Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Technology Sydney Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 28 August 2017
Choosing Wisely: Law’s Contribution as
a
Cause of and a Cure for Unwise Healthcare Choices
Nola M
Ries[*]
Abstract
The provision of unnecessary healthcare is a serious
problem in Australia and involves two key legal issues. First,
doctors’
fear of litigation drives defensive practices – ordering
tests and procedures, making referrals, and prescribing drugs to reduce
perceived legal risks, rather than to advance patient care. Second, suboptimal
communication and decision making processes undermine
a patient’s right to
make informed healthcare choices. This article critically analyses
these problems and proposes solutions.
An extensive body of medico-legal
literature is synthesised to highlight gaps between legal requirements and what
happens in practice.
Negligence case law is discussed to clarify legal
principles and show that courts discourage defensive practice. Finally, the
article
presents practical strategies to enhance communication and shared
decision making in the clinical encounter.
I.
Introduction
In 2015, the Choosing Wisely initiative was launched in
Australia as part of a growing number of international campaigns to eliminate
unnecessary and harmful healthcare
interventions.[1] Choosing Wisely
involves health professional peak bodies producing lists of interventions that
practitioners and patients should
question or avoid, including various
diagnostic and screening tests, drug therapies and other
procedures.[2] The initiative aims to
promote conversations between clinicians and patients about the evidence base
for healthcare options and encourage
choices that reduce the provision of low or
no value interventions. Indeed, a growing body of research reveals the extent of
medical
overuse, which is related to the problems of overtesting, overdiagnosis
and overtreatment.[3]
A recent
study of ineffective care in Australia concludes that ‘thousands of
patients get treatments that cannot help them.
The consequences are serious.
Their original health problem remains and the intended cure might make them
sicker.’[4] Diagnostic imaging
services – X rays, CT scans, MRIs, ultrasounds - account for around 15% of
Medicare costs ($3.1 billion)
and at least 20% and up to half of those services
may be unnecessary.[5] Similarly,
pathology testing is increasing by up to 10% each year in Australia and the need
for some of this testing is
questionable.[6] Enthusiasm for cancer
screening, including for breast, prostate and thyroid cancer, has resulted in
overdiagnosis and unnecessary
interventions in cases that, if left untreated,
would not harm the person during their
lifetime.[7]
Polypharmacy
– the concurrent use of five or more prescription medications – is a
growing problem, especially among older
Australians and is associated with
adverse health outcomes, including harmful side effects and drug
interactions.[8] Between 20 to 50% of
Australians aged 65 or over are estimated to take one or more potentially
inappropriate medications[9] and a
five-year study of hospital admissions of older Australians found that nearly
44,000 admissions were due to preventable medication-related
problems.[10] Excessive medical
intervention in the end of life period is a persistent problem with at least
one-third of dying patients receiving
non-beneficial treatments in
hospital.[11] In Australia, the cost
of providing avoidable care in public hospitals is estimated to be at least $928
million.[12] Internationally,
overtreatment is said to have cost American healthcare payers somewhere between
$158 billion and $226 billion in
2011.[13]
Choosing Wisely
has the potential to improve healthcare quality and safety and reduce the
individual harms and system-wide waste of
providing low value or unnecessary
interventions.[14] But its success
depends on the extent to which it influences practitioner and patient behaviour;
indeed, a ‘central goal ...
