Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal |
INHERENT DEFECTS AND THE REPAIR COVENANT IN
COMMERCIAL LEASES
DR ANDREW
MCGEE [*]
I INTRODUCTION
Does the covenant to repair in a commercial lease include an obligation
to put right an inherent defect in the building, if that inherent
defect causes
the building concerned to fall into a state of disrepair? Or is it the case
that, whoever bears the obligation of repair
under the relevant covenant, that
person need only remove the damage caused by the inherent defect, without
removing that inherent
defect itself? What happens if the only way the damage
can be remedied is by removing the inherent defect? Does such work still
constitute
‘repair’, or does it amount to ‘renewal’ and
so fall outside the repair covenant?
There has been an abundance of case
law on this topic,[1] yet the
position, at least in Australia, remains unclear. Indeed, although the current
position in the UK is clear, it will be argued
here that much of subsequent
judicial construction of the early cases in the UK is vulnerable to criticism,
and that this might constitute
a ground for taking an alternative approach in
Australia, particularly in light of the fact that the UK position arguably leads
to
unjust results where the bearer of the repair obligation is the
tenant.[2]
In the following
section, the respective UK and Australian positions are briefly
outlined.[3] I then review the UK
position in more detail, focusing, in particular, on judicial construction of
the early cases, to see if there
has been an unnoticed change in the UK
position, a position which takes itself to be founded on the early cases but one
which, in
fact, arguably departs from them. In the conclusion, I suggest that it
might be better for Australia to take a different track.
II THE COVENANT TO REPAIR IN THE UK AND AUSTRALIA
A Repair and Renewal Distinguished
Before reviewing the authorities in detail (a task reserved for section
4), it will be convenient to state the principle adopted with
respect to repair
in the UK. The bearer of the obligation to maintain a building ‘in good
condition’ or ‘tenantable
repair’, or simply
‘repair’,[4] is not under
an obligation to renew the whole or substantially the whole of the
building.[5] If it were otherwise, he
or she would effectively be giving the landlord back a different thing from that
which was taken under the
lease.[6] It
is obvious enough, of course, that ‘repair’ inevitably involves some
renewal, and that the distinction between repair
and renewal must be drawn, not
by reference to parts of the building, but by reference to the whole or
substantially the whole of
it, in order for the distinction between repair and
renewal to acquire a grip and so be given a sense. If the distinction were to
be
applied to parts, rather than the whole or substantially the whole, the
distinction between repair and renewal would be untenable,
because repair
inescapably requires some renewal. The application of the distinction is well
illustrated by the comments of Buckley
LJ in Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler[7] in the following
passage:
A skylight leaks; repair is effected by hacking out the
putties, putting in new ones, and renewing the paint. A roof falls out of
repair; the necessary work is to replace the decayed timbers by sound wood; to
substitute sound tiles or slates for those which are
cracked, broken, or
missing; to make good the flashings, and the like. Part of a garden wall tumbles
down; repair is effected by
building it up again with new mortar, and, so far as
necessary, new bricks or stone. Repair is restoration by renewal or
replacement of subsidiary parts of a whole. Renewal, as distinguished from
repair, is reconstruction
of the entirety, meaning by entirety not necessarily
the whole but substantially the whole subject matter under
discussion.[8]
Whether the work required in a particular case constitutes renewal or
replacement of the whole/substantially the whole (and so falls
outside the
repair covenant), or renewal or replacement merely of defective parts, and so
repair, is a question of degree.[9]
For this reason, the distinction between repair and renewal will in some cases
be blurry – some cases will fall at the borderline.
In such cases, it will
be a matter of judgement. Perhaps the addition of the words ‘or
substantially’ to ‘the whole’
make this even more so,
introducing a broader range of different fact scenarios which might be decided
differently, depending on
the intuitions of the particular judge whose
responsibility it is to decide the issue in a particular case. This has arguably
led
to some inconsistencies in application of the principle in the
UK.[10] As noted by Antra Hood, the
test is ‘deceptively
simple’.[11] Perhaps an
indication of the deceptive nature of this simplicity is the fact that no less
than three different tests (all arguably differing only in verbal
formulae) are to be found in the authorities. Mustill LJ expounds the tests
in
McDougall v Easington District
Council[12] as follows:
(i) whether the alterations went to the whole or substantially the whole
of the structure or only to a subsidiary part;
(ii) whether the effect of the
alteration was to produce a building of a wholly different character from that
which has been let;
(iii) what was the cost of the works in relation to the
previous value of the building, and what was their effect on the value and
lifespan of the building?
It is not my intention to analyse the
‘surprising results’ of the application of these tests referred to
by Antra Hood.[13] Instead I shall
focus merely on the implications of the tests for cases which have concerned
what might be called inherent defects.
It is here that there might arguably be a
divergence of views between the UK and the Australian authorities.
B Repair and Inherent Defects – the UK
Position
An inherent defect refers essentially to a defect in the building which is a
product of improper design.[14] In
one sense, of course, putting right an inherent defect might, at least in
ordinary language, accurately be described as repairing the building. Add
to this the fact that, in the UK, it has been said on more than one occasion
that ‘repair is an ordinary
English
word’,[15] and one would be
forgiven for thinking that inherent defects would naturally fall within the
covenant to repair even though, strictly
speaking, no damage has been caused to
the building. This is not, however, the case. Precisely because, if there is no
damage resulting
from the inherent defect, the building cannot be said, in any
meaningful sense, to have fallen into disrepair, the building cannot be
said to be in need of
repair.[16] In short, defective
design in the building is not the same thing as damage to that
building.[17] Rather, the building
has, from its inception, existed in a defective state, and so has not
subsequently fallen, from a perfect state,
into one of disrepair. Consequently,
removal of an inherent defect does not require ‘repair’ of the
building. This proposition
is settled
law.[18] To that extent, it is
perhaps misleading to claim that ‘repair’ is an ordinary English
word, given that any lay person
passing by a house where workmen might be
putting right the inherent defect would undoubtedly, if asked what the workmen
were doing,
say that the workmen were ‘repairing’ the house. Far
from ‘repair’ being an ordinary English word, it has
a technical
legal sense: it applies to a building which has fallen, from a state in which
there were was no disrepair, into one in
which there is disrepair, and which is
therefore in need of repair. It does not apply to a building which,
although of defective design which requires attention, has not fallen into a
state of disrepair.
The point can be illustrated by the case of Quick
v Taff-Ely Borough Council.[19]
In that case, the plaintiff tenant leased a house which, over a number of years,
suffered from severe condensation. The condensation
caused bedding, furnishings,
clothes and woodwork to rot, making living conditions in the house almost
unbearable. The condensation
was caused by an absence of insulation around the
concrete window lintels and single-glazed metal-frame windows. Importantly, the
liability under the repair covenant of the landlord local authority was to keep
the structure and exterior of the house in repair, not the
decorations. Consequently, although damage was caused to the decorations, in the
relevant sense,
the inherent defects in the house – the absence of
insulation around the concrete window lintels and the single-glazed metal-frame
windows – did not cause ‘damage’ to the building, but only
affected the amenity of the premises. Consequently,
the building was not in a
state of disrepair, and the landlord local authority was not liable under the
repair covenant. As Dillon
LJ expressed the point:
the key factor in the
present case is that disrepair is related to the physical condition of whatever
has to be repaired, and not
to questions of lack of amenity or
inefficiency...Where decorative repair is in question one must look for damage
to the decorations
but where, as here, the obligation is merely to keep the
structure and exterior of the house in repair, the covenant will only come
into
operation where there has been damage to the structure and exterior which
requires to be made good.[20]
The case of Quick v Taff-Ely Borough
Council[21] was applied
in Post Office v Aquarius Properties
Ltd.[22] In this case, the lease
contained an obligation on the tenants ‘to keep in good and substantial
repair...the demised premises
and every part thereof’. There was a defect
in the structure of the basement of an office building which was present from
the
time the building was constructed. In periods when the water table rose, the
defect allowed ground water to enter the basement so
that the water stood ankle
deep on the floor for some years. However, aside from permitting water to enter
the basement, no damage
was caused to any part of the building by the defect.
Accordingly, both at first instance, and on appeal, the tenants were found
not
to be liable under the repair covenant: the building had not fallen from a state
of repair into a state of disrepair and the
element of damage necessary to bring
the repair covenant into operation was therefore
absent.[23]
Thus, where
there is an inherent defect in the building – for example, a defect in the
construction of the building –
but no damage is caused by that defect, the
tenant (or landlord, as the case may be) is not liable, under the repair
covenant, to
remove the defect. The law on this point is the same, both in the
UK and in Australia.
On the other hand, where the building has fallen
into disrepair as a result of the inherent defect, that is, where the
inherent faultiness in the design and/or
construction[24] of the building has
caused damage to the building – for example, defective foundations
have caused the walls of the building to bulge and/or crack – the
UK and
Australian authorities diverge. In the UK, the inherent defect itself, and not
merely the consequent damage thereon, may fall
within the repair covenant.
