![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
![]() |
SANCTITY OF LIFE, A SENSE OF LIFE, AND GOOD ENDINGS
GRANT GILLETT [*]
Since the Terry Schiavo case the idea of sanctity of life has shown itself to
be open to interpretations which seem too hard edged
to be compatible with the
kind of concern about human life that bioethics ought to be fostering. When we
turn elsewhere for a concept
that will do the work that is needed we find the
phrase ‘a sense of life’ made famous by Martha Nussbaum. But what is
meant by this? That it is linked to the sanctity of life seems inescapable but
the link is problematic in a way that demands a closer
inquiry, Nussbaum links
it to a quasi-objective sense of a good life which raises issues of quality of
life and not mere prolonging
of life and yet seems to defuse the judgmental
stance that is sometimes associated with the concept of quality of life. I
settle
on a reading in terms of subjectivity and the nature of the other (as
encountered in the work of Levinas) such that an ethics of
the subject as a
being engaged with us in a distinctive way becomes the starting point of
philosophical inquiry about human life
and death. This then gives a sense in
which the life of a human being is sacred but not in a way that favours its
continuance in
all circumstances but focuses our attention on the subjectivity
at the centre of the life.
I INTRODUCTION
Since the Terry Schiavo case the idea of sanctity of life has shown
itself to be open to interpretations which seem to have little
to do with the
kind of concern about human life that bioethics ought to be fostering. It is
hard to escape the idea that hard-edged
and absolute duties are being mobilised
to support stances which lack a certain type of engagement with an unenviable
human predicament.
When we turn elsewhere for a concept that will do the work
that is needed, we find the phrase ‘a sense of life’ made
famous by
Martha Nussbaum (in her work Love’s
knowledge).[1] But what is meant
by this? The link to the sanctity of life is inescapable and important but is
problematic in a way that demands
a closer inquiry. To pursue that inquiry we
might explore the way the term is used by the author but also trace its
resonances with
other work in ethics and the contexts of that conversation. To
that end we can begin with what surrounds the phrase in Nussbaum’s
text so
as to get some idea of its structural location in the author’s thought. In
particular one wants to know how such an
idea or feeling is related to the
sanctity of life doctrine and the duties associated with it.
A sense of
life is said to be required for reflective equilibrium, in the sense used by
John Rawls to indicate the melding of ethical
intuition with ethical principles
in one’s response to a given case. Ethical intuitions are, famously,
linked to different
conceptions of the good life (or orthodoxies) usually held
to be irreconcilable and competing in a fragmented moral landscape, so
that they
are beyond rational argumentation.[2]
Nussbaum, an Aristotelian, does not concede that point and asks how we might be
able to evaluate the idea of ‘the good life’.
She remarks:
we
notice and clearly describe the tensions among the views we find. Where there is
inconsistency or irreconcilable tension ... we
aim to revise the overall picture
so as to bring it into harmony with itself, preserving, as Aristotle says
“the greatest number
and the most basic” of the original judgments
and perceptions. There is no rule about how to do this. Individuals simply ask
what looks deepest, what they can least live without – guided by their
sense of life, and by their standing interest in consistency
and
community.[3]
She illustrates
by exploring the case of Strether (in Henry James’ The Ambassadors)
who is sent to Europe to check on the scion of a solid New England family who
has been sent to Paris for ‘finishing’.
He finds himself a little
‘at sea’ in relation to the values and duties sanctioned by New
England society and that he
is approaching his moral quest ‘marked by a
child’s fresh delight in seeing and an undirected openness to the new
concrete
thing’. She comments:
This sense that life is an
adventure, and that part of its joy precisely is the confrontation with the new
– this is a sense
of life already far removed from that where dignity is
preserved by keeping down the new, acknowledging it only insofar as it
exemplifies
some law whose sense is already understood. ... heroically untouched
by any horrible or wonderful aspect of
life.[4]
She is clearly
distancing herself from a contrasting morality ‘solidly grounded’ in
an articulated set of duties and allegiances
defined by a clear cut framework
which one accepts as definitive of the good for those ‘like me’,
that which is said
to be irreconcilable with others of its ilk by thinkers like
MacIntyre and Engelhardt.