is to change the culture of medical care that
has historically supported overuse of unnecessary tests, treatments and
procedures.’[15]
Socio-cognitive theory and behavioural research reveal that changing how
clinicians practice is not as simple as issuing exhortations
such as: “You
should not order a scan for routine complaints of low back
pain”[16] or “Avoid
prescribing antibiotics for upper respiratory tract
infections.”[17] Many forces
influence the use of evidence in healthcare decision-making. These include
factors at the micro level of the individual
patient and practitioner, at the
meso level of the organisational and practice environment, and the macro level
of the market for
health services and public policy
influences.[18] Saini and colleagues
categorise the drivers of medical overuse into three domains: money and finance;
knowledge, bias and uncertainty;
and power and human
relationships.[19] The challenge is
to identify the factors that are modifiable and target strategies to bring about
desired changes.[20]
At the
level of the practitioner-patient relationship, two important legal issues are
implicated in unwise healthcare choices: first,
practitioners’ fear of
litigation and second, suboptimal communication and decision making processes
that neglect the patient’s
right to make adequately informed choices. The
Choosing Wisely campaign promotes the message that “Less is more”,
yet
clinicians may believe that doing less is more likely to result in a lawsuit
or complaint by a disgruntled patient. This belief drives
defensive medical
practices, which occur when doctors order tests and procedures, make referrals,
and prescribe drugs primarily to
reduce the risk of lawsuits or complaints from
patients, rather than to advance the patient’s diagnosis or
treatment.[21] The
practitioner-patient relationship is based on a foundation of consent and
adequately informed decision making: ‘all medical
treatment is preceded by
the patient's choice to undergo it. In legal terms, the patient’s consent
to the treatment may be
valid once he or she is informed ... [and chooses] on
the basis of relevant information and
advice.’[22] This is vital to
ensure ‘respect for the integrity of the patient and better health
care.’[23] Yet the legal ideal
of an empowered patient making informed decisions is often not realised in
practice.
The purpose of this article is to contribute a legal
perspective to the problems of medical overuse and low value care. I critically
analyse legal factors that drive unwise choices and argue that the law –
properly understood and applied in practice –
offers curative potential
for unwise choices. Practitioners’ misapprehension of their legal duties
and risks contributes to
defensive medical practices; these misperceptions must
be corrected to reduce the fear of legal liability as a driver of medical
overuse. I synthesise relevant case law to demonstrate that courts are alive to
the problems of defensive practice and do not impose
negligence liability in
every situation of missed or delayed diagnosis or conservative treatment. I then
focus on a patient’s
right to make informed choices and advocate for
strategies to support effective communication and shared decision making in the
clinical
encounter. Ultimately, engaging in patient-centred communication to
enable wiser healthcare choices is a better strategy than defensive
medicine to
minimise practitioners’ liability
risks.[24]
II. Law’s
Contribution as a Driver of Unwise Choices
Defensive
medicine
Within a clinical encounter, multiple factors influence
the provision of unnecessary and low value
care.[25] These include
practitioners’ and patients’ intolerance of uncertainty; a bias
toward doing something over doing nothing
(such as testing or treating instead
of watchful waiting to see if symptoms
abate)[26]; clinicians’
tendency to overestimate the benefits of intervention and to underestimate
harms[27]; practitioner payment
models and financial incentives, especially fee for service
payments[28]; oversupply of some
practitioners[29]; fragmented care;
and patient expectations.[30]
Practitioners’ fear of legal liability also contributes to unwise
choices by driving defensive medical practices. An advisor
to a major Australian
medical defence organisation and medical indemnity insurance provider describes
the pressures doctors face:
The problem now is that doctors are serving a community which has become more demanding and in which perfection seems to be expected. Furthermore, the profession is also being encouraged to be proactive in its efforts to screen for conditions ... What do doctors do in a litigious and more demanding environment? Well, they may do many things. [They want] to protect themselves against a complaint or negligence claim or against the fear of “missing” an unlikely or rare diagnosis. Ordering more tests is a logical consequence.[31]
Surveys of doctors indicate that defensive practices are
common,[32] especially among certain
medical specialists groups.[33] In
Australia, nearly 60% of general practitioner respondents to a 2015 survey said
that the threat of litigation drives unnecessary
care.[34] An earlier survey of 3,000
doctors revealed specific behaviours driven by medicolegal fears, including
referring patients to specialists
(reported by 43% of respondents), ordering
tests (55%) and prescribing medications
(11%).[35] Data from diverse
countries - the United States,[36]
England,[37]
Japan,[38]
China,[39]
Israel[40] and
Austria[41] – report that over
70% of doctors say they regularly engage in defensive medical practices.