The law in the UK is that, regardless of how the damage is caused, as
long as there is damage, then the work required to put right
that damage –
even if putting right the damage includes removing the inherent defect that
caused it – will fall within
the covenant to repair, provided that the
work required involves no more than renewal of defective parts of the building,
rather
than renewal of the whole or substantially the whole of the building. As
we shall see in more detail below, in the case of Ravenseft Properties Ltd v
Davstone (Holdings) Ltd,[25]
Forbes J, reviewing the UK authorities in response to the tenants' submission
that inherent defects do not fall within the repair
covenant,
stated:
[T]he court, when dealing with wants of reparation caused by an
inherent defect, chose to treat the matter as one of degree, and in
Brew
Brothers v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB 612, the court effectively said
that every case, whatever the causation, must be treated as one of
degree....The true test is, as the cases show, that it is always a question of
degree whether that which
the tenant is being asked to do can properly be
described as repair, or whether on the contrary it would involve giving back to
the
landlord a wholly different thing from that which was demised (emphasis
added).[26]
The argument
that the damage was caused by an inherent defect in the building and so should
not be the tenant's responsibility under
the repair covenant has been strongly
and consistently rejected. One simply looks at the work required to put right
the damage and
remove the defect, applying one or more of the three tests
referred to by Mustill LJ in McDougall v Easington District
Council[27] and, depending on
the outcome of the application of that test, it may be that the bearer of the
repair obligation under the covenant
must remove an inherent defect in addition
to the damage caused
thereby.[28]
Thus, on the UK position, it is not possible to state unqualifiedly that
inherent defects do not come within the repair covenant at
all. Whether or not
an inherent defect comes within the repair covenant will depend on two factors:
whether damage is caused and,
if so, the extent of the damage, and
therewith the extent of the work required to put right that damage. It is on
this point – where the inherent
defect causes damage – that
the UK and Australian positions appear to diverge. I will examine these UK
authorities in more detail in section 4 of
this paper.
C Repair and Inherent Defects – the Australian Position
The Australian position seems to differ from that taken in the UK where
damage occurs as a result of the inherent defect. In Lazar v Williamson and
Others,[29] during the
tenant’s lease of a theatre, it became necessary to replace the
defectively constructed beams in the roof of the
theatre in order to make the
roof secure so that the premises could continue to be operated as a theatre. The
beams were so constructed
that, ‘when machinery used for the purpose of
the theatre was set up, the beams sagged, bent downwards, and lost the rigid
condition necessary for the security of the
roof.’[30] The defective
construction had caused the theatre to fall ‘into a condition of
dilapidation or
disrepair’.[31] In other
words, the inherent defect had caused damage to occur. Sir J Martin CJ and
Faucett J, with Sir G Innes J dissenting, held
that the work required was not
within the repair covenant because it was a structural defect. Sir J Martin CJ
said:
It appears to me that the parties to this lease, that is to say,
Samuel Lazar and the defendants, when they entered into this sub-lease,
did not
in any way have in contemplation the expending of any money for making good any
structural defects in the theatre. The building
was not constructed in the
substantial way in which it ought to have been.... We cannot gather that these
parties in any way intended
that, under this covenant to repair, any alterations
in the theatre were contemplated...I am of the opinion that the covenant to
repair does not apply to any alteration or reconstruction of the building,
either wholly or in part. The alterations made do not
come within the meaning of
the word
‘repairs’.[32]
According
to Sir J Martin CJ, then, liability for structural defects which require
addressing does not come within the contemplation
of the parties on entry into
the lease. Faucett J was of the same opinion:
As to liability of the
defendants under th[e] covenant, the law is too clear to admit of question. No
doubt, if at the time of the
lease the house is out of repair, the lessee, under
this covenant to repair, is bound to put it in repair...The question, then, is
whether the repairs executed were such as were contemplated by the parties to
the covenant sued upon. If such repairs were rendered
necessary by ordinary wear
and tear, the defendants would be liable; but they would not be liable if, by
any structural defect in
the building, the repairs needed are not such as were
contemplated by the parties who entered the
contract.[33]
Sir G Innes J
dissented on the ground that once the building has fallen into a state of
disrepair, as happened here, the work came
within the repair covenant
notwithstanding that the disrepair was caused by inherent defects: ‘I
cannot see that dilapidations
so caused do not come within the covenant to
repair’.[34] His Honour
therefore adopted the position that has subsequently become the orthodox
position in the UK.
In Graham and Anor v The Markets Hotel Pty
Ltd,[35] Jordan CJ held, for
reasons that do not clearly emerge, that the removal of lavatories was not a
breach of the obligation to yield
up the premises in good repair because the
original lavatories were defectively constructed, and there was no obligation on
the tenant
to make good inherent defects. In a significant passage of the
judgement in the New South Wales Court of Appeal, Jordan CJ made the
following
remark:
if, when it was taken over, [the structure] was subject to some
inherent defect of a substantial kind, an agreement merely to repair
does not
impose an obligation to remove the defect, but only to maintain the structure
subject to the defect so far as this can be
effected by repair. By inherent
defect is meant some original or supervening defect of an abnormal kind, such as
would not be found
in a properly built structure, would not be produced in such
a structure by the degenerative processes of user and decay, and cannot
be
remedied except by the replacement or remodelling of the structure or some
substantial part of it.[36]
On appeal to the High Court, it was decided that, on the facts, the case
did not concern an inherent defect. But it is noteworthy
that, in obiter, Latham
CJ endorsed Jordan CJ’s comments concerning the absence of liability under
a repair covenant for inherent
defects. Latham CJ cites Jordan CJ’s
comments with approval.[37]
Importantly, however, Latham CJ also says:
There is a difference between
repairing a house and building a new house in place of an old house. It is a
question of degree whether
rebuilding part of a house does or does not fall
within the category of repairing a house. A covenant to repair does not involve
the covenantee in an obligation to make improvements, but if he cannot perform
his covenant to repair without making improvements,
then the expense of making
the improvements falls upon
him.[38]
These comments
mirror similar comments made by Jordan CJ in the Court of Appeal, where his
Honour, just before making the remarks
concerning inherent defects,
stated:
Under an ordinary agreement to repair, there is no obligation to
replace the structure wholly or substantially if, without the fault
of the party
agreeing, replacement of this kind becomes necessary. But, as a general rule,
the fact that the structure has fallen
into such a state of disrepair that the
necessary repairs can be effected only by the replacement of part – even a
considerable
part – of the structure, does not absolve a party from his
liability to
repair.[39]
These comments of
Latham CJ and Jordan CJ, together with the claim that a tenant is not liable to
put right an inherent defect but
only to maintain the structure subject to the
defect so far as this is possible by repair, show that their Honours effectively
espouse
two separate principles. They agree with the UK authorities that it is a
question of degree whether the work required is repair or
renewal. But they
disagree that this is the only relevant consideration at issue in all
cases. On the contrary, when there is an inherent defect causing damage, the
tenant is never
liable to put right the inherent defect but only to maintain the
structure, so far as is possible, subject to the inherent defect.
Inherent
defects do not fall within the covenant to repair at all.
The difference
in these two principles is expressed even more clearly by Nevile J in Clowes
v Bentley Pty Ltd.[40] The case
did not concern an inherent defect, but his Honour, having reviewed the
authorities, stated the following qualification:
I should perhaps add the
qualification that the plaintiffs were under no obligation to put right an
inherent defect in the premises
which would inevitably at some future time
either within the term of the lease or after its expiration cause the collapse
or destruction
of the premises, nor would their obligation extend to
renewing substantially the whole of the demised premises, which would in effect
give to the lessor
a different thing than that which the tenant took, as
distinguished from the renewing of subsidiary parts which must be involved
in
the connotation of
repair.[41]
As we saw in the
case of Graham and Anor v The Markets Hotel Pty Ltd in both the Court of
Appeal and the High Court,[42]
Nevile J here clearly formulates two principles, only the second of which is
identical to the position taken in England. The first
principle is that the
tenant is under no obligation to remove an inherent defect that would result in
damage to the property –
even if that damage is substantial enough to
result in the collapse or destruction of the
premises.[43] The second principle
is that the obligation does not extend to renewing the whole of the demised
premises, as distinguished from
renewing subsidiary parts. This is the principle
that coincides with the UK position. That his Honour nevertheless treats these
as
two separate principles is clear enough from his use of the word
‘nor’: ‘nor would their obligation extend to renewing
substantially the whole of the premises.’ Consequently, in these cases,
the presence
of an inherent defect of a substantial kind cannot be seen to be
catered for by the principle that the obligation to repair does
not extend to
renewing the whole of the demised premises.
These cases notwithstanding,
the Australian position is not, however, completely clear-cut. The Tasmanian
case of Martin v Croft,[44]
seems to accord with the English authorities. The case concerned damage caused
by drains that were defective prior to the entry into
the lease. Interestingly,
none of the Australian authorities are discussed by Wright J in reaching his
decision. Instead, he relies
exclusively on the distinction between repair and
renewal, and the English authorities of Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler[45] and Brew Bros Ltd
v Snax (Ross) Ltd,[46] together
with the orthodox interpretation given in those cases of Lister v Lane and
Nesham,[47] about which we shall
have more to say below. Both Lurcott and Brew did not concern
inherent defects, so it is unsurprising that his Honour would find in those
cases only the principle that a tenant
is not obliged to renew the whole of the
premises, and that anything falling short of such renewal will be repair, and
therefore
within the repair covenant. For example, as we see below,
Lurcott concerned only the operation of time on a wall; it did not
concern the operation of time on a defectively constructed wall.
The notion of an inherent defect did not arise on the facts and consequently was
not discussed. His Honour was not, of course,
bound to follow Graham or
Clowes, these being cases from other Australian jurisdictions. But these
cases are nevertheless of persuasive force and should arguably have
been
addressed as being more on
point.[48]
Before seeing whether
there originally were two distinct propositions in the UK case law by carrying
out a more thorough review, we
shall next look at whether the UK position as it
currently stands is capable of yielding unjust outcomes.
III IS IT POSSIBLE THAT THE UK POSITION MIGHT LEAD TO INJUSTICE?
There can be no doubt that the position as articulated in the UK has not
been considered by any of the judges who have turned their
mind to the issue to
give rise to any potential injustice. Nevertheless, the difficulty with the
position can be shortly stated.
