![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
![]() |
CURRENT CHALLENGES FOR THE DOCTRINE OF THE
SEPARATION OF POWERS – THE GHOSTS IN THE MACHINERY OF
GOVERNMENT
THE HON DEAN
WELLS[*]
Abstract
In Westminster systems the Doctrine of the Separation of Powers is a useful
tool for jurisprudential analysis provided it is applied
in the context of other
principles, like the sovereignty of Parliament and the independence of the
Judiciary. The power of Parliaments
to imprison people for Contempt, and the
propensity of Judicial activists to purport to determine the truth of what is
said in Parliament,
both threaten these principles, and erode democracy.
I INTRODUCTION
It is a great pleasure, not to mention a delicious irony, to come to the
University of the Real World to talk to you about the misconceptions
of a
Frenchman who lived three hundred years ago. You see, when Montesquieu wrote
L’Esprit des Lois and articulated the Doctrine of the Separation of
Powers, he thought he was describing the British Constitution. He wasn’t.
He described what appeared to be its structure, and failed to notice the
efficient secret of how the Westminster
constitution operated in the real world.
The American revolutionaries had read Montesquieu, and when they drew up the
constitution
of the USA they faithfully followed his constitutional
prescription, thinking that it was a guarantee of long term good government.
The end result was George W Bush, C’est la vie.
What
Montesquieu taught us is that there are three functions of government, or three
powers: the legislative, executive and judicial
powers: in our terms,
Parliament, Cabinet supported of course by the public service, and the courts.
The Parliament passes the laws, the Cabinet and public service
administer them and make decisions the laws have given them the power
to make,
and the courts decide whether the laws have been correctly followed in cases
brought before them. Let us look at some contrasts
between these functions.
The legislative function is essentially prospective, prescriptive and general.
Legislation usually decrees
that from a certain time, all persons in relevant
circumstances will behave in the way the legislation stipulates. The judicial
function is essentially retrospective, determinative and specific. The
pronouncement of a court is typically that at a certain time
in the past a
person or group of persons behaved in a way that breached the law. Because
legislation is prospective, prescriptive
and general, while adjudication is
retrospective, determinative and specific, our intuition is naturally drawn to
the diametrically
opposite functions, and attracts us to the thought that they
should be performed by different people with a different mindset.
The
executive function does not fit neatly into a third symmetrical position to
complement this framework of a duality of opposites.
The function is
essentially to execute – so the executive appoints people to statutory
posts, spends money appropriated by
Parliament, implements legislation passed by
Parliament and so on. Historically the executive, in the person of the King,
was the
unitary source of power from which the judicial and legislative powers
were peeled off. Of course, in the 21st century with some
exceptions, (for example the discretions of the Attorney-General and the Royal
Prerogative of Mercy,) the executive performs functions
delegated by Parliament.
Two conventions govern the day to day relationships between the
legislature, the executive and the judiciary in a Westminster system.
These are
the sovereignty of Parliament and the independence of the courts. The rationale
for Parliamentary sovereignty is in fact
the democratic principle itself. The
legislature is the only arm of government which the people directly choose. It
has to be constitutionally
supreme or democratic government will not exist.
Thus the Cabinet is supposed to perform its delegated functions taking care not
to usurp the functions of Parliament. For example the Legislative Standards
Act 1992 (Qld), which was introduced into the House by Premier Wayne Goss
but which I had the honour to see through its final reading on 21
May 1992,
adjures Ministers to avoid drafting legislation containing Henry VIII clauses,
which are clauses that allow the making
of regulations by the executive which
have the effect of directly or indirectly amending the Act itself. Meanwhile,
the second convention,
the independence of the judiciary, is an essential
prerequisite for fair trials, but the courts conduct their daily business
knowing
that while there will be no political interference in the case before
them, the convention of the sovereignty of Parliament means
that their
decisions, or the law on which their decisions are based, may be reversed or
altered by an Act of Parliament.
The existence of three functions does
not, by itself, entail that there are, or ought to be, three different machines
to perform them.
The existence of radio, recorded music and timekeeping does not
entail that my radio/cassette/alarm clock does not, or ought not
to exist.
Having separate institutions to perform the legislative executive and judicial
functions, however desirable it may be,
needs to be argued for rather than
simply assumed. Therefore, it would not be enough to condemn a practice to
point out that it
breached the Separation of Powers. It is not self evident
that all such practices are suboptimal. If, for example, Montesquieu
had ever
been hit by the blinding revelation that in Westminster systems the executive
actually controls the legislative programme
of the Parliament or that the
Parliament has the ability to sack Cabinet, this would not be enough to found a
plausible argument
against the practise. You would need also to show that there
was some detriment attached to this breach of the Separation of Powers.