That nearly three-quarters of doctors say they deliver healthcare services
as a form of medico-legal protection suggests a misapprehension
of the legal
standards they are expected to meet and an exaggerated perception of the legal
risks they face. Indeed, surveys of general
practitioners and specialists in
Australia and other countries find that doctors’ perceived risk of being
sued is much higher
than the actual risk and clinicians who practice defensively
seem to perceive many patients as potential
litigants.[42] In New South Wales,
for example, a study published in 2000 reported that nearly 70% of GP
respondents believed they faced ‘a
high likelihood of legal suit within
the next five years.’[43] Even
after the subsequent enactment of NSW statutory reforms to limit negligence
actions, a later survey found that a majority of
GP respondents believed that
lawsuits against doctors were increasing and over three-quarters of them
‘feared being liable
for things out of their control’ even though
the law does not impose a standard of perfection or demand
infallibility.[44]
Legal
requirements
Physicians and other health practitioners have a
legal duty to exercise a reasonable degree of care and
skill.[45] For a claim of negligence
to succeed, a plaintiff must show factual causation and that liability ought to
be applied in the circumstances.[46]
To establish factual causation, the patient must prove that a practitioner fell
below the legally required standard of care owed
to the patient and that the
patient suffered reasonably foreseeable harm as a
consequence.[47] In considering the
scope of liability, a court will consider ‘whether or not and why
responsibility for the harm should be
imposed on the’
practitioner.[48] This latter
provision allows courts to consider policy and normative
arguments.[49]
A common
reason cited for defensive practice is that clinicians fear liability for a
missed diagnosis or delayed treatment. However,
courts and disciplinary bodies
consider the full clinical context when determining whether a practitioner acted
reasonably in accordance
with commonly accepted practice. The law tolerates
‘error[s] of judgment where the medical practitioner acts with care and
diligence, but simply makes a wrong
decision.’[50] A practitioner,
acting with due care and skill, can make a decision supported by prevailing
evidence and practice that is later shown
to have been mistaken: ‘In
identifying whether a medical practitioner has acted carelessly, the assessment
must be undertaken
without the benefit of hindsight, and must be determined from
the nature of the conduct and not from its
consequences.’[51]
Doctors
who defensively order tests, give treatments or make referrals are motivated by
worry that if they fail to do so, some harm
may materialise for their patients,
who may then pursue legal redress. Yet legal standards require that a doctor act
reasonably,
not infallibly, in taking precautionary measures to reduce the risk
of harm. For example, the NSW Civil Liability Act states that a
‘person is not negligent in failing to take precautions against a risk of
harm
unless’ several criteria
are
met.[52] The risk must be
foreseeable (one that a doctor know or ought to know about), it must not be
insignificant, and a reasonable peer
in the doctor’s position would have
taken the precautions. In determining the latter point, a court will consider
factors such
as the probability of the risk materialising, the serious of the
harm, and the burdens involved in taking
precautions.[53]
Case
examples
A recent case example illustrates the application of these factors where a
patient alleged a doctor was negligent in failing to mitigate
a risk of harm. In
a 2016 NSW Supreme Court decision, a cardiologist was found to have acted in
accordance with reasonable medical
practice in a situation where a
patient’s undetected heart malformation led to a stroke and permanent
disability.[54] The patient had a
patent foramen ovale, a hole in the heart that often causes no problems and may
be left untreated if identified.