Effectively, where damage is caused by a design
fault in the building then whether or not the repair covenant has been broken
has
been made to depend simply on the extent of the damage, or the amount
of work required. If the damage is minor, and the extent of the work required
does not amount to renewal
of the whole or substantially the whole of the
building, the tenant in failing to remove the damage and the defect which caused
it
will have breached the covenant to repair. If, on the other hand, the damage
is major and cannot be put right without renewal of
the whole, then the tenant
will not be liable.
But why should a breach, and therefore a
responsibility for damage, be made to depend entirely on the extent,
rather than the cause, of the damage? It seems very strange indeed that
legal responsibility should vary simply with the extent of work required,
without any regard whatsoever to the cause of the damage which gave rise
to the need for the work in the first place. The argument that the overall ratio
of cost – the
third of the tests outlined by Mustill LJ in McDougall v
Easington District
Council[49]– might
alleviate the injustice is untenable. If the breach is caused by something
beyond the contemplation of the parties when entering
the
lease,[50] it is no answer to the
tenant to say to him that, be that as it may, the costs of removing the defect
are minimal, so the tenant
should be responsible.
The essential point
here is that the risk of an inherent defect becoming manifest during the term of
the lease – a defect that
would not be discoverable at the time the lease
was entered into – would not be something that a tenant would reasonably
contemplate
having responsibility for under the repair covenant, as it is
something completely beyond their control. True it is that there are,
of course,
other risks that can equally be said to be beyond the control of a tenant, for
instance, a passing car on a newly gravelled
street might flick the gravel onto
a window and cause a crack in the window, and the tenant would, of course, be
liable under the
repair covenant for the repair of the window. But these kinds
of risks are ones that arise from occupying the premises during the
term of the
tenancy. The tenant does not, however, have any control over the
construction of the premises they come to occupy, and should not
therefore have to bear the risk of the building becoming defective if that
defect
was not discoverable at the time the lease was entered into. To hold
otherwise is to make the tenant responsible for something that
happened prior to
the lease and over which he had no control. The landlord is normally in a
superior bargaining position and can
make it the tenant’s responsibility
by providing a covenant to that effect in the lease. It seems wrong for the
courts to go
further than the lease itself goes by unnaturally construing the
repair covenant to make the removal of an inherent defect causing
damage
‘repair’ for the purposes of that covenant.
A second
difficulty with the UK position is a logical one. As we have seen, the rule is
that an inherent defect is not itself damage,
and so is outside the repair
covenant until damage results from it. If someone puts it right even though
there has been no damage,
then they cannot be said to be repairing the building.
This holds even if the defect is minor, not only if it is major –
the point is that the defect is not itself damage and so does not amount to
disrepair. Yet when damage is caused by the inherent
defect, if that damage is
only minor, and the defect causing it is minor, the defect
suddenly comes to fall within the repair covenant, as happened in
Ravenseft. This is an illogical state of affairs. As a matter of logic,
only the damage, and not the inherent defect, should fall within the
repair
covenant, because an inherent defect is not itself damage – and does not,
therefore, amount to disrepair.
It might be responded that, be that as
it may, if removal of the damage requires removal of the defect, and removal of
the damage
is within the repair covenant, then to comply with that covenant, the
tenant must remove the inherent defect when removing the damage
in order to
prevent that damage being caused again, etc. But such a reply begs the question.
The very point at issue is that, when
the damage is itself the result of the
inherent defect, and the inherent defect, not being damage, is outside the
repair covenant,
it is illogical to hold the tenant liable under the repair
covenant for the inherent defect as well as for the damage caused by it,
simply
on the ground that the damage cannot be remedied without removal of the inherent
defect. To hold otherwise is to blur the
distinction between disrepair and
inherent defects, the very distinction that the law has consistently upheld as a
necessary and
cogent one, and it is no answer to this logical point to
say that, nevertheless, if the resultant damage cannot be removed without the
removal of the inherent defect, that takes
the inherent defect inside the repair
covenant. On the contrary, it is more rational to conclude the very opposite:
the fact that
the damage is caused by an inherent defect, and an inherent defect
is outside the repair covenant, means that the damage resultant
thereon should
likewise fall outside the repair covenant, if the only way to remedy the damage
is to remove the inherent defect.
If the reason inherent defects are not
disrepair is that the premises are in the same condition as they were in when
they were taken
(no damage) then there is no reason why, when those defects
themselves start to cause actual damage, they should then be classified
as
disrepair (rather than the actual damage they cause being so classed).
An
alternative analysis would be to say that the tenant is only liable for the
damage resulting from the inherent defect, and not
the inherent defect itself
(rather than to say, as we just have, that the tenant should be liable neither
for the damage resulting
from the defect nor the defect causing the damage).
This position is, of course, maintainable in a situation where the damage can
adequately be remedied without removing the inherent defect. But what about
situations where the damage can be remedied only for
a short time, before it
recurs again owing to the inherent defect? For the following reasons, this
analysis ends up being identical
to the one that I have just been defending: if
the tenant were to be made liable only for the damage resulting from the defect,
rather
than the defect itself, this would lead to the absurdity of the tenant
repairing the damage only to see it recur, repair it again,
see it recur again,
and so on and so forth. A court would not regard a patch up job of this sort as
constituting adequate ‘repair’
for the purposes of the repair
covenant. As a matter of common sense, if the damage caused by the defect is
going to recur within
a short space of time, the work undertaken to remedy the
defect would not be properly be considered to have reached the standard
of
repair that would be required under the covenant. This would therefore be a
situation in which the damage caused by the inherent
defect cannot be removed
without removing the inherent defect.
The above analysis of the
difficulties besetting the UK position no doubt partly explains why a different
position – perhaps
with one or two
exceptions[51] – is taken in
Australia, where damage that is caused by an inherent defect does not fall
within the repair covenant. It is
submitted that this analysis is more
persuasive than that espoused in the UK courts, and should remain the position
in Australia
should the issue be litigated and reach the highest level here.
In the following section, I attempt to strengthen this conclusion by
reviewing the English authorities in more detail. We shall see
that, initially
at least, there was arguably separate recognition given to cases where inherent
defects were concerned, but that
this separate recognition was eventually eroded
through judicial interpretation of those earlier cases. If some of this
interpretation
might respectfully be thought to be erroneous, then, to that
extent, such a conclusion would provide additional grounds for adopting
a
different analysis in Australia should the issue be litigated again here,
particularly if the litigation should reach the High
Court.
IV REVIEW OF THE ENGLISH AUTHORITIES
In this section, a detailed review of the English authorities is
undertaken. I will approach this task by taking as my primary focus
the
influential judgement of Forbes J in Ravenseft Properties Ltd v Davstone
(Holdings) Ltd,[52] in which his
Honour undertakes an examination of the authorities. I propose to review Forbes
J’s own consideration of the authorities
here to see if his analysis is
justified. Although his Honour’s judgement has been approved on more than
one occasion by the
English Court of Appeal and has been described by that court
as a ‘careful’
judgement,[53] it will be seen that
some of his Honour’s conclusions from the authorities are vulnerable to
criticism.
A Ravenseft: the Facts and Decision
In Ravenseft, a 16-storey block of maisonettes was constructed of
a reinforced concrete frame with stone cladding. Expansion joints were omitted
from the structure because at the date of construction it was not standard
practice to include expansion joints – it was not
known, at the time, that
the expansion rate for the concrete frame differed from that for the stone
cladding. About 13 years after
construction, part of the stone cladding became
loose and in danger of falling, owing to the bowing of stones caused primarily
by
defective design, though the danger was also partly caused by defective
workmanship in failing to secure the stones. The landlord
effectuated the
necessary remedial work and claimed the cost of doing so from the then tenant
under the repair covenant. The tenant
denied liability under the covenant, on
the ground that the damage was caused by an inherent defect and defective
workmanship. The
total cost of the work was £55,000 of which only
£5,000 was attributable to the work of inserting the joints. The cost
of
erecting the building in 1973 would have exceeded £3 million.
Forbes J held that the tenant was liable under the repair covenant.
Reviewing the authorities, he rejected counsel’s proposition
that there
was a doctrine that want of repair due to an inherent defect fell outside the
repair covenant. Rather, it is a question
of degree whether that which the
tenant is being requested to do amounts to repair, or alternatively would result
in the tenant giving
back to the landlord a wholly different thing from that
demised, and so amounts to renewal, thereby falling outside of the repair
covenant.[54] Alternatively,
applying the test of the costs of the works in relation to the value of the
building, Forbes J stated that he could
not ‘accept that the cost of
inserting these joints could possibly be regarded as a substantial part of the
cost of the repairs,
much less a substantial part of the value or cost of the
building.’[55]
B Ravenseft: the Law – Forbes J’s Review of the Authorities
In Ravenseft, counsel for the tenant had argued that there was a
‘doctrine that want of repair due to an inherent defect could not fall
within the repair covenant’. The contention was rejected by Forbes J.
Instead, his Honour said, the law has consistently maintained
that the question
to be posed is simply whether what the tenant is asked to do can be fairly
represented by the word ‘repair’,
a question that is to be judged as
a matter of degree in each case. His Honour cites what is perhaps the most
well-known and often-cited
passage in support of this proposition, from Lord
Esher MR in Lister v Lane and
Nesham:[56]
if a tenant
takes a house which is of such a kind that by its own inherent nature it will in
course of time fall into a particular
condition, the effects of that result are
not within the tenant's covenant to repair. However large the words of the
covenant may
be, a covenant to repair a house is not a covenant to give a
different thing from that which the tenant took when he entered into
the
covenant. He has to repair that thing which he took; he is not obliged to make a
new and different thing, and, moreover, the
result of the nature and condition
of the house itself, the result of time upon that state of things, is not a
breach of the covenant
to repair.