Immediately we can say something that a sense
of life is not – it is not wedded to absolutes narrowly conceived and
defined
in advance so that they can be applied sans phrase to the
contexts in which they are to be discharged. Sanctity of life is often construed
this way but, if Nussbaum is right, perhaps
the relevant value should not
be.
We can also follow a clue offered by Jean Paul
Sartre[5] in his discussion of the
‘spirit of seriousness’ which ‘considers values as
transcendent givens independent of
human subjectivity’ handed down to us
as part of our essential being.
A sense of life seems to embody the idea
that the ethics guiding our mortal judgments should be developed in the light of
a finely
attuned sensitivity to the human condition and a nuanced view of
contested situations rather than seen as instancing and applying
ethical truths
laid down in an extra-human domain somehow immutable and impervious to the
particularities of human predicaments.
II THE SANCTITY OF LIFE.
If that is true, then a sense of life is not, in any flatfooted way,
committed to a doctrine of the right to life whatever the condition
of the human
being concerned, but rather regards the sanctity of life as something to be
interrogated in the light of human subjectivity.
But if that sounds a bit
‘woolly’ and an unlikely place to start real world ethical and legal
thinking in the difficult
context of the clinic or healthcare in general, we
should notice that our intuitions are not nearly as clearcut in relation to life
and death as some pronouncements make them out to be even if one holds a firm
and widely accepted set of values. When we ask what
is sacred about life we are
immediately led to conclude that it cannot be mere biological life or what
Helmut Thielicke[6] calls ‘the
empty shell of what once was human ... which can therefore no longer act as an
independent subject’ ‘merely
a biological culture’ but must
rather be a subject who can be addressed as ‘you’. Thielicke, a
protestant theologian,
aims in this claim to agree with Pius XII who focuses on
the person as a subject and gives supreme weight to ‘the presumed
will of
the unconscious patient’ in the provision of life prolonging
measures.[7] He is also in agreement
with John Paul II in his 1995 encyclical Evangelium Vitae who affirms the
value of human life as the setting where we meet God and enter into communion
with God and others. Thus ‘the
life of the body in its earthly state is
not an absolute good’[8] and:
euthanasia must be distinguished from the decision to forego so-called
“aggressive medical treatment,” in other words,
medical procedures
which no longer correspond to the real situation of the patient either because
they are disproportionate to any
expected results or because they impose an
excessive burden on the patient or his
family.[9]
Notice that, in this
Encyclical roundly rejecting both abortion and euthanasia, John Paul II makes a
distinction between biological
life and the life of a subject who can have
meaningful relationships (with God or other human beings). It is worth noting
that we
are called, even by these traditionally conservative voices to consider
the sanctity of life as involving a more nuanced principle
than the principle of
saving life in all circumstances and with whatever outcome, a view that seems
sometimes to be the thrust of
an absolute proscription against any medical or
ethical complicity in accepting death as a natural end of life. The
‘gospel
of life’ seems to regard death as something that, in the
words of the hospice movement, should neither be hastened or unduly
delayed so
that we should aim for a ‘natural death’ in so far as that is
possible in our medically technologized world.
In fact we are now in
territory with which I feel distinctly familiar as a series of concepts come
into view deserving close consideration
in the light of a sense of life as a
possible interpretative lens for the idea of the sanctity of life; they are:
(i) Substantial benefit or an outcome which now or in the future the
patient would consider worthwhile; and
(ii) The RUB or the Risk of
Unacceptable Badness.
These two concepts are more or less self
explanatory and help spell out what we mean by respecting the life of a human
subject in
the context of decisions regarding limitation of treatment in
end-of-life care.
III WHOSE LIFE IS SACRED?
We should turn first to the investigation of the relation between
subjectivity and a sense of life. A subject lives a life which forms
a kind of a
story and even though a life lived is more than such a story the discussion of
the fitting end to a human life can usefully
begin with the narrative view of
human life.[10]
If an
individual’s narrative and life project determines what counts as doing
the right thing for that person, certain conclusions
follow that can be made
vivid in a thought experiment (one I commonly use in our ethics course).