If it
mitigated the sovereignty of Parliament, or derogated from the independence of
the judiciary, that would be an argument.
A symbiotic relationship between the
architect and the builder is no threat to construction standards; but it would
be a serious
threat to have the builder altering the architect’s designs,
or for either the builder or the architect to be in a cosy relationship
with the
building tribunal.
The argument for independence of the judiciary is
obvious, and regarded as conclusive in the Westminster world by intelligent MPs
on both sides of politics. If the judicial function of interpreting the laws is
performed by different people from those who legislate
them, the laws are likely
to be applied more objectively and impartially. In other words, you are more
likely to get a fair trial.
History shows that if the people who prospectively
enact the laws, deciding what thou shalt not do, are also the people who
retrospectively
determine whether thou hast done it, it is all too easy for them
to confuse the question of whether they would like you to be in
jail with the
somewhat different question of whether you had actually committed a jailable
offence. To put it simply, the legislators
are, of necessity, partisan
politicians; judges don’t have to be.
Good reasons for an
independent executive are harder to find. Why, after all, would you want the
Cabinet to be beyond the scrutiny
of your local Member? Montesquieu, who was
followed by George Washington, Thomas Jefferson and that crew, wanted to have
two separate
mobs of elected politicians in order to provide ‘checks and
balances’. That phrase, ‘checks and balances’
is code for
‘brake on radical reform’ - that is to say a built-in conservative
bias in the constitution. Walter Bagehot,
the 19th century British
jurist who debunked Montesquieu, said that the ‘efficient secret’ of
the Westminster constitution
was that the Executive and the Legislature are not
really separate. The Parliament, or a majority of it selects the Cabinet and
because they are therefore not at odds with one another they can comparatively
easily despatch the business the public expected them
to do when they voted to
put them there.
The Doctrine of the Separation of Powers and its
relevance to Westminster political theory became dinner table conversation in
Queensland
in 1988 when someone asked former Queensland Premier, Joh Bjelke
Petersen, about it. It happened during the Fitzgerald Inquiry that
uncovered
widespread corruption in the Queensland government and Police Force and led to
seven Ministers, a Police Commissioner and
various other unjustly rich and
deservedly famous persons being charged with offences of dishonesty and
corruption. A young barrister,
Michael Forde, (who inevitably became Judge
Forde) was inspired to ask Bjelke Petersen, “What do you understand by the
Doctrine
of the Separation of Powers in the Westminster system?” Bjelke
Petersen didn’t have a clue. In that one moment of blithering
incomprehension he did more for civics education that he had done in nearly
twenty years as Premier. From Coolangatta to Thursday
Island, people were
asking each other between gusts of laughter, for their thoughts on the Doctrine
of the Separation of Powers in
the Westminster system. If you wanted to have
any political credibility it was also necessary to know the answer.
What Bjelke Petersen should have been able to tell the Commission of
Inquiry was that in Westminster democracies the separation of
powers is complete
as far as the judiciary is concerned – judges have to be beyond political
interference from Parliament or
government – but the legislative and
executive powers are not separate in the way they are in non Westminster
systems. In
Westminster systems the executive ie the Cabinet, is part of the
legislature. The Ministers are all Members of Parliament, and they
are
accountable to Parliament and can be sacked by Parliament.
By contrast,
in non Westminster systems, like the USA, the Executive i.e. the President, and
whoever he chooses to appoint as Secretaries
of State (ie Ministers), are not
members of the legislature: they don’t have to account to the legislature
for what they do,
and when the executive is one party and the majority of the
legislature is another, life becomes interesting, and occasionally, though
rarely, the business of government grinds to a halt. This happened in 1995/6
when a Republican Congress refused to pass President
Clinton’s money bills
to stop him spending so much on social welfare. Many public service agencies
closed, and 300,000 public
servants stayed home for months. The framers of the
U.S. Constitution deliberately created the possibility of disunity of purpose
between the legislature and the executive. This kind of scenario is
one result
of inserting such “checks and balances” into the constitution.
Another was Watergate.
Gough Whitlam once remarked that a Watergate
scenario could not occur in a country where the executive was responsible to the
legislature,
and subject to Question Time daily.
The lack of a complete
separation between executive and legislature in Westminster constitutions means
that a government that decides
to grasp the nettle can actually do things.
Because our Cabinets are chosen from Members of Parliament, the Cabinet has to
be the
group that has the numbers in the Parliament. Unlike an American
President, an Australian or New Zealand Prime Minister or an Australian
State
Premier doesn’t spend a lot of time wondering whether government policy is
going to be knocked over in the Lower House.