This passage has consistently been
cited as support for the proposition in other
cases.[57] It is taken to confirm
the point that whether or not the work required falls into the covenant to
repair is to be determined by reference
to whether what is required would
involve the tenant giving back to the landlord a new and different thing from
that which he took
under the tenancy. If it does, then the work required falls
outside the repair covenant, and the tenant is not liable to perform
the work
under that covenant. Otherwise the tenant is liable. In other words, the passage
is authority for the proposition that renewal of the whole or
substantially the whole of the building is not repair. No doctrine that want of
repair due to an inherent defect
cannot fall within the repair covenant appears
in the passage.
The problem with this – admittedly authoritative
(given the number of times it has been cited as authority for the proposition
endorsed by Forbes J) – interpretation of the passage is simply that it is
incapable of accounting for the first sentence that
appears there. In that first
sentence, Lord Esher MR states without qualification that, ‘if a tenant
takes a house which is
of such a kind that by its own inherent nature it
will in the course of time fall into a particular condition, the effects of that
result are not within the tenant’s covenant
to repair’ (italics
added). The subsequent judicial gloss on the passage is not capable of
explaining the meaning of this sentence.
On the contrary, according to that
subsequent judicial interpretation, the fact that the damage might have been
caused by an inherent
defect is completely irrelevant. In applying the test of
whether the work required is renewal or whether it can properly be termed
‘repair’, no reference is necessary to the notion of an
inherent defect – it completely drops out of account as immaterial to
the
issue. The difficulty with this interpretation of the passage, then, is simply
that it cannot explain why Lord Esher MR made
reference to a condition caused by
the building’s own inherent nature, nor the unqualified nature of Lord
Esher MR’s
proposition that the effects of that result are not within the
tenant’s covenant to repair. Forbes J’s (and earlier and
later
judicial) failure to explain the first part of the passage is therefore a
consideration that counts against this interpretation
of Lister.
One response to this criticism might be that the second sentence
explains what Lord Esher MR must have meant by the first one. The
argument would
be that Lord Esher MR explicitly states that the covenant to repair a house is
not a covenant to give back a wholly
different thing from that which the tenant
took when he entered into the covenant. But the problem with this response is
two-fold.
First, if this argument were correct, it would follow that Lord Esher
MR had himself fallen into error. For rather than explaining the first
sentence, the second sentence would, on this interpretation, falsify the
first sentence: if the issue is simply whether the work required is repair or
renewal, then it would be false to say that, if
a building is of such a kind
that by its own inherent nature it falls into a particular condition, the
effects of that result are not within the covenant to repair. On the contrary,
whether or
not the effects are within the covenant to repair would depend on
whether or not their remedy would require renewal, or simply repair,
regardless of the inherent nature of the building.
The second
problem with the response is that an alternative explanation for the second
sentence has not been ruled out – an
explanation which is, moreover,
capable of making the passage read consistently and which is, therefore, a
superior interpretation
from that adopted by Forbes J and other authorities. It
is submitted that there are two reasons why one might be giving back to
the landlord a different thing from that which the tenant took under the
tenancy. The first
is indeed because one might undertake a renewal of the whole
or substantially the whole of the building. But a second, different,
reason
might be because one is removing an inherent defect from the building. When a
building has been defectively constructed, then
it is from its inception an
imperfect structure, even though no damage may yet have manifested itself as a
consequence of the defective
design or
construction.[58] A building without
that defect – a building that has not been constructed defectively, or is
not of a defective design –
is necessarily a different thing from one
which has been constructed defectively, or is of a defective design. This is so
regardless
of whether the work required to remove the defect requires renewal of
the whole or not. This is because, if the building is defectively
designed or
constructed, it has never been anything other than defective in its nature. In
particular, as we know from the discussion
above, it has not fallen from a
state in which the defect was absent to one in which the defect is present.
This makes it completely unlike a case of disrepair. If disrepair, as opposed to
an inherent defect, is removed, then the building
is restored to what it was
originally. In the case of an inherent defect, by contrast, the tenant takes
what was from its origin
and by its very nature a defective building. If the
tenant removes the defect, the tenant does not restore it to what it was
originally,
but rather makes of the building a different thing from that which
it was originally. Therefore, if the tenant were to remove the defect,
then even if the removal of the defect would not require the renewal of the
whole
or substantially the whole of the building, the tenant would nevertheless
be returning to the landlord a different thing from that
which he took under the
tenancy.
In short, the reference to ‘giving back a different
thing’ can refer to two different scenarios:
1. it can refer to the
more usual scenario where the extent of work required on a building might amount
to renewal rather than repair.
In such a case, if the tenant were liable for the
work, he would be giving the landlord a different thing from that which he took
under the tenancy; but it can also refer to:
2. the difference between a
defective building and a building that is not defective. These are two different
things. If the tenant
takes a defective building and returns a building that is
not defective, he or she has given back to the landlord a different thing
from
that which was taken under the tenancy – he or she has, in essence, given
back a building that is different in kind from
that which was received under the
tenancy.[59]
This
interpretation of Lord Esher MR’s passage is capable of rendering the
first two sentences of the passage consistent with
one another. Recall that, in
that famous passage, Lord Esher MR expresses the proposition in the first
sentence in an unqualified
way; he says simply that, if the tenant takes a house
which is of such a kind that by its own inherent nature it will in the
course of time fall into a particular condition, the effects of that result are
not within the tenant’s covenant
to
repair’.[60] He does
not say: it may not be within the covenant to repair, depending on
whether what is required to be done amounts to renewal or repair of the whole.
If the tenant removes an inherent defect, then necessarily something other than
what was received is given back, regardless of the
extent of the work
required.
Further support for this interpretation of the passage can be
found if the passage is read in its context. Lord Esher MR explicitly
states:
‘You have to consider not only what the damage is – what is the
amount of repair required – but also whether the covenant has been
broken [italics
added].’[61]
On Forbes
J’s test, by contrast, one has to see what amount of ‘repair’
is required in order to see whether the covenant is broken: if the amount
of work does not require renewal of the whole/substantially the whole,
then the covenant is broken; otherwise it is the landlord’s
responsibility.
The criterion for whether the covenant is broken is therefore
the extent of the work required. But this is not what Lord Esher MR
says. On the
contrary, although one considers the amount of ‘repair’ that is
required, one also has to consider whether the covenant has been
broken.[62] So for Lord Esher MR,
there are two separate issues here. If, for example, the damage is caused by an
inherent defect, then regardless
of the amount of repair required, the tenant
will not be liable for it under the covenant because the covenant will not have
been
broken. As such, the test Forbes J purports to find in the authorities, if
that is indeed the test, departs from the authority of
Lister.
Finally, support for this interpretation of the passage
can be found if more attention is given to the third sentence cited in
the famous passage. In that sentence, Lord Esher MR states: ‘He has to
repair that thing which he took; he
is not obliged to make a new and different
thing, and, moreover, the result of the nature and condition of
the house itself, the result of time upon that state of things, is not a
breach of the covenant to repair (italics added)’.
The
italicised portion of the quotation has received insufficient attention in
judicial construction of the passage from Lister. It may be that, in this
portion of the passage, Lord Esher MR is referring exclusively to the result of
time on the building. But
alternatively, the passage can be read as referring to
both the result of the nature and condition of the house itself and the
result of time on the building. If that is the case, then again he is explicitly
stating, without qualification, that the result
(ie damage caused by) the
inherent nature and condition of the house itself is not a breach of the
covenant to repair. Once again,
there is no caveat that the result may
not be a breach, depending on whether its removal requires repair or amounts to
renewal.
If these arguments concerning the meaning of Lord Esher
MR’s passage in Lister are correct, why is it that their meaning
has been lost in subsequent judicial interpretation of them? I would suggest
that their
meaning has been lost because the same verbal formulation –
‘whether what is being given back is a different thing from
what was given
under the tenancy’ – is used to express what are essentially two
different tests, one of which is used
to determine whether the work requires
putting right an inherent defect, and the other of which is used to determine
whether the
work required involves not merely repair, but also renewal, of the
whole or substantially the whole of the building. For this reason,
the test for
an inherent defect became buried, so to speak, under the test for renewal of the
whole. Another reason why the two different
issues became merged is no doubt due
to the fact that, on the facts in Lister, under the renewal test, the
tenant would also be giving back to the landlord a different thing from
that which he took under the tenancy, because removal of the defect in that
case
did, as a matter of fact, require a renewal of the whole building. This
has, it is submitted, consequently misled subsequent judges in
their
consideration of the case into thinking that the only issue – regardless
of whether there is an inherent defect or not
– is whether the work
required involves renewal of the whole or substantially the whole.
The
next case considered by Forbes J is Southeby v
Grundy.[63] In that case,
the main walls of the house had been built entirely without footings, or at
least on footings which were defective.
The house was pulled down after being
condemned by the London County Council as a dangerous structure under the London
Building Acts,
after the walls had started to bulge and had become fractured.
The landlord sued the tenant for breach of the repair covenant. It
was found, on
the evidence, that the only way in which the order could have been avoided would
have been by underpinning, which would
have meant shoring up the premises, the
removal of existing foundations, stage by stage, and the substitution of a new
foundation
in the way of footings and concrete. Lynskey J found that this work
would have amounted to a renewal of the whole building, and so
could not fall
within the repair covenant.
Forbes J’s reliance on that case may,
however, be questionable, because Lynskey J’s judgement is itself arguably
open
to objection. In Southeby Lynskey J, noting that he is concerned
with the case of an inherent defect, reasons as follows:
That raises the
question whether it can be said that this was a building which, by its own
inherent nature would, in course of time,
fall into a particular condition. I am
sure that that is so, but the matter does not end there, because, in view of
some of the other
authorities to which I have been referred, particularly
Anstruther-Gough-Calthorpe v McOscar, it seems to me that it must be a
question of degree in each
case.[64]
Forbes J cites this
statement as authority for the proposition that there is no doctrine that
inherent defects do not fall within
the covenant to repair. Even if the case
concerns an inherent defect, the question remains whether the work required
involves giving
the landlord something different in kind from what was demised
(that is, whether the work is renewal or repair), and that question
is a matter
of degree in each case. But Lysnkey J may have erred by taking this view on the
authority of Anstruther-Gough-Calthorpe v
McOscar,[65] because that case
did not concern an inherent defect at all; it concerned the standard of repair
required under a repair covenant.