A young man, Nigel, is admitted to hospital to investigate headaches and
epilepsy. He has a CT and an MRI scan that show a malignant
brain tumour. He is
told that his diagnosis and that he has a life expectancy of a few months. He is
shattered so the neurosurgeon
suggests he talk to a nurse or chaplain.
Two days later the neurosurgeon comes back saying he has good news. He
says that they have been working on brain transplants for some
years and that a
young motorbike rider has been mangled in an accident with a train. They have
kept his brain alive but the rest
of his body is beyond saving. Nigel is told he
can have a brain transplant so that he need not die from his malignant brain
tumour.
Nigel is, momentarily, overjoyed. However, just as the neurosurgeon goes
to leave, he asks “Hold it, who is going to wake up
from this
operation?”
Now most people do not believe that Nigel will wake up
which implies that most of us believe that the brain is the seat of the life
of
the person as a person. It is clear that an adequate level of brain function is
required both to support conscious life and to
keep a cumulative record so that
a lived narrative can be inscribed in the person. And, as long as this lived
experience can be activated,
there seems to be a continuation of the life of the
person as a person rather than merely a ‘biological remnant of a
person’.[11]
Some
prominent themes marking individual subjectivity emerge from the story including
personal identity -a story of one’s own, conscious awareness
of the world around one, and intentional interaction with others.
Personal identity is, an autobiographical feature whereby an
individual constructs a life story for him or herself, perhaps not very original
or deliberate,
but with a narrative structure and its own integrity. As the
individual living this life among these people, the narrative may
be more often edited rather than authored it is continually being updated in the
light of everything that
is happening and it is open-ended. Therefore (as
Aristotle, Jean Paul Sartre, and many others have noted), one’s life story
is not finished until death because everything prior to that is part of the
remembered (perhaps by self and definitely by others)
story of a given the lived
life.
Second, conscious awareness or lived experience is the
person’s response to the world and others (which may only be as a passive
observer amongst others). Locked in Syndrome,
for instance leaves the person in
the position of a moral patient reliant upon others for the quality of their
experiences. I have
argued elsewhere that there are philosophical reasons to
doubt that the Cartesian or purely inner self is a human possibility because
consciousness essentially is an active, interactive, and exploratory cognitive
function of whole
subjects.[12]
Third,
intentional action and interaction is the expression of an
individual’s conceptions and
interests.[13] Even where the
individual concerned is severely disabled, there can be a quality of interaction
that those who know the person discern
and respond to in complex and nuanced
ways. But once the possibility of any such action or interaction is irrevocably
lost because
of severe and widespread brain damage, the person's life as a
person has ended.
We can, at this point, usefully revisit Aristotle
(whose influence is felt in Christian thought through St Thomas Aquinas).
Aristotle
argued that the human soul is best thought of as a holistic set of
functions and capacities realized in the human body through its
interaction in
rational and social/political (discursive) so that there is a close link between
brain function and the integrity
of a unique psychological being. Therefore,
once that which supports the soul has been effectively destroyed, the life of
the person
as a person is ended. If bodily life as a ‘biological
remnant‘ of a fully human life is then continued, it cannot have the same
significance
as the life of a person as a subject, a fact with profound ethical
implications.
IV ENDING THE NARRATIVE IN A FITTING WAY
A person can stop living the story of his or her life in the sense of
experiencing it as a lived life and in such a situation those
of us who know and
love the person concerned need to try and ensure that the life story is ended in
a way that is fitting. For that
to be possible medical ethics and medical law
have to work closely together.
The ethical issues in this area were
raised by the case of Tony Bland injured in the Hillsborough stadium disaster.