It does happen here, but very
rarely. It usually takes that other check and balance, an Upper House, to
deliver that sort of paralysis.
Just to summarise so far, we do not have
a Montesquieu style or even an American style separation of powers in the
Westminster system.
The separation is most complete in respect of the
judiciary, but even between the executive and the legislature, there are
conventions,
particularly the convention of the sovereignty of Parliament, which
governs what is a matter for Cabinet and what is a matter for
Parliament. The
modus vivendi could easily be upset. For example, judges could, en
masse, set out to make new law rather than simply to find the law. Or
Cabinet could deliberately set out to use its subordinate legislation
power to
undercut the intentions of Parliament. Or the Legislature could go to town on
the establishment of Commissions of Inquiry
so as to undercut the judicial
sphere. For the separation of powers to work in the Westminster system, there
has to be a certain
degree of restraint, and the executive, the legislature and
the judiciary have to respect each other’s territory. This is
known as
the Principle of Mutual Restraint. It is referred to, for example, in the
speech of Lord Browne-Wilkinson in the Privy
Council case of Prebble v.
Television New Zealand.[1] His
Lordship says, ‘There is a long line of authority which supports a wider
principle... that the Courts and Parliament
are both astute to recognise their
respective constitutional roles.’ When the principle is being carefully
observed the institutions
of government tend to concentrate on what they do best
and stay off each other’s turf. Recently there have been some very
significant incidents in which the Principle of Mutual Restraint has been
disregarded. These incidents evoke ghosts from our unsavoury
past. I will go
on to identify three of these ghosts in the machinery of government.
II THE GHOST OF THE HIGH COURT OF PARLIAMENT
The independence of the judiciary is universally accepted in the sense
that everyone agrees that there should be no interference with
a Judge
determining a case. However there is nothing in our Constitution, or in the
statutory or constitutional environment of Westminster systems, or even other
democracies, that prevents other parts of
the Constitution from aping and
purporting to exercise judicial functions.
For example on 18 May 2004, in
the Parliament of Zimbabwe, an incident occurred that shows how bad this can
get. The Minister for
Justice, the Honourable Patrick Chinamasa, was speaking
to the Stock Theft Amendment Bill, when he launched a personal attack on
the Member for Chimanimani, the Honourable Roy Bennet. The Minister said,
‘Honourable
Bennet has never forgiven this government for seeking to
redistribute this land. He forgets that his forefathers were thieves and
that
what he owns – is an inheritance of stolen wealth accumulated over a
century and a half.’ In the deadpan style
of Hansard everywhere, the
Zimbabwe Hansard record notes, ‘Hon Bennet charged towards Honourable
Chinamasa and shoved him to
the floor.’
The matter was referred to
the Parliamentary Privileges Committee, which was constituted by two Government
Members, two Opposition
Members, and a nominee of the President, Robert Mugabe.
Bennett was found to be in contempt by a predictable majority of three to
two,
and the House accepted the Committee’s recommendation of 15 month’s
hard labour. Recourse to the courts did not
assist him – it was after all
a decision of the Parliament, which remains sovereign whether it is rorted or
gerrymandered or
not. There is no legal mechanism for an appeal against pseudo
judicial decisions of Parliaments here either. To no avail Amnesty
International campaigned hard to secure his release. I raised the issue in the
Queensland Parliament on 9 March 2005. On that occasion
I said, ‘His
parliamentary colleagues were his judge, jury and executioner and every one of
them had a vested political interest
in the outcome of the vote.’
Eventually on 28 June 2005 he was released on parole, after serving a proportion
of his sentence
that would have entitled him to be released under Zimbabwe law
even if the rest of the world had not protested.
Could this happen here?
Yes, it could – except for New South Wales the Parliaments of Australia
and New Zealand have the power
to sit in judgement on and punish their own
members, or their own constituents. Originally the colonial Parliaments, and in
particular
Queensland Parliament did not have such powers. Judicial powers were
always part of the intrinsic jurisdiction of the British Parliament,
which was
once called, and archaically may still be referred to, as the High Court of
Parliament. In Mediaeval times, when the
King held Court, he made judicial
decisions. Over the centuries those functions were delegated, and by the 1830s
the separation
of powers between legislature and judiciary was so much the
status quo that the Privy Council held, that a colonial legislature did
not have an inherent power to order the arrest of a stranger. In the
case of
Kielley v Carson[2] the Court
held that while the House of Commons and the House of Lords used to be the High
Court of Parliament, colonial legislatures
had no such history, and therefore no
inherent jurisdiction to punish, but only the power to deal with impediments to
the ‘due
course of proceedings’. Significantly the Court held that,
To the full extent of every measure which it may be really necessary to
adopt, to secure the free exercise of their legislative functions,
they are
justified in acting by the principle of the common law. But the power of
punishing anyone for past misconduct as a contempt
of its authority, and
adjudicating upon the fact of such contempt, and the measure of punishment as a
judicial body, irresponsible
to the party accused, whatever the real facts may
be, is of a very different character, and by no means essentially necessary for
the exercise of its functions by a local Legislature.
