of Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) and
Guardianship and Administration Act 2002 (Qld) The first schedule
to each of those Acts provide the statutory criteria for an exercise that is
reminiscent of at least the
methodology of utilitarian calculus inasmuch as the
decision in a particular case is made by reference to a constellation of primary
and secondary considerations that are intended to identify the best interests of
a particular person.
As previously noted in this article, if these two
propositions (the consent and reasoned decision-making propositions) are applied
too glibly or uncritically,[10] one
risks setting up a form of ethical decision-making, whether by a substituted
decision-maker or otherwise, which is of a kind
that might lapse into a form of
discourse that is (unintentionally) amenable to the supposed ethical
child-prodigy performing the
role of, say, substituted decision-maker. This is
because if the criteria for reasoned decision-making are identified as a
necessary
if not sole criterion for fully informed consent, then it arguably
follows that adherence to or facility with the former justifies
or validates the
latter.
By way of illustration, let us adopt in a very simplistic way the
earlier reference to substituted decision-making under either of
the Acts as a
quasi-exercise in utilitarian calculus. A simplistic approach to that
proposition begs the following syllogism:
1. Calculus is a branch of
mathematics;
2. Child prodigies are a common enough occurrence in
mathematics;
3. Therefore a child mathematical prodigy could apply this
exercise in quasi-utilitarian calculus in the role of substituted
decision-maker.
This is an obviously flawed syllogism, but why and how?
The thought of a child prodigy fulfilling the role of substituted decision-maker
is counter-intuitive: but why? If adults of full legal capacity can, at least as
a matter of law:
- Consent to
the future withdrawal or withholding of life-sustaining measures; and/or
- Can either give guidelines to
substituted decision-makers or appoint substituted decision-makers would will be
guided by the relevant
legislation;
and
- If the fact that a greater
number of factors (identified in the relevant legislation) are suggestive of one
result over another is
of itself of significance;
Then why cannot a child
prodigy, one who is capable of both reciting the relevant legislation and
parsing the facts with the legislation,
act as the substituted decision-maker?
The answer, obviously, is the varying significance to be placed on a
given factor across a range of cases: the substituted decision-makers
across a
range of cases might identify the same relevant statutory criteria but come to
different conclusions because of the different
significance or weight of those
identical statutory criteria across the range of cases. As accessible and
transparent as the reasoned
decision-making process is intended to be under the
legislation, it does not follow that this process is merely a question of adding
up the number of factors for and against every possible
decision.[11]
The
self-evident character of this last proposition is reinforced by the analogous
consideration that whilst it is conceivable that
a child prodigy could memorize
and recite every historical fact on record about Australian history, it does not
follow that such
a child would be entrusted with the interpretation either of
that history or of current events in light of the past whether as the
holder of
a professorial chair in history or as a political commentator.
II WHAT DOES THE ABSENCE OF CHILD ETHICAL PRODIGIES TELL US
ABOUT ETHICS?
Notwithstanding the obvious character of the reason why a child prodigy could
not be a proper substituted decision-maker, it is argued
that a lesson
nonetheless emerges for methodology in ethical discourse (especially as it
intersects with legislation) from the question
that I have posed in that regard.
The entry point to understanding that lesson is an understanding of the purposes
of legislation
of this kind and the purposes to which it is put. This entry
point suggests itself because of what is argued to be a fundamental
misconception in the approach of the relevant legislation.
The relevant
fundamental misconception is that substituted decision-making is primarily if
not exclusively an exercise in law, ethics,
logic or decision-making
before the fact.
In the hurly burly of courtrooms and hospitals,
it is understandable that this fundamental misconception should arise. It
arguably
arises because ethicists, lawyers, health care providers and (via
the elected Parliament) the entire body politic seeks to provide, in
advance, guidelines to assist decision-makers in difficult situations
at times
of crisis. Either from the fruit of our collective experience over time or from
some identified and agreed first principles,
we try to provide guidance
to those decision-makers.
However, the sad reality is that the governing
authorities of hospitals, the professional negligence insurers who cover health
care
providers, the lawyers who advise aggrieved relatives, also all look to
those guidelines for something more than mere guidance for
decision-makers. They
also look to those guidelines for legitimacy: in short, to test whether a
particular decision was lawful or whether it is variously actionable as a breach
of the legislation;
actionable as a lapse of duty in tort or contract; or, and
perhaps ultimately, an offence under the criminal law.