The issue in that case was whether the tenants
were liable to execute such repairs (taking account of the age, character, and
locality
of the premises) as would make the premises reasonably fit to satisfy
the requirements of reasonably minded tenants of the class
that would then be
likely to occupy them, or whether, on the contrary, the tenants were liable for
the costs of all acts necessary
well and sufficiently to repair the premises so
as to put them in that state of repair which they would be in were they managed
by
a reasonably minded owner. It was found that the latter was the requisite
standard.[66] No issue concerning
inherent defects was raised, or discussed, in the case. It is instructive to
note that Anstruther’s case is the only case cited by
Lynskey J to support his judgement. Given that he relies exclusively on the one
case, and that the case relied on is
off point, Southeby’s
authority for the issues determined in Ravenseft must be considered
questionable. It is noteworthy that Forbes J himself might be seen to
acknowledge a difficulty with the judgement,
when he comments that Lynskey
J’s judgement: ‘is clearly to reject, or overlook, any
argument that a want of reparation caused by inherent defect could not in any
circumstances be within the ambit of the repairing
covenant (italics
added)’.[67]
It should
be noted that to reject an argument, and to overlook an argument,
are two completely different things, and Forbes J has not ruled out the
possibility that Lynskey J has merely overlooked,
rather than rejected, the
argument. His reliance on Lynskey J’s judgement is for this reason
unsound. To that extent, it is
submitted the authority of Lynskey J’s
judgement in Southeby must be considered questionable on this
issue.
Forbes J then considers the case of Collins v
Flynn.[68] In that case,
inadequate foundations caused a pier carrying one end of a girder supporting a
large portion of the back wall and,
indirectly, part of the side wall of a house
to subside, in turn causing fractures in the walls. The pier and the walls had
to be
rebuilt with newly designed foundations. Sir Brett Cloutman VC was
concerned, in particular, with whether the tenant would be liable
under a repair
covenant for an inherent defect that affected, not the whole of the building,
but only a subsidiary part of it. For
this reason, the case is most interesting
for our purposes. In that case, Sir Brett Cloutman notes that many of the cases
in which
the principle that a tenant will be liable for improvements necessary
to subsidiary parts did not concern inherent defects. For example,
Lurcott v
Wakeley and Wheeler,[69]
a leading case on the distinction between repair and renewal, did not
concern an inherent defect,[70] thus
the principle did not necessarily have any implications for the facts before
him. To this extent, his Honour treated this case
as less relevant for the
determination of the issue in that case. On the other hand, the cases of
Pembery v Lamdin,[71]and
Wright v Lawson,[72]
were significant because those cases did concern inherent defects
and, in particular, defects affecting only subsidiary parts of the
buildings in question, yet the tenant was not held in those cases to be liable
under the repair covenant. Wright v
Lawson,[73] for instance,
concerned a bay window which had been erected and cantilever beams which were
wholly inadequate and which caused the
window to become dangerous. His Honour
stated: ‘I observe that that this is no doubt a case of inherent defect in
construction
and relates only to a subordinate part of the
structure’.[74]
Sir
Brett Cloutman VC’s point here is that the case is treated differently
from other cases – such as Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler,[75] –
because, unlike in that case, Wright v
Lawson,[76] concerned an
inherent defect. To that extent, although Wright v Lawson was a case
concerning only a subsidiary part of the structure, the decision there (that the
matter did not fall within the repair
covenant) was reconcilable with the view
taken in Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler,[77]which held that
renewal of subsidiary parts nevertheless falls within the covenant to repair.
Pembery v Lamdin,[78]
the other case mentioned by Sir Brett Cloutman VC, concerned, more
unusually, the question of whether the landlord (not the tenant) would be
responsible under the repair covenant. In that case, the tenant took a lease of
a ground floor shop and
basement. She intended to use the basement as a cocktail
bar. Owing to the age of the brickwork, but also because no steps were taken
to
waterproof the building when it was built, the building fell into a state of
disrepair. Waterproofing of the external walls was
required to remedy the defect
causing the damage, and to render the basement usable as a cocktail bar.
Although a substantial amount
of work was required in order to effectuate the
waterproofing, only a subsidiary part, and not the whole, of the building
required
work.[79] Despite this, the
repair covenant was held not to apply, and the landlord was not liable to remedy
the defect.
It is noteworthy, however, that the leading judgement in
Pembery made extensive use of Lurcott v Wakelely and
Wheeler,[80] which undoubtedly
causes confusion for subsequent judges in so far as, strictly speaking, that
case is not relevant to the issue
of inherent defects, as Sir Brett Cloutman VC
himself rightly notes.[81] This is
undoubtedly the reason why Forbes J, when he himself considers Pembery v
Lamdin in his judgement in Ravenseft, did not consider that the case
posed any problems for his own decision.
Forbes J’s comments on
Sir Brett Cloutman VC’s judgement in Collins v
Flynn,[82] are instructive. This
case represented a difficult authority for Forbes J, in so far as Sir Brett
Cloutman VC held, as we have seen,
that there could be no liability for an
inherent defect, even where that defect concerned a subsidiary part of the
building. This
seems to confirm the interpretation of Lister’s case
for which I argued above, where the unqualified nature of Lord Esher MR’s
comments in the first sentence of the
famous passage, discussed above, was taken
to point towards the possibility, as we have seen, that ‘giving back a
different
thing’ might have two different interpretations – the
important, and perhaps overlooked one being, for our purposes,
that giving
something back that is no longer inherently defective is ipso facto to
give back something different in kind from that which was received under the
tenancy, notwithstanding that the extent of the work
required may not constitute
renewal of the whole building.
How could Forbes J reconcile Collins v
Flynn with Southeby v Grundy? He could not. In order to
justify his decision in Ravenseft, Forbes J had to reject the
analysis of Collins, and decline to follow the case. He does so by
rejecting Sir Brett Cloutman VC’s interpretation of Southeby v
Grundy in Collins. In Southeby, Lynsky J made the following
remark:
It may be that the inherent nature of a building may result in its
partial collapse. One can visualise the floor of a building collapsing,
owing to
defective joists having been put in. I do not think Lister v Lane would
be applicable to such a case. In those circumstances, in my opinion, the damage
would fall within the ambit of the covenant
to repair, but, as I say, it must be
a question of degree in each particular
case.[83]
This comment in
Southeby might be seen to represent a problem for Sir Brett Cloutman
VC’s analysis, in so far as it states that if the inherent nature
of a
building resulted only in its partial collapse, Lister would not
be applicable in that event. However, Sir Brett Cloutman VC interprets the
remark as an obiter comment, and therefore did
not consider himself to be bound
by Lynsky J’s remarks in this passage. This is because Southeby was
not concerned with what might be termed subsidiary parts of a
building:
Plainly the doctrine of liability for the defects in a
subsidiary part could have nothing to do with [Southeby’s] case.
The case, as it seems to me, was on all fours with Lister v Lane and
Nesham. Oddly enough, Lynskey J does introduce it, in what I think is an
obiter passage. He said ([1947] 2 All ER at pp 761, 762): "It may
be that the
inherent nature of a building may result in its partial collapse. One can
visualise the floor of a building collapsing,
owing to defective joists having
been put in. I do not think Lister v Lane would be applicable to such a
case. In those circumstances, in my opinion, the damage would fall within the
ambit of the covenant
to repair, but, as I say, it must be a question of degree
in each particular case." These "obiter joists", if I may so describe them,
were
mentioned both in Lister v Lane ([1893] 2 QB at p 216) and in Lurcott
v Wakely ([1911-13] All ER Rep at p 44; [1911] 1 KB at p
914).[84]
Having treated the
remarks of Lynskey J in Southeby as obiter comments, Sir Brett Cloutman
VC concludes that the tenant was not obliged to put right the inherent defect in
Collins:
I now come to the crucial point. Do the words "repair"
and "renew" import a liability to rebuild with newly designed foundations and
footings the pier supporting the girder, which in turn carries a great part of
the rear wall and a part of the side wall in addition?
This is manifestly a most
important improvement, which, if executed by the tenant, would involve him in
rendering up the premises
in different condition from that in which they were
demised, and on the authority of Lord Esher MR in Lister v Lane and
Nesham, I do not think that the tenant is under any such obligation.
Furthermore, although a suggestion of liability for removal of an inherent
defect in a subsidiary part seems to have been touched on in Southeby v
Grundy, I do not think that the obiter remarks of Lynskey J as to defective
joists have any bearing on the present
case.[85]
If it is necessary
to go beyond Lister v Lane and Nesham, then I think that the decisions in
Wright v Lawson (the bay window case) and Pembery v Lamdin (the
damp basement case) are ample authority for the view that this doctrine of
subsidiary parts does not throw on the lessee an
obligation to provide an
improvement to eliminate an inherent defect, though affecting only a part of the
building; and I so hold.
It follows that the tenant is entitled to succeed on
the preliminary
issue.[86]
Forbes J deals
with these comments of Sir Brett Cloutman VC as follows:
In these
passages it seems to me that Sir Brett Cloutman misdirects himself on the ratio
of Sotheby's case. The question of whether the inherent nature of the
building might result in its partial collapse was not obiter at all. It
was part
of the ratio in this sense that, treating the question as a matter of degree, a
partial collapse, in the view of Lynskey
J, would have been of a degree which
brought it within the tenant's covenant to repair, whereas a total collapse
would put it outside.