The response of
colonial MPs to this wise decision was, as you might expect, to reverse it.
They hastened to give themselves power
to sit in judgement on each other and on
those they served. Often they have, for example in 1870 the South Australian
Parliament
sent Sergeant Major Patrick McBride to jail for one week for sending
a letter to a Member of Parliament alleging that he had lied.
In 1994 the
Western Australian Parliament imprisoned Brian Easton for one week for sending
to Parliament a petition containing
allegations against other private citizens.
In 1955 the Australian Parliament sent Raymond Fitzpatrick and Frank Browne to
jail
for 90 days for alleging that a member had engaged in corrupt schemes
relating to refugee migration.
In Queensland the power is now defined
by the Constitution Act and the Parliament of Queensland Act 2001
(Qld). What it comes to is that your elected representatives have the power
to fine each other, or you, if the mood takes them, but
probably not the power
to put you in prison directly. To acquire that address however, you would only
need to refuse to pay the
fine, as any conscientious objector, whether an MP or
a stranger to the House, would.
This is not a fanciful scenario. The
pseudo-judicial power has not been used in Queensland for a long time, but it
has not fallen
into desuetude. On Wednesday 8 November 2005, the Speaker
said,
I do not believe the House can any longer tolerate the persistent and
continued disrespect for and attacks on the authority of the
Speaker...
Therefore I have referred to the [Privileges] Committee... the numerous reported
reflections on the Chair ... In doing
so, I note that reflections upon and
disrespect to presiding officers on account of their actions in the House may
constitute a contempt.
Erskine May’s 22nd edition at page 123
states – .reflections on the character of the Speaker or accusations of
partiality
in the discharge of his duties ... have attracted the penal powers of
the Commons.
The point of the Speaker’s reference to the penal
sanctions of the House of Commons is that when Queensland Standing Orders
are
silent on a point, Common’s practices and precedents are followed. In the
event, the Privileges Committee, in their infinite
goodness and mercy, did not
take the opportunity to jail dissidents. The point is that they could have.
The matter is just so not
hypothetical.
Westminster Parliaments ought
to divest themselves of this power to deal punitively with their own citizens.
There are a dozen arguments,
all of them conclusive as to why we should abandon
this dangerous and odious capacity. Firstly, MPs are elected with a mandate to
implement a philosophy. They are voted in because the people of their
electorate, having considered the ideas of the parties or
candidates presented
to them, preferred one programme to another. The people gave the Members no
mandate to be a judge or a jury
in a specific case. Indeed they never turned
their mind to specific cases. Secondly, when MPs sit in judgement on a matter
like
the Roy Bennet case, or the Australian instances just mentioned, they all
have a vested political interest in the result. The ghost
of the High Court of
Parliament, wherever it makes its apparition in the antipodes, will nearly
always deliver a violation of the
principles of natural justice. Members of
Parliament, when sitting in judgement, will almost always find themselves
judging matters that in a courtroom, a judicial officer so placed, would be
disqualified from hearing. Thirdly, as we noted, the
legislative function is
prospective, prescriptive and general, while the judicial function is
retrospective, determinative and specific.
The mindset of one, whose vocation
in life is to dream possible dreams and to get public servants to make them
happen, is not generally
apt for the performance of judicial functions. Not for
no reason are the practices of our courts surrounded by thousands of rules
of
evidence and procedure designed to minimise error and protect the liberty of the
citizen. When a matter is tried by parliamentarians
rather than Judges, we
throw away all these safeguards. We forfeit the benefit of having an
individual’s liberty determined
by the dispassionate, if not cynical,
minds of people dedicated to determining accurately the facts, whose
life’s work is to
decide what is rather than what ought to be, and expose
that citizen’s liberty to the momentary whims and inclinations of a
mob of
dreamers whose very job description requires them to paint with a broad brush,
whose whole value to their society lies not
in any pretence to specialist skill
in matters particular, but rather in their capacity to articulate the competing
ideas between
which the voters will choose in the hope of fashioning a better
world. Fourthly, in a democracy MPs are supposed to be the servants
of the
people. They cannot consistently be their judges. Fifthly anyone imprisoned by
Parliament will be technically, but by definition,
a prisoner of conscience (to
use the language of international diplomacy) because nobody imprisoned by
Parliament will have been
charged and convicted of a specific breach of the
criminal law. I could go on but the point is made. We ought to abolish this
power
now. The only reason we still have it is bone headed conservatism and the
lack of a recent local abuse of the power to spark the
necessary change.