Accordingly, it
follows that reform of tort law relevant to medical negligence would likely have
a huge influence on the content of
euthanasia law reform generally and
substituted decision-making in respect of withholding or withdrawing
life-sustaining measures
in particular. This is because reform of tort law on
this point could better distinguish between the guidance and legitimacy tests.
For if governing authorities of hospitals, the professional negligence insurers
who cover health care providers and the lawyers who
advise aggrieved relatives
were to find that a reformed tort law better identified, first, the duties of a
given health carer to
provide or withhold life-sustaining measures and, second,
the criteria for best practice or such like in health care generally, then
fewer
people would turn to the hospital ethicist for
advice.[12]
In short: I
surmise that the fear,[13] even if
an unspoken or unconscious fear of being sued plays a disproportionate role in
producing what might be regarded as conservative
approaches to providing
life-sustaining measures in circumstances where no advance health directive or
substituted decision-maker
is readily available. Hence the various professionals
involved turn to the ethicist, the doctor or the lawyer and say: In this
situation,
what should we do? Implicit to which enquiry is the question:
before the fact, please assure us that we are doing at least that which
is legal if not also that which is right?
It is regretfully argued that
the methodology best suited to ethical discourse does not generally permit of
such reassurance. This
is because the question, at least as posed in this
manner, is reminiscent of scientific method (a phrase that is employed here,
only
for the purposes of clarifying the argument, in a pejorative sense). It is
an analytic question which assumes that past experience
or first principles
(perhaps derived from experience but, in the circumstances this discussion,
derived from the schedules to the
legislation) can be used to correctly identify
before the fact an appropriate result in the circumstances of a
particular case. It is a question which also assumes that, for the purposes
of
this discussion, the schedules to the legislation and/or the caselaw
interpreting past applications of the criteria in those schedules,
can serve as
a heuristic framework to identify at least the legal if not the right thing to
do.
It would be tempting to avoid the challenge of these questions by
making a strong distinction between the legal thing to do (which is
likely reasonably accessible) and the right thing to do (which is likely
to be not merely difficult to access but perhaps also difficult to
articulate). However, in the scenario of euthanasia and/or the provision
of life-sustaining measures the intersections of ethical and legal values
are so
visceral as to risk colouring a strong distinction between the legal thing to do
and the right thing to do as mere avoidance.
To date, my research has
explored the following question: Do we only really gain a sense of reassurance
that we have done the right
thing after the fact of a decision and/or
action rather than beforehand? This question is only partially interested in the
psychological phenomenon
of reassurance and is mostly interested in an analogy
of ethics with historical method: Is it only with the passage of time that
the
wisdom or otherwise of our actions becomes clear? Or as is commonly attributed
to Zhou Enlai in discussion with Dr Kissinger
in regard to what the former
thought of the good done by the French Revolution of 1789: It is too soon to
tell.
Euthanasia is one of a handful of human experiences where that
observation is particularly pertinent and, for similar reasons notwithstanding
it being a different (albeit arguably related) phenomenon, the same is true of
substituted decision-making in respect of the withholding
or withdrawing of
life-sustaining measures.[14] This
is because for the same reason that we will never see a child ethical prodigy
similarly the reassurance that we have done right
in a situation such as
substituted decision-making in the provision of life-sustaining measures, is a
phenomenon which generally
comes after the
fact.[15]
As already noted,
this proposition is understandable by reference to the earlier analogy with the
child prodigy historian: an ability
to recite the facts of history that are on
record is not the same as an ability to comprehend or otherwise exhibit a
consciousness
of history as a human skill, insight or art. The historian’s
ability to recite facts may well be of assistance in gaining insight
and
comprehension but it is not a sufficient condition for its achievement. Just as
works of art commonly change in significance
with continued interpretation over
time, is it not the case that we too reflect on our lives and interpret
differently the significance
of certain of our past actions and decisions? Is it
not the case that the wisdom (or limitations) of our past actions and decisions
only emerges with the perspective of retrospectivity?