The judges ruled
that we should respect the hypothetical wishes of Tony Bland
himself (as we might say ‘considered as a human subject not a
biological
organism’), and thus that his death should be fitting in the whole context
of his life. Their reasoning about the
removal of the gastric feeding tube
keeping him alive is similar reasoning to that in the cases of Brophy and
Quinlan;[14]
if Anthony
Bland were to be momentarily restored to consciousness with full knowledge that
he would shortly revert to his PVS, and
if he were to instruct those caring for
him that he no longer wanted artificially to be kept alive, the doctors and
nurses would
be obliged to respect his wishes. ... The horror of his situation
is such that few would not think it perfectly reasonable for him
to decide that,
as he has already lost all sense and consciousness, he would prefer to die.
...Anthony Bland is an individual human
being and the principle of
self-determination says he should be allowed to choose for himself and that, if
he is unable to express
his choice, we should try our honest best to do what we
think he would have
chosen.[15]
Notice the
prominent place given to Tony Bland as a subject with consciousness and a sense
of self-determination so that we ought
to attend to the patient's life and
attitudes, and do our best to respect the patient him or herself when we
consider the provision
of life-prolonging treatment. In fact, because it is a
basic feature of the life of any person that he or she should live out his
or
her own life story, it is not just futile to keep an irreversibly comatose body
alive in Persistent Vegetative State (PVS) but
it is a certain kind of violence
to (or disrespects the sanctity of) the subject as a self-determining human
being.
A similar line of reasoning led a New Zealand court to decide
that the termination of an Auckland patient's life would not be
unlawful.[16] Mr L, a man of 59
years, had been totally paralysed by Guillain-Barre Syndrome (which strips the
coverings from nerves throughout
the body) so that he had a type of
‘Locked in Syndrome’. The specialists who saw him agreed there was
no hope of recovery
and his view was reliably said to be that he did not ever
want to be left in such a state. His wife supported the medical team in
their
request to terminate his ventilator treatment and the court ruled that it would
not be unlawful for the medical team in charge
of Mr L to terminate his life
support (that having been done, he died within 30 minutes an outcome deemed to
be in accordance with
his being as a human
subject).[17]
Two
further cases recommend the same conclusion but provide a conceptualization that
also hinges on the idea of respect proper to
a human subject. An Irish case
concerned a woman aged 43 who had been severely brain injured at the age of 22
during a gynaecological
operation. She was, at the time of the judgment:
spastic, her jaws were clenched, she could not swallow, she was
incontinent and bedridden ... For 20 years she received nutrition
and hydration
through a nasogastric tube. This caused her some distress and she pulled it out
on many occasions ... [she] was unable
to speak and attempts by a speech
therapist to establish some form of communication proved unsuccessful. [she]
appeared ... able
to recognise members of her nursing staff, and reacted to
strangers by showing distress. She could follow people with her eyes and
reacted
to noise, although this appeared to be mostly by way of reflex
action.[18]
The High Court,
per Lynch J, consented to the withdrawal of artificial nutrition and hydration
(upheld by the Irish Supreme Court).
The main points of the judgment were that:
1) the ward's best interests should prevail over other
considerations;
2) the court exercised a parens patriae jurisdiction
to ensure that those interests were protected;
3) the right to life includes
a right to a dignified death;
4) the provision of nourishment through a
gastric tube was intrusive;
5) the right to self-determination means that a
competent adult has the right to refuse any medical treatment
whatsoever;
6) this right should not be denied a person who did not have the
mental capacity to exercise it; and
7) in this case the ward should be
allowed to die a natural death.
The reasoning and its obvious links to
the Bland case are clear. The link between a right to life and the right to a
dignified death
is, however, novel and striking but in deep accord with the
present discussion of a sense of life and a framework for ethical decisions
informed by what is profoundly worthwhile in a human life. Absent this
connection we can use life prolonging treatments without adequate
ethical or
juridical constraints (appropriately sensitive to the concerns of a human
subject) on that use. The Irish court invokes
a ‘right to a dignified
death’ but an appeal to the idea of substantial benefit (as defined) or a
sense of what is fitting
in the whole context of the person’s life story
delivers the same conclusion.