III THE GHOST OF TORQUEMADA
The conclusion that you ought to extract confessions by torture from
heretics and witches, and burn them to death on the stake is
one that you can
arrive at perfectly logically if you merely assume the insane first premise that
you are the infallible possessor
of the ultimately true view of the world.
Democracy however assumes that nobody is infallible, and that all views
of the world are in principle capable of becoming government
policy, subject
only to democratic votes. Democracy requires that all points of view ought to
be allowed to be expressed, albeit
with safeguards to protect the reputation of
citizens. This is the fundamental reason for the parliamentary privilege of
free speech.
In the case of Prebble v. TV New
Zealand[3] the Privy Council held
that a Member of Parliament could not waive parliamentary privilege because the
parliamentary privilege of
free speech is not primarily a privilege of the
Members of Parliament who exercise it, but a privilege of the Parliament itself.
It was the representative body, not the individual member who possessed the
privilege.
Thus absolute privilege exists for the benefit of electors,
not the elect. It is a safety valve which ensures that propositions someone
in
the community believes, whether true or false, and opinions someone in the
community holds, whether popular or unpopular, can
be expressed. It is for the
people, not for the Grand Inquisitor, to judge whether these propositions are
true or false, and it
is for the people to make these opinions popular or
unpopular. In a well functioning democracy the people are the arbiters of what
is true or what will be popular. The parliamentary privilege of free speech
is the privilege of the people to hear the truth or
its opposite spoken, and to
re-elect or sack those who speak it. The so-called cowards’ castle is
actually the people’s
crucible. It enables the people rather than the
Grand Inquisitor to be the judge of the value of what is spoken.
In a
case finalised the year before last, applying and extending Australian
precedents, the New Zealand courts, in the case of Buchanan v.
Jennings, gave themselves the power to determine litigation relating to
certain proceedings of Parliament. Jennings made allegations in the
Parliament,
to the effect that a member of the Wool Board had made certain corrupt deals to
procure an international commercial benefit.
Such things of course would never
happen in Australia, but if they did, Australian courts would be under pressure
to follow the
precedent. Outside Parliament,
Jennings[4] was questioned by the
media as to what he said. He indicated that he wasn’t going to repeat the
allegations outside of Parliament
but that he stood by what he had said inside
the House. The court found that he had ‘effectively repeated’ what
he had
said inside Parliament.
The truth or otherwise of what he had
said in the House was therefore capable of being determined by the court as if
he had said it
outside of the House. He was liable for damages and paid
$50,000. The decision of the New Zealand Court of Appeal in this matter
was
upheld in the Privy Council. There is a rumour to the effect that this had
nothing to do with the fact that the New Zealand
Parliament has now abolished
appeals to the Privy Council.
The Privileges Committee of the New
Zealand Parliament reported on these events last year. It identified the
following ‘issues’.
First the decision involves courts in assessing
and adjudging parliamentary proceeding. This, the report says, breaks down the
‘long standing principle of mutual restraint’. Second, it has an
effect on free speech itself. Both MPs and witnesses
before committees may
avoid saying what they believe to be true, for fear of legal reprisal. Third,
it has a chilling effect on
public debate. Members of Parliament and private
citizens who are witnesses to Parliamentary Committees will be reluctant to
submit
themselves to subsequent media interview for fear that a legal stratagem
will be found to hold them accountable for things they said
under absolute
privilege. Fourth, it has an effect far beyond defamation. If the Doctrine of
Effective Repetition justifies courts
in probing into the proceedings of
Parliament in respect of defamation proceedings, why not every crime and civil
wrong that is committed
by the use of words? For example, breach of
confidentiality, sedition, incitement, obscenity, and contempt of court.
Further what
logical reason could there be to confine it to parliamentary
proceedings? All those involved in court proceedings also have absolute
privilege. Yet statements made in court are as capable of being effectively
repeated as statements made in Parliament. The logical
extension of the
Doctrine of Effective Repetition would make our courts, as well as our
Parliaments, unworkable. According to the
Clerk of the New Zealand Parliament,
and author of Parliamentary Practice in New Zealand, David McGee, the slide down
the slippery
slope to the logical conclusion of unworkability has already begun.