In short: is the
pang of regret a hallmark of a proper engagement with ethical discourse and
decision-making? Here ‘regret’ is not employed only or simply
as synonymous with either remorse or sorrow. Regret here also refers to the
bitter-sweet phenomenon
that the vicissitudes of life have forced on us a
circumstance which we would have wished to avoid had we the luxury of living in
either an ideal world or at least a world of our own design.
It is true
that we may regret those decisions and actions which we later feel were wrong.
That experience can itself be a point of
learning about the ethical life.
Equally however, it is true that we may regret that which was unavoidable and
necessary and wistfully
reflect that if only the world was otherwise then both
ourselves and those whom have been affected by our decisions and actions might
have been spared some of the seemingly unavoidable pain of life. It is that
experience which is emphasised here as a crucial part
of an ethic of regret.
This is because if we focus our enquiry and standards before the fact on the
process of our decision-making
then the subjective experience of regret that may
eventually follow after our decision or action can serve as hallmark of the
integrity
with which we engaged in the process.
Hence, just as a
hallmark attests to the quality of a silver item so too regret may serve to
identify the extent to which we did (or
did not) engage with integrity in the
relevant decision-making process. As I have previously noted, those of us who
have had to make
a decision to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining measures as
well as those of us who have worked with people who, in extreme circumstances,
had to make split second decisions which led to the deaths of co-workers,
comrades in arms and even family members, know that quite
often there simply is
not the luxury of time (or emotional calm) in which to even pretend that a fully
informed, unpressured decision
was reached before the event. From my
experience, many of those who have lived through such situations only come to
see (if they ever do some to see)
the prudence of their actions long
after the event.
If these observations resonate with us as true
then, at the very least, does it not follow that it is in the nature of a
Wittgensteinian
category-mistake to ask before the fact of, for instance,
withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining measures, whether the content
of our
decision is right?[16] Given the
category of the language game that is ethics or the nature of ethical discourse,
is not the more appropriate question before
the fact simply this: What
reassurance can we have that we are acting ethically, acting rightly before the
fact irrespective of the
content of the particular decision? In the result, the
focus of enquiry perhaps ought be more on the rectitude of the process or
art of
decision-making and less on the rightness of the decision itself? In the context
of this discussion about substituted decision-making
and the refusal or
withdrawal of life-sustaining measures, the touchstone of rectitude in the
process would be the decision-making
process and guidelines identified in the
statutory regime.
It is argued that these observations highlight both the
potency and relevancy of classical Aristotelian virtue ethics. In
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean
Ethics[17] the
ingénue ethicist is admonished (and I paraphrase) to hitch their wagon to
an older, wiser adept and imitate them. It does
not follow from this admonition
that our accumulated experience over the centuries of a long line of ethical
theorists (in whose
wagon wheel ruts we now follow) means that we, all these
roughly 2,500 years after Aristotle, have any greater certainty or reassurance
that we are doing right than Aristotle when asked to advise, before the
fact, whether life-sustaining measures ought be given or withheld in a given
situation.[18] If that last
observation is correct and nearly 2,500 thousand years of collective experience
and discussion about agreed first principles
for ethical decision-making
etc does not necessarily put us in a superior position to Aristotle when
faced with ethical dilemmas, then it is reasonable to infer
that no matter how
many times, either as a species or as individuals, we seek guidance that we are
doing right before the fact there are always going to be situations of
human experience in which the analytic approach is inadequate.
In short:
perhaps there are occasions when we ought not to seek reassurance that we are
doing right before simply by reference to analytic reasoning. Rather, we
ought focus less on the search for the right content of a decision
before the fact and instead draw comfort from Aristotelian ethics that
perhaps our proper goal is that we act rightly before the fact. In
this circumstance, the giving or withholding of life-sustaining measures, for
example, is one such occasion where the
prudence or otherwise of that decision
is best assessed only in retrospect (not prospectively) and the assayer’s
scales should
be calibrated with an eye more to the integrity of the
decision-making process and the goals and objectives of that process (acting
rightly) rather than to the (right) content or effect of the decision
itself.