The New Zealand case, Mr G, concerned a 69
year old man who had suffered a severe brain injury in a road accident 16 months
previously.[19] The judge
noted:
He is totally immobile, is unable to talk or otherwise communicate
in any meaningful way and is incontinent of urine and faeces. His
CT scans and
EEG show severe brain damage. Every effort has been made to rehabilitate him but
to no avail. He has remained in the
same state and there is no prospect of
recovery. He is kept alive by food and fluids through a gastrostomy tube and is
provided with
all necessary and appropriate medical and nursing
care.[20]
Judge Fraser
consented to the removal of gastric food and fluid, taking note of the cases of
Mr L, Tony Bland, and the Irish Ward
of court already described, and
of:
1. Mr G's injuries and his present condition;
2. specialist
opinions that artificial feeding and fluid be withdrawn;
3. the fact that the
prospect of meaningful recovery was ‘virtually nil’;
4. the
Ethics Committee's unanimous decision that they had no objection to withdrawal
of treatment;
5. the application for withdrawal by Mr G's family
6. the
evidence that Mr G's wishes if they could be ascertained would be to have
treatment withdrawn; and
7. the fact that withdrawal of treatment would not
cause pain and suffering.
He ruled that those measures should be used
which would allow Mr G ‘to end his life and die peacefully with the
greatest dignity
and the least
distress’[21] again implicitly
appealing to something like the fuller sense of life that we are currently
interrogating.
The thought that the life of a human subject implies that
there is a link between the right to life and the right to a dignified death
(or, alternatively, that respect for the sanctity of life turns on a conception
of human life that is something more than a mere
biological life), we notice
that there are conditions in which we can (and should) decide on somebody's
behalf that he or she would
not want his or her present existence to continue
(states of unacceptable badness). We ought to be able to reassure any patient
that
if such a state eventuated, then health care professionals would not keep
him/her alive by intrusive medical means but would respect
the human subject at
the heart of the issue and a sense of life proper to that conception resulting
in an ethical basis for the maintenance
and withdrawal of life prolonging
treatment that respects the dignity and integrity of the patient (as a human
subject).
V THE RUB: THE WORST POSSIBLE END TO THE STORY
A similar point can be made when the life of a human being is under mortal
threat. Consider the decision to withhold or withdraw life
saving treatment if,
for instance, a patient is admitted acutely and rescue treatment or
Cardio-Pulmonary Resuscitation (CPR) is
required. Two alternatives are commonly
mentioned – life and death; but there is another significant category:
survival in
an unacceptably bad state for the patient concerned. Here we
confront the RUB (the Risk of Unacceptable Badness). ‘To sleep,
perchance
to dream, Aye, there’s the RUB’.
Hamlet is contemplating
suicide. He has been told by a ghost (purporting to be that of his father, the
recently deceased king of Denmark)
that his Uncle (who has since married his
mother) murdered that same beloved father. Should he take revenge on his uncle
or just
exit? If his uncle is innocent, killing him is a mortal sin which Hamlet
has committed on the basis of demonic information, and for
which he will be
damned. But if he fails to avenge his father, he could not live with himself and
the regretful dreams that might
come in the sleep of death. In this quandary
(intensified, according to some commentators, by an Oedipal conflict) he is
paralyzed
by the prospect of eternity dead, therefore, impotent, but wracked
with the moral torments fuelling his suicidal thoughts, an unacceptably
bad
prospect; ‘Aye, there’s the RUB.’
The RUB is morally
challenging and doctors confront it often when they work in rescue medicine
considering resuscitation in a seriously
compromised patient, a severe brain
injury, or a devastating stroke. Facing the dual prospects life and death, we
often hear ‘Well,
doc, go for it; after all, any chance is better than
none.’ But is that so? The person may be left in an unacceptably bad
state,
hence the RUB!
This is a stark and taxing choice but one hopes
that the person making it on one’s behalf has a very clear idea of the
proper
sense of life and the role of relatives or other surrogate decision
makers. In most jurisdictions, those making the decision ought
to try and do
what the person at risk would have wanted to happen to him or her and not what
the relatives or anybody else think
should happen, or, worse, what is demanded
by an inflexible value. We should try and do what would be of substantial
benefit to the person concerned where that is best defined
as:[22]
An outcome which
now or in the future the patient would consider worthwhile.