The Court rejected the claim that the
specialist was negligent in not ordering an electrocardiogram (ECG). The
patient’s clinical
situation did not warrant an ECG since her complaints
of episodes of dizziness and visual disturbances were reasonably attributed
to
migraine headaches. Moreover, even if an ECG had been performed and the patent
foramen ovale detected earlier, the specialist
would not have recommended drugs
or surgery as the risks of such treatments could well outweigh the expected
benefits. The Court
noted that an aggressive approach of diagnostic imaging and
follow-up treatment ‘could lead to ...unnecessary intervention
– by
further testing, by surgical corrective procedure or by prescription of
medicine, all of which would carry their own risks
for the
patient.’[55]
Another
recent NSW Supreme Court decision, Coote v Kelly, dealt with an alleged
delay in a cancer diagnosis.[56] For
over a year, a doctor treated a lesion on a patient’s foot as a plantar
wart. A subsequent change in size and colour of
the lesion prompted another
doctor to order a biopsy and a malignant melanoma was diagnosed. The patient
died two years later from
metastatic cancer. The Court dismissed the negligence
claim, concluding that the doctor had acted reasonably in his care as the lesion
had the appearance of a plantar wart. In any event, the claim would fail on the
element of causation as it could not be determined
when the melanoma first
appeared and when it metastasised.
A disciplinary tribunal case,
Medical Board of Western Australia and
Richards,[57] concerned an
allegation that a GP acted carelessly in not referring for further investigation
a 33 year-old patient who reported
rectal bleeding. In the absence of a
worrisome family history or signs of more serious conditions like cancer or
inflammatory bowel
disease, the doctor attributed the bleeding to haemorrhoids
or an anal fissure. She took a watch and wait approach and did not order
a
colonoscopy or refer the patient to a gastroenterologist. The patient was later
found to have rectal cancer. The Medical Board
concluded that the GP had not
acted carelessly and accepted expert testimony that ‘[t]o “wait and
see how the disease
process evolves” is a technique that is correctly used
by competent practitioners on a daily basis. ... the alternative of
progressively investigating every presentation would be a costly and wasteful
process that would not ... constitute good general
practice.’[58] Moreover, a
defensive approach of referring patients for investigations ‘to rule out
every possible sinister cause in every
possible patient every time you see
them’ is not good medical practice.
[59]
Another expert
elaborated:
In general practice, there are relatively few clinical presentations where there is near certainty in the diagnosis. For many common presentations, the patient's description of the illness, coupled with the doctor's understanding of the pattern of disease in the community, allows the doctor to arrive at the most likely diagnoses and to discount those which appear highly unlikely. Investigations are then chosen on the basis of those probable diagnoses. It is simply not possible to investigate all symptoms to the point of absolute certainty the health system and the budget would collapse under the weight of a huge increase in investigations, with a clearly unfavourable costbenefit analysis. Diagnosis therefore comprises a constant tension between underinvestigation, and missing serious diagnoses, and overinvestigation, exposing the patient to unnecessary risk and unnecessary procedures. In most clinical encounters there remains an element of uncertainty.[60]
Courts have also disregarded expert opinion advocating a standard of care
that could drive unnecessary interventions. For instance,
in a Western
Australian case, a man consulted three medical practitioners in relation to
headaches and argued he should have been
referred for a brain CT scan. He
ultimately experienced brain injury from the haemorrhage of an arteriovenous
malformation (AVM).