As an example he points to Court of Appeal obiter dicta in the
Jennings case to the effect that Judicial Review is an exception to
parliamentary privilege (personal communication).
A new found capacity of
the courts to come into Parliament and litigate the truth of what is said there
constitutes not only an erosion
of the separation of powers, but a threat to our
democracy as well. The very notion of representative democracy requires that
the
people, through their elected representatives, not an unelected body,
however benign, should have the final say over what can be
said and done. It
will be necessary for all Australasian jurisdictions to pay serious attention to
the options available. These
options include abolishing the Doctrine of
Effective Repetition, which is what the New Zealand Privileges Committee
recommends.
We should do that too. The Doctrine is a dangerous piece
of judicial adventurism, and needs to be quashed.
IV THE GHOST OF THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS
(Author’s note: In May 2006, after this lecture was
delivered at QUT, but before the date of this publication, the Parliament of
Queensland removed Section 57 from the Criminal Code. Section IV of this
article is thus an argument to do something that has in fact now been done. The
media
denounced the removal of Section 57 as a move to allow politicians to lie
to Parliament, and this is how most Queenslanders will
remember the event. I
have left Section IV in as it provides a fascinating perspective on the gap
which sometimes exists between
popular perceptions, and the gravity and
actuality of what is sometimes at stake.
Note that the former MP at the
centre of these events is, at the time of publication facing other very grave
charges. This discussion
has nothing to do with those allegations. His
innocence or guilt regarding those matters has no bearing on the constitutional
issues
discussed here.)
The sovereignty of Parliament was
hard won. The early Stuart monarchs, King James I and King Charles I, believed
that they governed
by divine right. On 3 January 1642 King Charles I came with
a large squad of soldiers to Parliament with the intention of arresting
five of
the Members. When he could not see them there, the King is said to have
commented ‘The birds have flown,’ and
to have asked the Speaker
where they were. The Speaker is said to have replied, ‘I have neither
eyes to see, nor voice to
speak in this place but as the House is pleased to
direct me’. The King and the Speaker both walked away from this
encounter, but the King had signed his own death warrant. Two revolutions and
a
regicide later, in 1688, the Bill of Rights was passed. Article 9 of
that bill said that the proceedings of Parliament could not be impeached outside
of Parliament.
Three centuries and 16,000 kilometres away from those
events, in a Westminster system that had preserved Article 9 of the Bill of
Rights, a Member of Parliament was put in peril of his liberty on an
allegation that something that he said to a Parliamentary committee was
untrue.
Gordon Nuttall, the Member for Sandgate, and at the time the Minister for
Health, was alleged to have lied to the Parliamentary
Estimates Committee,
thereby breaching section 57 of the Criminal Code which
reads:
57 False evidence before Parliament
(1) Any person who
in the course of an examination before the Legislative Assembly, or before a
committee of the Legislative Assembly,
knowingly gives a false answer to any
lawful and relevant question put to the person in the course of the examination
is guilty of
a crime, and is liable to imprisonment for 7 years.
The rest
of the statutory environment is of interest because the Member for Sandgate
could only be seen as a possible target for investigation
for the commission of
an offence under section 57 if other provisions were overridden by section 57.
Section 8 of the Parliament of Queensland Act 2001 (Qld)
reads:
8 Assembly proceeding can not be impeached or
questioned
(1) The freedom of speech and debates or proceeding in the
Assembly can not be impeached or questioned in any court or place out of
the
Assembly.
(2) To remove doubt, it is declared the subsection (1) is intended
to have the same effect as Article 9 of the Bill of Rights (1688).
Meanwhile section 13B of the Acts Interpretation Act 1954
(Qld) says:
13B Acts not to effect powers, rights or immunities of
Legislative
Assembly except by express provision
(1) An Act
enacted after the commencement of the section affects the powers, rights or
immunities of the Legislative Assembly or of
its members or committees only so
far as the Act expressly provides.
The questions of law here,
particularly the question of whether section 57 can in this context been seen as
overriding other statutes
and conventions is an interesting one. So, of course,
is the question of fact. If a prosecution were to be brought it would necessary
to show that beyond all reasonable doubt the statement made by the then Minister
was knowingly false. In its report the Crime and
Misconduct Commission
(“CMC”) rehearses considerable material that might be adduced
as evident that the statement was false. But when it comes to the
question of
whether it was knowingly false, little is said in the report. In the
penultimate paragraph of its report dated December
2005 the CMC writes,
‘There is, however, clearly a question appropriate to resolution by a
tribunal of fact whether the Minister’s
answers to the crucial questions
by Mr Copeland were knowingly false.’ If this statement indicates
that the CMC regarded the absence of evidence as a reason for going to court to
try to
find some rather than as a reason for dropping the case, let us hope that
our prosecutors are not attracted to this novel idea.