Thus the
ethical responsibility of the health care team is to make the best decision they
can in the face of medical uncertainty about
the unfolding clinical reality (and
the relatives may be an invaluable source of information on what, for the
patient concerned,
would constitute substantial benefit).
Our
ethical worries reflect, in part, the widespread and rationally unsustainable
belief that life is to be saved at all costs, coupled,
for some, with the view
that beginning treatment and then stopping it is worse than not beginning at
all. But the need for the best
information – for instance, about the
severity of the initial insult and about its response to treatment –
favours what
we might call a trial of treatment rather than absolute
withholding. It is important that everybody understands that treatment is
being
trialed and that the patient’s response is an important indicator of how
long the treatment should continue. If the uncertainties
are acknowledged, the
idea of a trial of treatment clarified, and the need to act in a way consistent
with a sense of life as coloured
by the patient’s values (as a human
subject) is kept in mind, then people tend to cope well with withdrawing
treatment (and
do not see it as an inexplicable change in clinical management).
Most people understand that the withdrawal of potentially life-saving
treatment
is an issue to be revisited once its likely effect has been gauged and that any
decision (in which the RUB is a factor)
should be made in the light of some
all-in sense of what makes for a good human life (in terms appropriate to the
individual concerned).
The RUB cuts out the simplistic ‘two
options’ approach to life and death situations and makes it clear that the
chance
of survival might only be bought at the cost of a very high risk of an
unacceptably bad outcome. A sense of life guides us to take
stock and face our
responsibility to do what is in the best interests of the patient (as a subject)
or what s/he would want if he
were able to choose. By engaging others in the
process of decision, the team can get a sense of the values and interests that
the
patient had before the catastrophe and respect the more or less integrated
story that is their patient’s life, as a lived experience.
Even if there
is not an explicit advanced directive one can, as a result usually make a
judgment about the fittingness of certain
possible endings to the
patient’s story.
In an entirely analogous way we can, in a
discussion of CPR with the patient him or herself, convey the reality captured
by the RUB
so that, the ‘any chance is better than none’ approach
becomes much less attractive than it otherwise seems. Life (valued
positively)
and death (valued negatively) can then be compared in the light of a sense of
life and a third alternative - life to be valued negatively - can be put
into the moral balance along with the other two.
The RUB does not make
life and death decision-making easier and may make it harder but it does make it
more responsive to the hopes
and fears of any person faced with the mortal
perils that wait behind a hospital door. As a result, it becomes more likely
that what
we decide on that person’s behalf at the threshold of life is in
keeping with what that person would have written into the
story him or herself
as apprehended by an ethical participant equipped with a sense of life.
VI EUTHANASIA
In relation to the thorny issue of active voluntary euthanasia I feel deeply
hesitant in a way that I think of as being informed by
a sense of life so
that:
my own practice rests on the solid foundation of a commitment ...
to saving life, and this sustains me when I would be tempted to
settle for an
easier solution. ...I cannot, as things stand, envisage myself needing to be the
means of active euthanasia for any
patient, but I have a great deal of respect
for those whose humanity and care for their patient leaves them, they feel, no
alternative.
I do not envy
them.[23]
We are now able to
return to the idea of a sense of life and its use in clinical practice as a path
toward a more philosophical reflection
on human life and its value.
VII A SENSE OF LIFE IN THE MIDST OF THE CLINIC
One can think of a number of ways in which the sense of life as it
pertains to human subjects might inform our clinical lives. We
might, in the
light of Nussbaum’s writing, cultivate and not allow to slip away a sense
of life as a sense of the freshness
of what life brings and the way in which
life can refresh us and renew us when we are flagging or losing a sense of
‘what it
is all about’ or ‘whether it is all
worthwhile’. The sharing of our stories of inspiration, worth,
serendipity,
and courage in the face of adversity that find their expression in
each of us provide some indications as to how those things might
illuminate
clinical decisions.
A philosopher who has much to say to us here is
Emmanuel Levinas, himself indelibly inscribed by the events of the holocaust.