The judge accepted evidence that headaches are a common
complaint but AVM are very rare. One expert witness ‘subscribed to
an
extremely pro-active principle involving the early use of radiology,’
however this view was not persuasive as it did not
have wide support among
medical practitioners.[61] In
another case, the Court commented that the ready availability of a screening or
diagnostic procedure does not mean it should be
used.[62] The decision to use a
medically available procedure or therapy must be based on a reasonable
determination that it would assist in
diagnosis or treatment and courts do not
want to encourage ‘gratuitous screening for an occasional rare
condition.’[63]
A 2002
case alleged a delayed diagnosis of a rare soft tissue tumour (sarcoma) where
the initial symptom was a small lump in the patient’s
shoulder that the GP
thought might be scar tissue or a hematoma (swelling of clotted blood in the
tissue). Opining that the GP acted
reasonably in not referring the patient for
immediate biopsy, one expert stated:
... most people have lumps and bumps, but they are usually benign. If we were to take out every pea sized lump that a patient had, it would collapse the medical system ... it would be over-treatment. It would cause a lot of unnecessary surgery, a lot of unnecessary anxiety, a lot of unnecessary scarring. We have to use our clinical judgment...[64]
He acknowledged that defensive practices can allay a practitioner’s
fears but can be detrimental for patients: if doctors ‘practised
defensive
medicine and said [this could be cancer] to everything, it would make us sleep
at night. But the patients would be totally
anxious if we did that. ... To say
to a patient every time they walk in the room that [a lump] could be cancer, I
think is inappropriate
medicine.’[65]
As these
decisions illustrate, the law does not set a standard that requires doctors to
assume the worst and intervene aggressively
for symptoms that can be reasonably
attributed to a less serious
cause.[66] Legal liability for
missed or delayed diagnoses is more likely to arise in situations where a doctor
repeatedly ignores unexplained
signs of a more serious medical problem. In
Dobler v Halverson,[67] a
general medical practitioner was found negligent for failing to order an ECG and
refer a patient to a cardiologist. The case involved
repeated interactions with
an adolescent over a period of six years during which the patient experienced
three instances of loss
of consciousness (syncope) and migraines and the doctor
detected a heart murmur. The GP arranged various tests and a neurology referral,
but did not pursue possible cardiac issues. Expert medical opinion asserted that
the patient’s history warranted an ECG and
cardiology referral. One expert
was of the view that an ECG should be performed on any person who has
experienced a loss of consciousness.
The judge observed that this position may
be ‘overcautious’ but held that failing to organise an ECG after
three syncopal
episodes fell below a reasonable standard of
care.[68]
In Paul v
Cooke,[69] the patient, Mrs
Paul, sued a radiologist, Dr Cooke, for failing to diagnose a brain aneurysm. It
was later identified and she underwent
treatment, but had a stroke during the
procedure and suffered permanent brain damage. She argued that had she been
diagnosed earlier,
she would have been eligible for a different treatment that
carried less risk. The NSW Court of Appeal found that Dr Cooke had breached
his
duty to his patient but there was no causal relationship between this breach and
the harm she experienced. The evidence established
the aneurysm had not changed
or become more likely to rupture during the period of delayed diagnosis. The
risks associated with the
treatment options also had not changed during that
time and there was only a 1-2% chance of a rupture in the procedure available
in
2003 and the one that Mrs Paul underwent in 2006. In short, Dr Cooke had
breached his duty of care by failing to diagnose the
aneurysm, but was not
responsible for the stroke.
Loss of a chance of a better
outcome
In some negligence claims that allege a delay in
diagnosis and treatment, the harm claimed is a loss of a chance for a better
medical
outcome. The better outcome may be a chance at a cure, a prolongation of
life, or a reduction in the severity of harm experienced
(that is, some degree
of harm is inevitable due to the underlying disease, but is worsened by a delay
in diagnosis or treatment).
However, a mere possibility – that is, a less
than 50% chance - of a patient avoiding an adverse health outcome does not
amount
to actionable damage in a negligence claim.
In the 2010 decision
of Tabet v Gett, the High Court of Australia rejected loss of chance
claims that involve speculation about the possibility of a better
outcome.[70] In this case,
six-year-old Reema Tabet had an undetected brain tumour. She contracted chicken
pox and was admitted to hospital with
symptoms of headaches, nausea and
vomiting. Dr Gett, a paediatrician, was concerned about meningitis or
encephalitis. He ordered
a CT scan two days later after the child suffered a
seizure and the brain tumour was identified. She had urgent surgery but was left
with permanent brain damage. Tabet argued the doctor was negligent in failing to
order a CT scan on the day of her admission and
that this failure deprived her
of a chance of a better outcome. An earlier scan would have prompted earlier
treatment, including
the use of steroids to reduce intracranial pressure, and
thus given her a chance of less severe brain damage. Estimating the benefit
of
steroidal treatment was, however, ‘absolutely a guess [and] entirely
speculative.’[71] Some degree
of brain damage was inevitable due to the tumour.