An immediate and obvious advantage of this approach is that
there is no need for a distinction of any kind (whether strong or weak)
between
the legal thing to do and the right thing to do. This is because both the legal
thing to do and the right thing to do will
merge into the same issue for
forensic investigation: whether the decision-making process was rightly
followed. In the context of
the provision of life-sustaining measures this would
result in an assessment of whether the statutory guidelines and criteria
obviously
played a role and influenced the decision-making process.
III GUIDED BY THESE INSIGHTS, WHAT MIGHT FOLLOW BY WAY OF LAW
REFORM IN RESPECT OF THE GUARDIANSHIP AND ADMINISTRATION ACT 2000 (QLD)
?
It needs to be emphasised that this discussion of substituted ethical
decision-making whether in the context of end of life decisions
generally or the
withdrawal/refusal of life-sustaining measures in particular, occurs in the
context of a pluralist, secular, democratic
society. Accordingly, it is argued
that any suggested reform would ideally both enhance the understanding of
ethical decision-making
advanced here as well as at least respect if not
actually promote pluralist, secular, democratic values. The suggested law reform
advanced here is a mechanism for giving the community a voice early in any
process that deals with a complaint about the appropriateness
or otherwise of a
particular exercise of substituted decision-making under the Act. Consistent
with the paradigm for ethical decision-making
advanced in this article, the
suggested mechanism focuses less on assaying the content or effect of the
decision itself and instead
assays the probity of the decision-making process
itself.
From at least mediaeval times until the Stuart dynasty, there was
in England the phenomenon of the ‘grand jury’. Akin with the
function of the grand jury in most U.S. jurisdictions today, this jury did not
make findings of guilt at a
trial but instead was assembled before a
trial occurred in order to determine whether it was proper to charge a person
with an offence.[19] As such the
processes and functions of the grand jury mirror those of committal proceedings
in Queensland’s Magistrates
courts.[20]
A benefit of the
grand jury system is that it provides community input at a very early stage of
the criminal process. It is argued
that within a secular, pluralist, democratic
society it is difficult to under-estimate the importance of inviting the voice
of popular
wisdom or common sense into an assessment of the criminality or
otherwise of, for instance, withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining
measures.
This is important not because the views of a grand jury are more likely to be
right (whether at law or as an exercise in
ethical discourse) than those of a
substituted decision-maker or court. Rather, the primary importance of giving a
voice to the general
public through the grand jury at an early stage of the
process is that it acts as a weather vane for the prevailing popular consensus
at a given point in time on a given issue.
The secondary importance of
giving a voice to the general public through the grand jury at such an early
stage is that it increases
the transparency of decisions whether or not to
prosecute, decreases the pressures attendant with a broad exercise of
prosecutorial
discretion, and provides more timely input of the prevailing
popular
consensus.[21]
Accordingly,
the submission is that if a question arises as to whether a particular decision
to provide or withhold life-sustaining
measures was illegitimate, that issue
could be tested in a preliminary way by this special court of coronial enquiry
or special sitting
of the Guardianship Tribunal with the assistance of a grand
jury. The grand jury would sit as the tribunal of fact on a specific
question:
namely, whether the decision-maker both abided by the processes required by the
legislation and was guided by (and only
by) the criteria for decision-making
that is identified in the legislation.
There are obvious difficulties
with this proposition not the least of which is how the grand jury could purport
to get into the mind
of the substituted decision-maker and be satisfied that the
decision-making process was guided by (and only by) the relevant statutory
criteria. However, this is a forensic difficulty that is true of every jury
finding in respect of crimes or civil torts that involve
an element of
intention. Indeed, this potential weakness is a possible strength as it makes
the complaint process about substituted
decision-making consistent with a good
number of other judicial processes.