Interesting as the
issues of fact and law are in this matter, the jurisprudential questions it
raises are even more fascinating.
Had the matter proceeded to trial, it
would have been dealt with by a Court. The central issue of fact would have
been whether what
the Minister said was false. In other words it would have
involved the same issues as we canvassed in the discussion of the issue
of
republication above. The Parliament, and therefore the people, would have lost
the capacity to make the determination as to what
would be received as true.
That decision would have been made by experts – much more benign experts
that Torquemada, but playing
like him the role of arbiter of what may be
received as true. Even more interesting than the potential involvement of the
judiciary
in the legislative process, is the actual involvement of the
executive. The investigation was
undertaken by the CMC, which is part of
the executive arm of Government. There were, of course, many differences
between the intervention
of King Charles I in 1642, and the intervention of the
CMC in 2005. The main difference was that the CMC was wielding a statute
rather
than a sword. The other differences related mainly to costume, dramatisation
and choreography. The issue was the same –
whether a person elected by
the people to speak for them in Parliament was to lose his liberty as a result
only of the manner in
which he did so.
There is not in Queensland a great
reservoir of sympathy for politicians who get themselves into trouble. What
else would you expect
from a society that evolved from a convict colony where
the jailers were the government? The healthy and robust cynicism which
Queenslanders
have about those who govern them was exemplified by a constituent
of mine recently. On being told that the CMC had activated a little
known
section of the Criminal Code which made it a crime to tell lies within
the Parliament, and that the most likely casualties of this section were going
to be Members
of Parliament themselves, he was heard to respond, ‘well it
couldn’t happen to a nicer pack of bastards’. People
who divert
themselves with such thoughts however might well pause to reflect that this
process involves the passing of power from
people they control to people they do
not control. When Members of Parliament are able to speak freely then the only
worthwhile
judgement that can be made of the truth of what is said are the
judgements that the electors make at election time.
However, when
Members of Parliament are having the truth or otherwise of their utterances
determined by the executive or by the courts,
it is clear that the people no
longer are in control. Nightmare scenarios of how an unscrupulous executive
might use the recently
discovered power it has to investigate the truth of what
is said in Parliament can be left to fiction writers to come up with. You
could
however make a pretty good political thriller out of this material.
Let
us note however that section 57 does not address itself only to politicians.
Any person who addresses a Parliamentary Committee
and fails to tell the truth
is liable for a penal sanction. This is a rather embarrassing provision to have
on the statute books
for a government that is committed to encouraging
participation in the processes of representative government. Our panoply of
Community
Cabinet meetings, regional sittings of the Parliament, consultative
programs, and frequent invitations to large numbers of people
to give evidence
before Parliamentary Committees, indicates a degree of welcome which is belied
by the statutory environment into
which these willing participants in our
democratic processes come. Perhaps we should tell people who come to give
evidence at a
Parliamentary Committee meeting that they are putting their
liberty at risk.
It’s not hard to imagine the scenario in which
somebody could become a victim of this section. Say there was a meeting of the
Public Accounts Committee in some regional part of the State. Say it was
investigating the most efficient way of doing something
and representatives of a
particular company gave evidence that it could be done in such and such a way.
Say that representatives
of some rival company, in order to gain an economic
advantage, or publicity, or simply out of spite, alleged that they had told the
Committee something that was false, and that it was wilfully so, then the whole
process would start rolling. Maybe so long as we
have section 57 of the
Criminal Code on our statute books we should give invitees to hearings of
Parliamentary Committees a piece of paper to sign saying that they note
that
they are there at peril of their liberty. Or perhaps we could put a sign over
the portals of our nationally applauded participatory
Parliament ‘Abandon
hope all ye who enter here’.
The fact is that we don’t need
section 57 of the Criminal Code. There is a well recognised and well
understood means of placing pressure on people to tell the truth. That is to
ask them to swear
an oath. If people in a democracy choose to put themselves at
risk of their liberty by swearing an oath that is a matter of their
personal
choice; but it is outrageous that they should automatically be put at peril of
their liberty by simply participating in
democratic processes. Whether a
private citizen takes an oath inside a Parliamentary Committee or elsewhere,
doing so allows the
investigative arms of the executive, and the deliberative
tribunals of the judiciary to operate within their appropriate sphere.
There
should be no risk of sanction attendant simply on partaking in the processes of
our democracy. A sanction incurred by swearing
an oath, a sanction that can
apply anywhere, is much more appropriate.