In a negligence action
claiming a loss of chance, a plaintiff’s current position is compared with
the position he or she would
have been in had the defendant not been negligent.
For the claim to succeed, it must be more likely than not that the negligent
conduct
caused the plaintiff’s harm. A health practitioner ‘should
not be held liable where what is said to have been lost was
the possibility (as
distinct from probability) that ... damage suffered ... would have been less
severe than it was.’[72]
As a policy consideration against compensating speculative loss of chance
claims, the High Court expressed concern about ‘the
prospect of
“defensive medicine” with emphasis upon costly testing procedures in
preference to a sequential deductive
approach to diagnosis and
treatment.’[73]
Who
does get sued?
A growing body of empirical evidence describes a
“claim prone” physician and this data can help dispel the
misperception
that lawsuits and complaints are a pervasive threat for all
medical practitioners. An analysis of 11 years of complaints data for
Australian doctors found that ‘3% of Australia’s medical workforce
accounted for 49% of complaints and 1% accounted for
a quarter of
complaints.’[74] The greatest
predictor of being the subject of a complaint is poor communication, a finding
consistent with research
elsewhere.[75] The study reports
that common communication-related allegations are failing to obtain an adequate
history and not creating and discussing
a suitable follow-up plan. Doctors who
are the subject of complaints also face allegations related to diagnostic
testing, including
failing to correctly interpret test results and failing to
order an appropriate test. However, failures to order clinically indicated
tests
are not corrected by engaging in inappropriate diagnostic testing.
Inappropriate screening can lead to negligent false-positive diagnoses where a
patient is wrongly
diagnosed and then exposed to the risks involved in follow up
interventions.[76]
Instead
of practicing defensively and wastefully by ordering more tests and treatments,
clinicians can more effectively reduce their
risk of legal complaint by adopting
better communication techniques: ‘Litigation risk can be significantly
reduced by good
communication not only with the patient and family but also with
other healthcare practitioners, keeping good clinical notes, careful
follow-up,
and showing that you
care.’[77] The complaints data
also provides a foundation for proactively identifying and offering targeted
assistance to the minority of doctors
who account for many of the complaints. A
recent study of claims against over 50,000 American doctors shows that ‘a
relatively
small group of U.S. physicians accounted for a disproportionately
large share of paid malpractice claims’ and the distinctive
characteristics of this cohort support targeted risk reduction interventions,
such as training and peer
counseling.[78]
Part
III. Law’s Curative Potential – Consent, Communication and Informed
Decisions
The Choosing Wisely campaign seeks to reduce the provision
of low value care by encouraging clinicians and patients to discuss the
most
appropriate use of tests and treatments. A reasonable patient presumably wants
to know the evidence for and against the interventions
available to
them.[79] As Glasziou and colleagues
recommend, one way to reduce medical overuse is through better communication and
shared decision-making.[80] It is a
long-established principle that people with decisional capacity have the right
to make their own choices about medical interventions.