As, therefore, it was not a matter of part only, but of
putting in new foundations in the entire building, Lynskey J found it was
not
within the ambit of the covenant. Insofar as he appears to be misdirecting
himself on the ratio of Sotheby, the persuasive authority of Sir Brett
Cloutman's judgment in Collins must be considerably
eroded.[87]
We have already
seen that the value of Lynskey J’s judgement on the law of inherent
defects must be doubted insofar as he relied
on a case that was off-point. It
is, in any event, a single judge judgement. But even if that problem is waived,
Forbes J’s
claim that Sir Brett Cloutman VC misdirects himself on the
ratio of Southeby is not warranted. Southeby did not
concern subsidiary parts but the defective foundations underpinning the entire
house. Clearly, the remark about what would be the
case if the facts were
different is par excellence an obiter remark, as indeed is indicated by the
nature of Lynskey J’s own
language in Southeby’s case: ‘It may
be that the inherent nature of a building may result in its partial collapse.
One
can visualise the floor of a building collapsing, owing to defective joists
having been put
in.’[88]
As the
expressions ‘it may be that’ and ‘one can visualise’
make clear, the comments of Lynskey J are obiter
comments in so far as his
Honour, by those comments, is speculating what would be the case if the facts
were other than they indeed
were in the case before him. True it is that Lynskey
J treats the question as a matter of degree, but it does not follow that
speculative
comments as to which side of the line certain facts might fall are
not obiter comments. Consequently, it is submitted that Forbes
J’s
criticisms of Sir Brett Cloutman VC’s commentary on Southeby must
be rejected.
It follows, in my judgement, that Forbes J’s
conclusions in Ravenseft cannot be said to be entirely consistent with
the authorities. Not only does he make criticisms of earlier cases which are, in
fact,
unfounded, but he also relies on cases, such as Lurcott, which were
off point in so far as the case did not concern inherent defects at all. In so
far as Forbes J relies on that case for
the test of whether the work required in
Ravenseft falls within the repair covenant, his judgement must be
considered questionable. Notwithstanding that the position in the UK is
clear,[89] the rationale for that
position – based as it is on arguably erroneous interpretation and
application of previous cases –
must be doubted. This, in particular, is a
significant reason why Australia should not automatically follow the UK
authorities on
this issue.
V OBJECTIONS TO THE INTERPRETATION OF THE LAW ON INHERENT DEFECTS ADVANCED IN THIS PAPER
One problem with the approach recommended here concerns the applicability
of the doctrine to substantial parts of a building. If the
test concerning
inherent defects differs, as I contend, from that concerning repair and renewal
– so that, on my account, it
would not be the case that the tenant is
liable for the defect even where its removal does not require renewal of the
whole, or substantially
the whole, of the building – then wouldn’t
this position make it extremely difficult to distinguish repair from renewal?
We
have seen above that the distinction between repair and renewal only acquires a
grip when these terms are predicated, not of the
parts of the building,
but of the whole or substantially the whole. This is because, as
we have seen, repair always involves some renewal. Recall the examples given by
Buckley LJ in Lurcott:
A skylight leaks; repair is effected by
hacking out the putties, putting in new ones, and renewing the paint. A roof
falls out of
repair; the necessary work is to replace the decayed timbers by
sound wood; to substitute sound tiles or slates for those which are
cracked,
broken, or missing; to make good the flashings, and the
like.[90]
The objection to my
argument would be: how are we to police an intermediary test of whether, for
example, the leaking skylight was
caused by putties that were defective? What
if, in investigating the cause of the disrepair to the roof, one discovers that
the decayed
timbers were caused by the builder’s omission to put the
necessary proofing on the wood or a failure to use the right wood?
Or what if it
is subsequently discovered that one kind of timber is more durable than another
kind of timber, even though, at the
time the house was built, this was not
known? Doesn’t this make the case on a par with the facts of
Ravenseft?
In response to this criticism, it should be noted that
taking into account an inherent defect, even as applied to parts, and not the
whole, of the building, does not threaten the distinction between repair and
renewal. We can distinguish cases where the putties
need to be replaced because
the original work was performed in a defective way, from cases where the putties
need to be replaced
simply because of the passage of time and natural wear and
tear. Likewise, we can distinguish between tiles that crack prematurely
–
because the wrong ones were used, or because they were placed badly – and
tiles that crack because of the passage to
time, or because cheap tiles were
permissibly used in the construction. Consequently, it is possible to decipher
cases where the
damage is caused by an inherent defect and cases where the
damage is not so caused. There may be cases where the distinction is blurry
– where cases will fall at the borderline – but this is not a
particularly unusual problem in our law. At this point
it will of course be a
question of degree whether the problem results from an inherent defect or not,
and each case would have to
be decided on its own facts.
A second,
perhaps more searching, criticism is this: if the defect concerns only a part of
the building, and not the whole/substantially
the whole, then there will
obviously be cases where it would be wrong to say that the removal of an
inherent defect makes the building
one which is different in kind from that was
originally handed over at the beginning of the tenancy. Suppose, for instance,
that
the work required concerned the removal and replacement of defective putty
in the window frames. It would be ludicrous to hold that,
once those putties are
replaced, one is giving the landlord back a different building from that which
was originally demised under
the tenancy.
There are two responses to
this criticism. First, one should distinguish between insubstantial and
substantial inherent defects. It
will be useful, at this point, to recall the
words of Jordan CJ in Graham v The Markets Hotel Pty
Ltd:[91] ‘if, when it was
taken over, it was subject to some inherent defect of a substantial kind,
an agreement merely to repair does not impose an obligation to remove the
defect, but only to maintain the structure subject to
the defect so far as this
can be effected by
repair.’[92]
It is
only if the removal relates to an inherent defect of a substantial kind
that the building will, if the defect is removed, be of a different nature from
that originally demised. And whether or not
the defect amounts to a substantial
defect will be a matter of
degree.[93] This response might,
however, be seen to give rise to a fresh difficulty: does this not return us to
the UK test after all? Wouldn’t
removal of an inherent defect of a
substantial kind mean that the building itself is being renewed?
If that were so, isn’t the UK position, after all, a cogent
one?
The objection that this response might give rise to a fresh
difficulty merely assumes, however, that the test for whether an inherent
defect is substantial, and the test for whether the work required to remove the
defect
requires repair or renewal, are the same test. But there is no reason to
make such an assumption. One can conceivably have a defect
of a substantial
kind, which nevertheless does not require renewal of the whole building.
Clearly, there is a difference between
a building that is not fitted with
expansion joints – and the consequences that ensue from that omission
– and a building
which has defective putties fitted around its window
frames. Certainly the difference is one of degree, but there is nevertheless
a
significant difference between these cases. Arguably, in Ravenseft, a
building with the necessary expansion joints and cladding was a building
different in kind from one without the same, even though
the work required was
not held to amount to renewal, because the consequences of the defect were
substantial. It is this consideration
of a defect of a substantial kind that
lies behind the decision of Sir Brett Cloutman VC in Collins v Flynn.
There, and in the two important cases concerning inherent defects that Sir Brett
Cloutman reviewed – Wright v Lawson and Pembery v Lamdin
– the work required did not amount to the renewal of the whole of
the building, but only of a subsidiary part. Nevertheless, because the inherent
defect was of a substantial kind, Sir Brett Cloutman,
following those decisions,
held that it was outside the repair covenant. This shows that whether or not an
inherent defect is of
a substantial kind is decided according to a different
test from whether or not the work required to remedy damage amounts to renewal
of substantially the whole of the building. The two tests need not, and in fact
do not, coincide. Yet, as we have seen, the test
for whether the defect is of a
substantial kind has, by some judges, most notably Forbes J in Ravenseft,
been erroneously merged with, or, more accurately, effaced by, the test of
whether the work required amounts to renewal of the whole.
A second,
alternative response to the criticism is this. Unlike in the case of the
distinction between repair and renewal, there is
no reason to restrict the
application of the distinction between inherent defect and disrepair to the
whole or substantially the
whole of the building. Unlike the former distinction,
the latter can readily find application to parts of a
building.[94] Consequently, the test
of whether the tenant would be giving back to the landlord a different thing
from that demised can be applied
to the parts of the building just as much as to
the whole. If so, then the tenant would not be liable, under the tenancy, to
replace
even the defective putties of a window frame – if the
problem does indeed arise from, eg, defective workmanship or the use of the
wrong materials, etc. This appears to be the position
in Australia. In Graham
v Markets Hotel Pty Ltd,[95] the
inherent defect considered by Jordan CJ concerned a possible inherent defect in
a lavatory, not an inherent defect in the entire
structure of the building.
Although, in the High Court, the case was decided on other grounds – it
being held that there was
no such inherent defect, Latham CJ endorsed Jordan
CJ’s comments that, if there had been such an inherent defect, then
the tenant’s obligation to repair would have been accordingly
diminished.[96] These being obiter
comments, the issue of whether the distinction between inherent defects and
disrepair can be applied to parts,
rather than the whole, of the building must
be considered to remain unclear. But in response to the objection outlined
above, it
is only necessary to show that there is no reason in principle
why the distinction would not be applicable to parts, not just the whole.