The matter could be finally
determined in that forum except if the finding was to the effect that the
particular decision was prima facie illegitimate in which case, much like
committal proceedings in the criminal jurisdiction, the matter would be referred
on for further
consideration in a higher court (whether of civil or criminal
jurisdiction being moot for present purposes). Some of the advantages
of such a
proposal are reasonably obvious:
1. If the complaint is that life-giving
measures were illegitimately withheld, it avoids the need for prosecutorial
discretion (or
other mechanisms whereby decisions about whether to investigate
or commence legal proceedings are made) it avoids the need for such
discretion
to occur behind closed doors and without much accountability;
2. If the
complaint is that life-giving measures were illegitimately provided, it gives
the relevant decision-maker a forum for vindication
without being directly in
any kind of legal jeopardy;
3. This forum provides an expedient mechanism for
adding to the case law, and therefore the standards expected of decision-makers,
those measures that arise due to changes in technology without always playing a
game of ‘catch up’ with the Parliament;
4. Similarly, this
forum provides an expedient mechanism for testing public opinion and popular
mores without, again, the need for
playing ‘catch up’ with
the Parliament;
5. And finally, in a democratic and egalitarian society
committed to the rule of law as inherited from the common law tradition, there
is a special appeal in having the common sense of disinterested lay members of
the public involved in determining just such a question
rather than leaving it
simply to the professionals.
It is also appropriate to consider the
advantages of this proposal from the perspective of ethical theory or method.
And, in outlining
these advantages, I return to my dilemma about the lack of
child prodigy bioethicists.
Perhaps the lack of child prodigy
bioethicists is due to the fact ethics is best understood as an art rather than
a science –
a virtue acquired with experience rather than a method that
can be acquired from pedagogy. Accordingly, like all art it is best
judged:
- By others rather than
the artist alone;
- After the work
of art is completed rather than in the planning stage;
- Has to be experienced either in
its performance or the interaction of its display rather than simply imagined or
be the subject of
speculation;
- Over time and
allowing for changes in perception, opinion and regard for the artwork as
society changes rather than frozen once and
for all in the mind of the artist.
The final question asked in this article is whether, like how we judge
and discuss or appreciate art, are ethical decisions best understood
by
reference to such factors as the measure of regret we feel at the passing,
ephemeral experience of our interaction with art; the
regret which we feel after
we encounter a work of art (perhaps profound if disappointed by the experience
and tinged as bitter sweet
if pleased with the experience and sad at its
passing)? Just as these factors can legitimately influence our reaction to art,
are
these not also legitimate factors in appreciating ethical decisions? Hence,
a profound work of art will likely elicit the regret
that we have failed or
otherwise are incapable of producing the same art. Whereas a flawed work of art
will likely elicit regret
in the artist; or the artist’s sponsors when the
public judgement is known. For those reasons the author will now desist from
this discursus and leave the reader to assess the measure of regret occasioned
by the time spent reading it.
[*] Holding the degrees of B.A Hons I, LL.B, M.A and Ph.D from the University of Queensland, Mark has been a research fellow at St PaulR
s Theological College, Banyo, since
2003 and a barrister in private practice in Brisbane since 1998.
[1] This article draws on a research work in progress and is offered here with a view more to instigating discussion at than to present
a comprehensive treatment of the topic. Hence, the article is characterised more by the number of questions that it asks rather than
its
answers.
[2] B White and L
Willmott, Rethinking Life – Sustaining Measures: Questions for
Queensland (QUT Printing Services,
2005).
[3] I am acutely conscious
that the Issues Paper, consistent with current literature on the subject, makes
a strong distinction between
euthanasia and the withdrawal/withholding of
life-sustaining measures. For the purposes of this article it is of no
importance whether
such a distinction is accepted or rejected. This is because
the consequences of the argument in this article apply equally to both
phenomena
whether they be heterogeneous or
not.
[4] White and Willmott, above
n 3, 15, para 3; 79, para 13.4; 55, para 8.4; 50, para 6.4; 40, para
4.
[5] See: Enduring Powers of
Attorney Act 1998 (Qld) and Guardianship and Administration Act 2000
(Qld); as well as Re B [2002] All ER
449.
[6] See: J A Rawls, Theory
of Justice (Harvard University Press,
1972).
[7] See: R Dworkin,
Taking Rights Seriously (Duckworths,
1977).
[8] Notwithstanding
Finnis’ well-known opposition to euthanasia generally and his support for,
at most, a circumscribed definition
of palliative care, it is possible to adapt
the logic of his natural law approach to jurisprudence to support a conclusion
different
from his own. See: J Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights
(Clarendon Press, 1980).
[9]
For present purposes, all that is meant here by ‘quasi-exercise in
utilitarian calculus’ is that the relevant legislation seemingly
provides a checklist of factors which a decision-maker must consider.