In Schloendorff v
Society of New York Hospital, Cardozo J famously wrote that ‘[e]very
human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be
done
with his own body.’ [81]
This principle has been adopted in Australian law, with the High Court affirming
in Wallace v Kam that a patient has the right ‘to choose whether or
not to undergo a proposed
treatment.’[82]
In
Rogers v Whitaker,[83]
the Court articulated practitioners’ legal obligations in the
provision of information and advice to patients, including the
duty to disclose
the foreseeable, material risks of treatment options. The Court explained that
‘a risk is material if, in
the circumstances of the particular case, a
reasonable person in the patient’s position, if warned of the risk, would
be likely
to attach significance to it or if the medical practitioner is or
should reasonably be aware that the particular patient, if warned
of the risk,
would be likely to attach significance to
it.’[84] Thus, the duty to
inform has proactive and reactive
aspects.[85] A doctor has a
proactive duty to provide information that a reasonable patient would want to
know (an objective component), as well
as a reactive duty to respond to the
specific needs of the patient, taking into account factors such as the
patient’s education,
employment, personal relationships and
responsibilities, and responding to questions that reveal the patient’s
values, goals,
concerns and tolerance of risk (a subjective component). The law
envisions a situation where a patient, properly informed of their
treatment
options and the relevant benefits and risks, makes a decision in accordance with
their values and preferences.
This process of communication is vital to
enabling an individual to exercise their right to make informed choices about
their care
and what is done to their body. Yet, analyses of clinician-patient
encounters indicate ‘that physicians rarely meet even minimal
standards of
disclosure’ leading to the conclusion that consent, while ‘a vital
part of contemporary medical practice,
... is variably practised and rarely
achieves the theoretical
ideal.’[86] As with the
Choosing Wisely recommendations, a legal exhortation alone – “You
must ‘consent’ your patients”
– is not enough to bring
about desired behaviour.[87]
Attitudes, beliefs and unconscious habits can account for the gap between what
the law requires and what happens in practice. These
include the therapeutic
illusion, misapprehending consent requirements, and unconscious habits, all of
which need to be addressed
as barriers to effective communication and decision
making processes.
First, the “therapeutic illusion”
means many practitioners emphasise the benefits of treatment, downplay risks and
avoid
dealing with uncertainties in clinical
decisions.[88] This is a particular
problem for commonly (over)used screening tests and medications. A national
survey in the US investigated the
extent of patient involvement in ten common
medical decisions, including screening for colon, breast and prostate cancer,
going on
hypertension medication, and having surgery for low back
pain.[89] The study revealed that
doctors focus more on benefits than risks, especially for initiating medications
and cancer screening, and
discussions with patients do not reflect a high degree
of shared decision making. A recent Australian survey indicates that only
around
10 to 20% of people, including those who have had common types of cancer
screening, report that a doctor told them about the
risks of
overdiagnosis.[90]
When
asked, many patients cannot identify harms of commonly overused screening
tests[91] - not surprising if their
care providers stress the benefits – but patients also say they want to be
better informed. An interview-based
study in the US reported that ‘[m]any
patients expressed a desire for a discussion with their physicians regarding the
benefits
and harms of screening rather than receiving a simple
recommendation.’[92] An
overwhelming majority (93%) of respondents to an Australian survey on cancer
screening stated that both the benefits of screening
and the risks of
over-diagnosis should be discussed.
[93]
Second, practitioners’
may misapprehend their legal duty to inform and the purpose behind it,
perceiving consent requirements
as overly burdensome for them and their
patients. A survey of Australian doctors following the landmark Rogers v
Whitaker ruling investigated their understanding of consent requirements;
surprisingly, around 40% of the respondents believed they had to
tell patients
of all possible risks or outcomes, not just material risks that are
reasonably foreseeable.[94] Thinking
they must meet a nearly impossible disclosure standard produced hostile
attitudes about providing information to patients
and some doctors relied on
questionable therapeutic privilege grounds to withhold information from
patients.
Further, some clinicians are concerned about burdening patients
with decision making in the face of medical uncertainty or complexity.