VI CONCLUSION
The Australian position as to the whether inherent defects and their
consequences fall within the repair covenant is superior to the
present English
position. This is so for several reasons. First, removal of an inherent defect
causing damage is not something that
would reasonably be contemplated by the
tenant under a repair covenant, because the tenant has no control over matters
of construction
which take place prior to the existence of the lease. Although
there are obviously other matters over which the tenant has no control
but of
which he or nevertheless must assume the risk, those matters are usually risks
that arise during the term of the tenancy,
and to that extent the control that
the tenant has over those risks is different in kind. They are the kinds of risk
that are normally
and reasonably contemplated by the parties when entering into
the tenancy. Second, it seems somewhat peculiar that liability for
an inherent
defect causing damage should be made to depend entirely on the extent of
the work required to remove it. Third, it is illogical that an inherent defect,
not being damage but being a fault extant from
the very beginning, does not of
itself fall within the repair covenant, but does so if that defect causes
damage. It is more rational
that the defect, and the damage it causes,
fall outside the repair covenant. Fourth, the UK authorities exhibit various
anomalies and inconsistencies.
In particular, we have seen that subsequent cases
seem to have misconstrued the leading authority on the issue, Lister and Lane
v Nesham.[97] Furthermore, the
influential judgement of Forbes J in the case of Ravenseft is open to a
number of objections, which seem to be to be unassailable. These objections must
be seen to place question marks over
the case’s authority, or at least its
persuasive force in Australia. It is submitted that the position in Australia
should
remain that adopted in Lazar, Clowes and Graham v The Markets
Hotel.
In the meantime, given the state of uncertainty concerning
whether, if damage is caused by an inherent defect, a tenant will be liable
under the covenant to repair, it is advisable that a prospective tenant of a
stand alone commercial property seek some protection
by way of a building survey
which would reveal the presence of any inherent defects. In addition, it would
be prudent to insert carve
outs in the repair covenant to make it clear that the
repair covenant does not place an obligation on the tenant to put right an
inherent defect in the building and to put right any damage that is caused by
the presence of an inherent
defect.[98]
[*] LLB (Hons) (QUT), LLM (QUT), PhD (Essex), Assistant Parliamentary Counsel, Office of the Queensland Parliamentary Counsel, Brisbane.
[1] Surprisingly,
however, there have been very few articles written on the topic. The most
significant article, that of A Hood, ‘The
Extent of the Modern Covenant to
Repair in Commercial Leases’ (1997) 5 Australian Property Law
Journal 53, 57-8, is referred to below. A Stanfield’s article,
‘The Shifting Foundations Underlying Repair Covenants & how they
Affect the Landlord, the Tenant and Third Parties’ (1996) 17 Queensland
Lawyer 31 provides a useful summary of the law in the area, but concentrates
primarily on the effects on the law of the principles of Bryan v Maloney
(1995) 128 ALR 163. Her other article, ‘A Landlord's Liability to
Repair: when does it Arise and How far Does it Extend? (1995) 3 Australian
Property Law Journal 209 also concentrates primarily on the relationship
between the repair covenant and personal injury.
[2] Occasionally, the bearer of
the obligation is the landlord. Usually, it is the tenant.
[3] The focus here is exclusively
on the common law. I do not examine the position that obtains where certain
leases, for example, retail
shop leases, are governed by applicable legislation.
[4] These terms are not
synonymous: Lurcott v Wakeley and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905, 916-7
(Fletcher Moulton LJ). Further, an obligation to put into repair is
different from an obligation to maintain in repair: Lurcott v Wakeley
and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905. For our purposes, it matters little whether the
obligation is to put into repair, or whether it is to maintain in
repair, etc: the issue is whether an inherent defect, and damage consequent
thereon, can ever fall within the covenant to repair, regardless of
whether the obligation is to put the premises into a state of repair when the
lease
is taken, or whether it is merely to maintain the premises in a state of
repair.
[5] Lurcott v Wakeley
and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905, 914: ‘Is what has happened of such a
nature that it can fairly be said that the character of the subject-matter of
the demise,
or part of the demise, in question has changed. Is it something
which goes to the whole, or substantially the whole, or is it simply
an injury
to a portion, a subsidiary portion...of the demised propety?’
(Cousens-Hardy MR). It should be noted that the first
sentence of this quotation
is slightly unhappy in so far as it does not sit so comfortably with the second
sentence: the phrase ‘or
part of the demise’ should, strictly
speaking, be omitted, if the propositions enunciated by each sentence are to be
made consistent.
It should also be noted that three differing tests have been
mooted. See McDougall v Easington District Council [1989] 1 EGLR 93, 96.
[6] Lister v Lane and
Nesham [1893] 2 QB 212, 216-7 is the case most often cited for this
proposition. As will be seen below, in my judgement, Lister v Lane has
been misinterpreted by later judicial consideration of the point in relation to
the question of inherent defects, about which,
arguably, the case was
exclusively concerned. Nevertheless, there is ample authority for the
proposition: see Lurcott v Wakeley and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905; Brew
Bros Ltd v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB 612; Ravenseft Properties Ltd v
Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB
12.
[7] Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905.
[8]
Italics added. Ibid 925.
[9] Ibid
905; Southeby v Grundy [1947] 2 All ER 761; Brew Bros Ltd v Snax
(Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB 612; Ravenseft Properties Ltd v Davstone
(Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12; McDougall v Easington District Council
[1989] 1 EGLR 93, 96.
[10]
Antra Hood makes the following comments in relation to the application of the
test: ‘Replacement of the expansion joints in
a building (Ravenseft
Properties Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12), replacement of an
entire roof (Elite Investments Ltd v TI Bainbridge Silencers Ltd [1986] 2
EGLR 43), replacement of old single glazed windows by double glazed UPVC windows
(Sutton (Hastoe) Housing Association v Williams [1988] 1 EGLR 56), and
reconstruction of a roof (with a value of 20% of the value of the building)
(New England Properties v Portsmouth New Shops (1993) 67 P & CR 141)
have been held to be repair. On the other hand, rebuilding a wall for £8000
(compared to the value of the repaired building,
which was somewhere between
£7500 and £9500) Brew Bros Ltd v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB
612), replacement of the entire aluminium cladding of a modern high quality
office building (Credit Suisse v Beegas Nominees [1994] EGLR 76, 89
(Lindsay J) and reconstruction of a low-cost house to make it watertight
(McDougall v Easington District Council [1989] 1 EGLR 93), go beyond
repair’, ‘The Extent of the Modern Covenant to Repair in Commercial
Leases’, above n 1.
[11]
Hood, ‘The Extent of the Modern Covenant to Repair in Commercial
Leases’, above n 1,
56.
[12] [1989] 1 EGLR 93,
96.
[13] See Hood, ‘The
Extent of the Modern Covenant to Repair in Commercial Leases’, above n
1.
[14] Graham and Anor v The
Markets Hotel Pty Ltd [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR (NSW) 98,
103.
[15] Hoffmann J in Post
Office v Aquarius Properties Ltd [1985] 2 EGLR 105, 107, attributing the
dictum to Sachs LJ in Brew Bros Ltd v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB 612. My
own search of Sachs LJ’s judgement in Brew has been unable to
locate any dictum to that effect. See however, the comments of Lawton LJ in
Quick v Taff-Ely Borough Council [1985] EWCA Civ 1; [1986] 1 QB 809, 821, which are
reproduced in the following
note.
[16] In Quick v
Taff-Ely Borough Council [1985] EWCA Civ 1; [1986] 1 QB 809, 821, Lawton LJ puts it as follows:
‘as a matter of the ordinary usage of English, that which requires repair
is in a condition
worse than it was at an earlier time’. This cannot be
said of a building that was defectively constructed.
[17] Ibid 817.
[18] Ibid; Ravenseft
Properties Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] QB
12.
[19] Quick v Taff-Ely
Borough Council [1985] EWCA Civ 1; [1986] 1 QB
809.
[20] Ibid 818.
[21]
Ibid.
[22] [1987] 1 All ER
1055.
[23] Ibid 1063 (Ralph
Gibson LJ) and 1065 (Slade
LJ).
[24] In Post Office v
Aquarius Properties Ltd [1987] 1 All ER 1055, 1063, Ralph Gibson LJ states
that ‘the reasoning of the court in Quick’s case is equally
applicable whether the original defect resulted from error in design, or in
workmanship, or from deliberate parsimony
or any other
cause.’
[25] [1980]
1 QB 12, 21.
[26] Ravenseft
Properties Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12, 21. Ravenseft
is discussed in detail in section 4 below.
[27] [1989] 1 EGLR 93,
96.
[28] Ravenseft Properties
Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12, 21.
[29] (1886) 7 NSWLR
98.
[30] Ibid 107 (Sir Martin
CJ).
[31] Ibid 110 (Sir G Innes
J).
[32] Ibid
107-8.
[33] Ibid
108-9.
[34] Ibid
110.
[35] [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR (NSW)
98.
[36] Ibid
103.
[37] Latham CJ states:
‘as his Honour said, if, when the building was taken over, it
contained an inherent defect of a substantial kind, the covenant merely to
repair does
not impose an obligation to remove the defect...’ [italics
added] at 580. He then goes on to say that, on the facts, there
was no such
inherent defect, at 581.
[38]
[1943] HCA 8; (1943) 67 CLR 567, 579.
[39]
[1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR (NSW) 98, 103.
[40]
[1970] WAR 24.
[41] Italics
added. Ibid 27.
[42] [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43
SR (NSW) 98; (1943) 67 CLR
567.
[43] This may, however, be
thought to leave open the possibility that the tenant would be under an
obligation to remove it if there was
only insubstantial damage, that is,
damage that does not require work to prevent a collapse or the destruction of
the premises. Furthermore, the case
may be reconcilable with the English
authorities in so far as it may be that his Honour is simply pointing out that
an inherent defect
is not itself damage, and so does not fall within the repair
covenant until damage is caused. For this reason, it cannot be conclusively
determined whether Clowes really does depart from the UK authorities on
this point.
[44] (Unreported,
Supreme Court of Tasmania, Wright J, 21 October
1986).
[45] [1911] 1 KB
905.
[46] [1970] 1 QB
612.
[47] [1893] 2 QB
212.