Levinas
notes that human faces reveal others who are not things, in fact they
are subjects each of whom lives in a world that is, in an important
sense, not
my world but who share my world with me. I encounter these other subjects who
mean something to me in a different way
by calling to me or reaching out to me.
They cannot therefore be definitively categorised or described because they
always present
themselves in ways that may surprise me and challenge me and
therefore they do not fit neatly into my conception of the world. The
being-present or ‘proximity’ of another person with which I become
acquainted more and more deeply as we enter into discourse,
signals to me that
my story of the world is not the only one and that there are different worlds
into which I might be introduced
if the people who live those worlds are
gracious enough to accept me. They tell me things about differently inspir[it]ed
worlds which
can never be mine but which can by my contact with them enrich me
in a way that nothing else ever could. That is why Levinas is moved
to say:
‘You shall not kill is ... the principle of discourse itself and of
spiritual life’. After the enormity of the
Holocaust, the power of this
remark is unmistakable. Diamantides remarks, generalising the point he finds in
Levinas: ‘Ethics,
of course, is not simply law, either in theory or
practice. But justice and law surely proceed from the ethical relation found in
proximity.’[24]
We
might be moved, at this juncture to speak in terms of the world of spirit - the
human spirit or the spirit of medicine - as something
transcendent of any given
human individual, drawing on the fact that for each one of us the face of the
other opens a ‘pore’/‘door’
from a personal world to a
differently inspir(it)ed world. The world of spirit would then, speaking
ontologically, be the set of
all inspir(it)ed worlds replete with the diverse
stories each human being brings to that shared world just by living and finding
meaning in their lives. It would then follow that the world of spirit is
diminished when any of its stories are lost or, to put it
differently, when the
life of any human being is cut off while their story is being written even
though, because we are finite or
mortal individuals, our stories do have endings
which can be more or less fitting (and are tragically unfitting in cases such as
the suicide of a young person).
So we can now speak of a sense of life
and the spirit informing the doctrine of sanctity of life complementing each
other. A sense
of life gives us a sense of life’s value and what it is
that makes a life valuable which is only appreciated as one lives and
encounters
other living human beings whose lives are not only distinct from my own but also
full of things that make them worth living.
Clint Eastwood’s character in
Unforgiven observes: ‘It’s a helluva thing you do when you
kill a man, you take away everything he has and everything he‘s
gonna
have.’ Expressing a sense of the value of life as incalculable (despite
the fact that the Talmud is prepared to fix the
price of the life of a person
taken by bandits at the equivalent of two year’s crops) and deserving of
deep respect because
irreplaceable in a way that is neatly encapsulate by his
pithy remark.
Levinas’ invocation of ‘Thou shalt not
kill’ as the principle of discourse and spiritual life now takes on
further
substance such that the very idea of ending a human life should always
give us pause[25] even where we are
sure that a sufficiency of the powerful considerations in favour of ending a
life ought to guide our decision.
A sense of life would seem an essential
qualification for ethicists involved in such decisions and in the formation of
policies and
procedures relating to them.
VIII INSPIR(IT)ED PERSONS WITH A SENSE OF LIFE.
I have argued that to judge well as ethicists we need ‘a sense of
life’, a characteristic that has several dimensions
which cannot easily be
defined but can be indicated as preparatory work for further
definition.
First, we ought to be finely attuned to others in that it is
in discourse and inter-subjectivity that we find the grounding for a
sense of
what is at stake in matters of life and death. This is the ground on which human
subjects are encountered, subjects who,
as Thielicke and Pope John Paul both
note, are the beings we are concerned about in ethical life. Human beings as
biological entities
have a status derivative from the subjective beings who, in
life, they are. Notice I have not said that our bodies are inhabited
by subjects
as if there were a thing – the ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’
– in principle separable from the
body even though certain discourses
indicate a ‘metaphysical’ distinction (cf Aristotle’s
distinction between form
and matter). I regard human beings as subjective bodies
or embodied subjectivities who are born of women, live entangled with our
environment, and exhibit a being-towards-death with more or less resolve. Our
sense of life attunes us to whole beings of that sort.