Accordingly, it
seems trite to observe that notwithstanding the detail in the
legislation to the contrary, the greater the number of factors in the
checklist
which suggest a given outcome then the more likely it is that the combined
weight of those factors will determine a result;
ie If factors in the
checklist in favour of x-result outnumber the factors in favour of alternative
results, it is plausible to suppose
that this numerical superiority in and of
itself will constitute a further factor that influences a decision-maker. It is
this phenomenon
of numerical superiority influencing a decision-maker which is
reminiscent of utilitarian calculus inasmuch as, in the context of
substituted
decision-making exercised by reference to the legislation, it is akin to a
finding of a surplus of happiness (synonymous
here with ‘best interest of
the patient’) in one alternative which alternative ought then be
implemented.
[10] I hasten to
add that it is not argued here that the Issues Paper adopts just such a glib,
uncritical approach. Rather, it is simply
argued here that the building blocks
in the Issues Paper that have been identified here are capable of being
extracted from the Issues
Paper and applied in just such a way by
others.
[11] For the sake of
clarity, I repeat: my earlier reference to a quasi-exercise of utilitarian
calculus only refers to the likelihood
that if there is a greater number of
factors in favour of a particular decision in a given situation then that
numerical superiority
itself might understandably be of significance to a
substituted decision-maker notwithstanding that the tenor of the legislation
is
contrary to such a factor being determinative of the ultimate
decision.
[12] Hence the
proposition that, as a matter of applied ethics, the best quarter for addressing
the legal issues surrounding euthanasia
generally and the withholding or
withdrawing of life-sustaining measures in particular is from the area of tort
law rather than a
jurisprudence of human
rights.
[13] And I stress, it is
only a surmise based on my personal experience first as a clinical pastoral
counsellor in hospitals for several
years and later as a lawyer involved in both
personal injuries and professional (medical) negligence
litigation.
[14] Those of us who
have had to make a decision to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining measures as
well as those of us who have worked
with people who, in extreme circumstances,
had to make split second decisions which led to the deaths of co-workers,
comrades in
arms and even family members, know that quite often there simply is
not the luxury of time (or emotional calm) in which to even pretend
that a fully
informed, unpressured decision was reached. From my experience, many of those
who have lived through such situations
only come to see (if they ever do some to
see) the prudence of their actions long after the
event.
[15] Personally, I would
draw greater comfort from the knowledge that the substituted decision-maker who
determined my doom was tinged
with regret that the vicissitudes of life had
brought us both to such a circumstance than I would from the thought of some
juvenile
prodigy engaging in the same exercise with blithe
certainty.
[16] According to
Wittgenstein, examples of a category mistake include trying to measure time with
a ruler – the subject matter
is not amenable to the frame of enquiry or
reference applied to it. At least in the early philosophy of Wittgenstein,
category mistakes
accounted for most of the confusion and mistakes in
philosophy. See: L Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (C Ogden
trans, Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1922).
[17] See Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics (W D Ross trans, Oxford University Press,
1980).
[18] The classic examples
given by Aristotle are to compare ethics with various human arts and skills,
such as music or archery. Even
though musicians and archers today have the
benefit of those insights passed on by previous musicians and archers, it does
not follow
that the musicians and archers of today can, because of their
forebears, skip any lessons or avoid any of the practice necessary
to achieve
their art or skill. It is as if each generation does have to learn to invent the
wheel again.
[19] See: J Baker,
An Introduction to English Legal History (Butterworths, 2nd
ed, 1979) 64, 415.
[20] The
notable difference being that the grand jury’s function was to determine,
before the fact of arrest and charge, whether a true bill of indictment
could be maintained whereas, in Queensland, that same question is
asked by a
magistrate in committal proceedings after the fact of arrest and the
charge being laid.
[21] The
difficulties with broad prosecutorial discretion whether, for instance, to
prosecute for murder in circumstances suggestive
of voluntary, assisted
euthanasia have been highlighted in research over the past decade. See: M
Otlowski, ‘Mercy Killing Cases
in the Australian Criminal Justice
System’ (1993) 17 Australian Criminal Law Journal 10-39.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2006/14.html