[48] It is noteworthy that
in New Zealand, the UK position has been adopted. In Weatherhead v Deka New
Zealand Ltd (No 2) [1999] 1 NZLR 453, a restaurant was found to be
structurally unsound and notices were issued by the council requiring remedial
work to be undertaken.
The issue was whether the tenant was liable under the
repair covenant. Having reviewed the authorities – but notably, without
making reference in his judgement to Lister v Lane and Nesham [1893] 2 QB
212, 465 – Baragwanath J held that the work fell outside that required
under the repair covenant on the ground that it constituted
renewal. His Honour
relied, in particular, on Lurcott v Wakeley and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905,
and Brew Bros Ltd v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB 612 even though those
cases, as already noted, did not concern inherent defects. The UK
authorities were also briefly mentioned in Flora Investments Ltd v Samson
Corporation Ltd (1999) ANZ ConvR 399. There Paterson J, relying on
Ravenseft Properties Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12, 402
held that it is a matter of degree whether the work required can properly be
described as repair, or whether,
on the contrary, it extends beyond repair to
renewal of the whole of the demised subject matter. As argued below, there are
strong
grounds for doubting the correctness of Ravenseft, which, if
cogent, would have implications for the reliability of those cases which found
their analysis on Ravenseft.
[49] [1989] 1 EGLR 93,
96.
[50] The contemplation of
the parties test is used in Lurcott v Wakeley and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB
905; Ladbroke Hotels Ltd v Sandhu and Singh 72 P & CR 498. The UK
authorities do not adequately explain the relationship between the renewal test
and the contemplation of the parties test
– partly, no doubt, because, as
I have noted, the test for an inherent defect seems to have been effaced by the
test for renewal.
But it is not obvious that the result of applying the renewal
test and the result of applying the contemplation of the parties test
will
always coincide. As argued here, the case of inherent defects would be a case in
which it would not be contemplated by the tenant
that he or she should have
responsibility for it, even though its removal might not require renewal of the
whole or substantially
the whole of the building. It is noteworthy that the
application of the contemplation of the parties test in Australia has
yielded different results, precisely in the context of inherent defects. Thus in
Lazar v Williamson and Others (1886) 7 NSWLR 98, Sir J Martin CJ said
that the parties ‘did not in any way have in contemplation the expending
of any money for making good
any structural defects in the theatre’ at
107-8, and Faucett J said ‘they would not be liable if, by any structural
defect
in the building, the repairs needed are not such as were contemplated by
the parties who entered the contract’ at 108-9. Note
too, that in
Graham and Anor v Markets Hotel Pty Ltd [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR (NSW) 98, 103,
Jordan CJ defined an inherent defect as a defect ‘of an abnormal
kind’ which implies that it would not be something
that might reasonably
be contemplated by the parties.
[51] See for example the case
of Martin v Croft (Unreported, Supreme Court of Tasmania, Wright J, 21
October 1986) discussed
above.
[52] [1980] 1 QB 12,
hereafter
‘Ravenseft’.
[53]
Post Office v Aquarius Properties Ltd [1987] 1 All ER 1055, 1061 (Ralph
Gibson LJ).
[54] Ravenseft
Properties Ltd v Davstone (Holdings) Ltd [1980] 1 QB 12,
21.
[55]
Ibid.
[56] [1893] 2 QB 212,
216-7.
[57] Other than in
Ravenseft, the passage is mentioned in Lurcott v Wakeley and
Wheeler [1911] 1 KB, 924; Brew Bros Ltd v Snax (Ross) Ltd [1970] 1 QB
612, 640 (Sachs LJ) and 645-6 (Phillimore LJ); Pembery v Lamdin [1940] 2
All ER 434 where Slesser LJ identifies the passage and says that effectively the
same thing is said in Lurcott v Wakeley and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB –
in other words, he takes Lord Esher’s passage in Lister to the test
for renewal; McDougall v Easington District Council [1989] 1 EGLR
93, 95, where Mustill LJ refers to Lister along with Lurcott and
Brew, among others, and argues that three separate tests to determine the
extent of liability under the repair covenant exist but that,
at least on the
facts before him, the result of applying those tests was the same. It is to be
noted that the three tests mentioned,
discussed above, are formulations of the
test for whether the work required amounts to repair or renewal. In
McDougall and in Quick v Taff-Ely Borough Council [1985] EWCA Civ 1; [1986] 1 QB 809,
in Post Office v Aquarius Properties Ltd [1987] 1 All ER 1055, and in the
New Zealand cases of Weatherhead v Deka New Zealand Ltd (No 2) [1999] 1
NZLR 453 and Flora Investments Ltd v Samson Corporation Ltd (1999) ANZ
ConvR 399, the correctness of Ravenseft’s construal of
Lister has not been doubted. On the contrary, the judgement is referred
to with unequivocal
approval.
[58] Recall that an
inherent defect is not damage: it may therefore exist notwithstanding the
absence of damage in the
building.
[59] Inevitably there
will be borderline cases and whether a different thing is given back will be a
matter of degree. Consider a building
with defective putties fitted round the
window frames. When the defective putties are removed and replaced with new
ones, it cannot
be said that the tenant is giving the landlord a different thing
from that which was demised under the tenancy agreement. The defect
would have
to have substantial implications for it to be meaningfully said that a different
thing is being returned. But the test
for whether the defect is substantial (ie
a different thing is being returned) need not coincide with the test for
renewal. For the
reasons why this is so, see the discussion below in section
5.
[60] Lister v Lane and
Nesham [1893] 2 QB 212,
216.
[61]
Ibid.
[62] Admittedly, this
interpretation of the additional comment of Lord Esher MR might be thought to
sit uncomfortably with his use of
the word ‘repair’ in the passage.
For on my interpretation, he should simply be stating that one not only
considers the
extent of the work required (in order then to see whether
that work amounts to ‘repair’ or ‘renewal’) but also
whether the covenant
has been broken. But I think his use of the word
‘repair’ here can simply be explained by the fact that he has
inadvertently
made use of the ordinary concept of repair, rather than the
technical, legal concept.
[63]
[1947] 2 All ER 761.
[64]
Ibid.
[65] [1924] 1 KB
716.
[66] Ibid 728 (Bankes LJ);
730-1 (Scrutton LJ); 733-4 (Atkin
LJ).
[67] [1978] EWHC QB 1; [1979] 1 All ER 929,
935.
[68] [1963] 2 All ER
1068.
[69] [1911] 1 KB
905.
[70] [1963] 2 All ER 1068,
1072.
[71] [1940] 2 All ER
434.
[72] (1903) 68 JP
34.
[73] Ibid.
[74] [1963] 2 All ER 1068,
1071.
[75] [1911] 1 KB
905.
[76] (1903) 68 JP
34.
[77] [1911] 1 KB
905.
[78] [1940] 2 All ER
434.
[79] The evidence
established that the work ‘necessitates removing all the panelling and
battening from the walls, cleaning them
down, raking out the brickwork,
asphalting the walls, and building a 41/2 ins. wall inside to keep the asphalt
in position, and laying
new concrete floor about 4 ins. thick to prevent water
coming under the walls, as it does at present, and trickling across the existing
floor. With regard to the dampness along the flank wall of the house that is the
corridor and side of the staircase, in my opinion
the cause is the same
penetration of water from the earth under the pavement, and in addition there is
a patch of broken defective
rendering to the cement plinth along the side of the
house. Here it would be possible for the wall to be waterproofed
externally’.
This was the evidence of the surveyor: Pembery v Lamdin
[1940] 2 All ER 434,
437.
[80] [1911] 1 KB
905.
[81]
[1963] 2 All ER 1068,
1073.
[82]
Ibid.
[83] [1947] 2 All ER 761,
761-2.
[84] [1963] 2 All ER
1068, 1073.
[85] Ibid
1074.
[86]
Ibid.
[87] [1978] EWHC QB 1; [1979] 1 All ER 929,
936.
[88] [1947] 2 All ER 761,
761.
[89] The case has been
followed, or approved, in Quick v Taff-Ely Borough Council [1985] EWCA Civ 1; [1986] 1 QB
809; McDougall v Easington District Council [1989] 1 EGLR 93; and
Elite Investments Ltd v T I Bainbridge Silencers Ltd [1986] 2 EGLR
43.
[90] Lurcott v Wakeley
and Wheeler [1911] 1 KB 905,
925.
[91] [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR (NSW) 98,
103.
[92]
Ibid.
[93] This is exactly the
position taken by Jordan CJ in Graham v The Markets Hotel Pty Ltd [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942)
43 SR (NSW) 98, 103, where he says: ‘The question whether a particular
defect is inherent or matter of repair is one of fact and degree’,
citing
Lyon v Greenhow (1892) 8 TLR 457. Note that this statement differs from
the statement that whether the work required is repair or renewal is a matter of
degree. Here
I am concerned with whether a defect is an inherent defect or not
– a question that is completely irrelevant to the issue of
repair versus
renewal, on the UK authorities.
[94] It is, however, more
likely that the distinction would be considered to apply to substantial
parts, eg, the whole of one of the walls of the building, rather than any
part, such as a
window-frame.
[95] [1942] NSWStRp 43; (1942) 43 SR
(NSW) 98, 103.
[96] Graham v
Markets Hotel Pty Ltd [1943] HCA 8; (1943) 67 CLR 567, 581 (Latham CJ); 586 (Starke
J).
[97] [1893] 2 QB
212.
[98] More detailed
suggestions of an alternative repair covenant are given by Antra Hood in section
7 of her article ‘The Extent
of the Modern Covenant to Repair in
Commercial Leases’, above n 1. However, the clause suggested by Antra Hood
would also need
to include a carve out explicitly excluding from the repair
covenant any obligation to put right damage which is caused by an inherent
defect, and not merely the inherent defect itself.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QUTLawJJl/2007/20.html