As subjects
attuned to our own (and others) being-in-the-world we should be deeply open to
discourse, not merely in order to catch
on to what others are saying out there,
nor merely as expectant listeners for the echoes of our own ‘take’
on life but
as mortal-beings-in-the-world-with-others caring (even
concerned) about the life-worlds of others and what stories and inspir(it)ations
they
bring to our shared world.
Attentive or attuned awareness of and
responsiveness to others as others makes us recognise and respond to mortality,
perhaps as instanced
in ‘the widow, the cripple, and the orphan’
(not as mere exemplars of types but) as embodied particular subjectivities
each
one of whom is a unique (and perhaps unquiet) piece of the spirit world of which
we all partake (or, to use Diamantides’
phrase, are in
proximity).
As these thoughts and attitudes inform our souls in ethics
and medical law, we can become individuals in possession of a developed
‘sense of life’ in Nussbaum’s sense. That should make us alert
to freshness, the unrepeatability of the moment,
the fragility of goodness as
lived by mortals, the need for desire to be properly informed, and to the care
of the self so as to
attend to the health of the soul through argument and
engagement with others in the light of spirit and truth.
If these
dimensions enter into the nature of our being, then our being becomes ethical
because they are intrinsically transformative.
The result of that transformation
is a being suffused with a sense of life in such a way that our understanding of
life, death and
human nature is likely to be more rather than less adequate to
the encounters with mortality that abound in the clinic.
[*]Grant Gillett, Neurosurgeon and Professor of
Medical Ethics, Dunedin Hospital and Otago Bioethics Centre, University of Otago
Medical
School, Dunedin PO Box 913 New Zealand grant.gillett(at)stonebow.otago.ac.nz
[1] M Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge (Oxford: University Press, 1990).
[2] A MacIntyre, After
Virtue (Notre Dame: University Press, 1984); T Engelhardt, The
Foundations of Bioethics (Oxford University Press, 1986).
[3] Nussbaum above n 2, 174.
[4] Ibid, 179.
[5] J P Sartre, Being and
Nothingness (Methuen & Co, 1958) 626.
[6] H Thielicke, The Doctor as
Judge of Who Shall Live and Who Shall Die (Fortress Press, 1970) 17.
[7] Ibid 15.
[8] Ibid 706.
[9] Ibid 712.
[10] The next section condenses
arguments to be found in my Bioethics in the Clinic: Hippocratic
Reflections (Johns Hopkins University Press,
2004).
[11] Thielicke above, as
in note 7.
[12] Grant Gillett,
‘Wittgenstein’s Startling Claim: Consciousness and the Persistent
Vegetative State’ in C Elliot
(ed), Slow Cures and Bad Philosophers:
Wiitgenstein, Medicine and Bioethics (2001)
70-88.
[13] Sartre above n 6,
433; D Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Clarendon,
1980).
[14] K Schrode,
‘Life in Limbo: Revising Policies for Permanently Unconscious
Patients’ (1995) 81(5) Houston Law Review
1609-68.
[15] Airedale NHS
Trust v Bland [1992] UKHL 5; [1993] AC 789 (Hoffman LJ).
[16] Auckland Area Health
Board v Attorney-General [1993] 1 NZLR
235.
[17] G Gillett, L Goddard
and M Webb, ‘The Case of Mr L: A Legal and Ethical Response to the Court
Sanctioned Withdrawal of Life-Support’
(1995) Journal of Law and
Medicine 3, 49-59.
[18]
In the Matter of a Ward of Court (1995) 2 ILRM 401-2.
[19] Re G [1996] NZFLR
362.
[20] Ibid 2 (Fraser J).
[21] Ibid 17.
[22] A Campbell, G Gillett and
G Jones, Medical Ethics (Oxford University Press, 4th ed,
2005) 12.
[23] Gillett, above n
11, 230-1.
[24] M Diamantides,
The ethics of suffering (Ashgate, 2000) 13.
[25] I have explored ‘the
pause’ in several pieces of work (see eg above n 11, Ch 12).
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2006/15.html