It is interesting to note why
it is that we have this section in our Criminal Code. The paradox is
that the Member for Sandgate was put in peril of his liberty in respect of a
provision the Parliament voted, without
controversy to abolish in 1995. In the
first half of the 1990s the Goss government undertook a root and branch
re-examination of
the Criminal Code. That was done with the assistance
of the Criminal Code Review Committee consisting of Rob O’Regan QC, Jim
Herlihy and Michael
Quinn. Its recommendations became a Bill for a new
Criminal Code for Queensland. I introduced that Bill into the
Parliament in May 1995 and it contained no provision equivalent to section 57.
The reasons why are covered above.
There were many controversial
aspects to the new Criminal Code Bill 1995 (Qld). The deletion of
the equivalent of section 57 was not one of them. There was no debate in the
Parliament about this matter
and it did not become an issue that it was to be
deleted. The Criminal Code Bill 1995 (Qld) became the Criminal Code
Act and received royal assent from Her Excellency the Governor in 1995. It
was not however at that time proclaimed. The reason for
that was that its
proclamation needed to go hand in hand with the proclamation of a new Simple
Offences Act, and the Bill for that
was not ready. Further consultation and
fine tuning on that comparatively minor piece of legislation would have taken
another few
months. However, at that point an election intervened. In the
subsequent ministerial reshuffle I was relegated for a short period
to the
backbench, and my successor as Attorney-General was left with the responsibility
of completing the Simple Offences Bill and
introducing it into the House. Six
months later a by-election caused a change of government. The Simple Offences
Bill had not been introduced. The new government, being a conservative
government, did not approve of root and branch reforms. Conservative
philosophy
dictates that you build on what you have rather than tear it down and start
again. You may graft new growth, but you
do not destroy the organism and plant
a new one. Accordingly they repealed the Criminal Code Act 1995 (Qld).
As a result, section 57 remains part of our law. A number of amendments were
introduced to the Criminal Code Act 1899 (Qld) at the same time in 1996
as the Criminal Code Act 1995 (Qld) was repealed. Some of them
implemented reforms presaged in the Criminal Code Act 1995 (Qld).
However, in the spirit of conservative law reform, only those matters that were
seen as urgent or necessary in the circumstances
of the day were amended. No
attention was given to section 57. As a result, section 57, though it had been
repealed in 1995, again
became an unnoticed part of the furniture of the house
we live in without anybody ever actually turning their mind to
it.
Clearly we ought to get rid of this undemocratic provision. There
may be some in our community who feel that they would be able to
construct an
argument to the effect it is desirable that non elected officials should be
appointed to sit in judgement on the truth
value of what elected officials say.
Perhaps they could even come up with some argument to the effect that it is much
more democratic
that an impartial umpire who has never been contaminated with
the mandate of the people should judge the results of political debates.
Perhaps they could deploy the argument used by Adolf Hitler when he was accused
by the fading German opposition in the 1930s of
showing bias because he had
banned political parties. On that occasion the Fuhrer said, ‘I am not
biased. I have banned them
all’.
Don’t get me wrong. A
totalitarian state is a long way down the track from a situation where the
executive arm of government
can investigate legislators elected by citizens to
speak for them in Parliament, simply and only for the manner in which they do
so. An awfully long way down the track. But that is the track.
V CONCLUSION
To sum up, there is no magic to the Doctrine of the Separation of Powers.
It is not a mantra whose incantation will automatically
discredit a practice.
Backed however, by other principles we hold dear, like the sovereignty of
Parliament, which is basic to representative
democracy itself, and the
independence of the judiciary, the separation of powers is a useful and potent
instrument for jurisprudential
analysis.
It is clear from the examples we
have just considered that the principle of mutual restraint is not being
observed. Politicians are
making or remain empowered to make pseudo judicial
decisions, judges in New Zealand are making and judges here are at risk of being
drawn into making decisions about the truth value of statements made in
parliament, and in Queensland we have an independent statutory
authority, which
is part of the executive, investigating a legislator elected by the people to
speak for them, only for the manner
in which he did so. The principle of mutual
restraint is not being adequately observed in the Westminster world. The
institutions
of government in the Westminster world ought to behave with more
self discipline than this. Where they fail to be, in Lord
Browne-Wilkinson’s
words, ‘astute to recognise their respective
constitutional roles’, it is up to the lawyers to tell them to be.
[*] Dean Wells MA, LLB, MP,
Lecture given at Queensland University of Technology on 26 April
2006.
[1] [1994] All E. R. 407,
413.
[2] (1841-42) 1V Moo PC
63.
[3] [1994] All E. R. 407.
[4]
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2006/6.html