Johansson
and colleagues worry about ‘pushing responsibility on to often ill
prepared citizens’[95] and
argue ‘there is a risk that informed choice transfers responsibility for
treatment harms from the health professional the
patient. This presents a great
ethical difficulty, particularly when not all facts have been provided or
understood or when facts
have been presented in a skewed paternalistic manner to
promote a certain choice.’[96]
As long as material information is presented in a manner that allows patients to
make informed decisions based on their values and
circumstances, it is not
legally problematic that they assume responsibility for that choice. A patient
has the right to make an
informed choice to forego intervention with the
knowledge that there may be a chance of a problem going undetected or untreated:
‘A patient, duly warned about [options and risks], must accept them and
their consequences.’[97] A
patient ‘should not be compensated for the materialisation of a risk he
would have been prepared to
accept.’[98]
Third,
some research indicates that doctors’ overuse of tests and treatments is
driven by habitual patterns of practice, instead
of individualised,
patient-centered discussion and
decision-making.[99] Hall and
colleagues point out that practitioners must be aware of and counter their
biases toward recommending particular interventions
without adequate patient
discussion: ‘Informed consent also demands maturity and self-awareness on
the provider’s part
to resist the temptation to abandon (or subconsciously
subvert) the difficult task of shared
decision-making.’[100] For
instance, a study of urologists and radiation oncologists ‘showed the
unconscious bias of each discipline to its own mode
of treatment for a
hypothetical case of localized prostate cancer, even though the evidence
favoured watchful
waiting.’[101] It is
recommended that ‘[e]fforts to address overuse should consider the
possibility that it is concentrated among physicians
who practice in repetitive
ways, relatively uninfluenced by the
patient.’[102] This
recommendation resonates with the empirical evidence that a small population of
physicians accounts for a majority of litigation
and complaints.
Finally, deferential or cynical attitudes and beliefs on the part of
patients may also be barriers in consent discussions. Some patients
‘understand the consent process as a routine in which they are expected to
enact a role that has already been scripted by doctors
in the interest of
doctors.’[103]
They may
believe they should leave the choice to the doctor or that they must simply
agree with the course of action the doctor presents
to
them.[104]
IV.
Getting to Wiser Choices
Colla and colleagues point out that each of
the drivers of low value care ‘requires a unique set of policy
interventions’[105] and I
propose here practical strategies to enhance the provision of appropriate care
in accordance with expected legal standards.
Misperceptions about liability
risks and the legal expectations for information disclosure need to be corrected
with accurate guidance
about what the law requires. Educational interventions
directed at practitioners must be combined with practical tools to support
effective communication and decision-making in clinical encounters.
Improve knowledge of the law and legal
requirements
Lack of knowledge is a barrier to desired professional
behaviour and must be
remedied.[106] Persistent fears
about liability will undermine other initiatives that aim to support wiser
choices. In particular, clinicians need
reassurance that doing less will not
increase their legal liability risks. Regulatory bodies, professional
associations and medical
defence organisations can complement the Choosing
Wisely initiative by providing guidance to practitioners on legal standards and
expectations. For example, educational materials and continuing professional
development resources could summarise the kind of analysis
presented in Part II
of this article, including judicial acknowledgement of the problems of defensive
medicine. Clinicians should
also be educated that they face legal risks in
practicing defensively and providing interventions for reasons other than
advancing
the patient’s diagnosis and treatment. They could face
complaints of overservicing or negligence claims if they do not adequately
present risk information and reasonable options that have a lower chance of
harm.[107] The Choosing Wisely
recommendations can assist clinicians in having evidence-informed conversations
with patients. They may also
be helpful as evidence about the standard of care
should the clinician face a claim alleging delayed diagnosis or treatment when
they followed a more conservative course of action consistent with Choosing
Wisely
recommendations.[108]
Clinicians
also need supports to understand and meet their duties to provide adequate
advice and information to patients. Importantly,
the problem identified by
Ripley and colleagues must be countered: ‘Too often, health care providers
focus on informed consent
as a protection from litigation or as a legal
formality and not as an opportunity to partner with the patient to ensure the
best
outcome.’[109] The
rejection of the Bolam principle in Rogers v Whitaker set the
legal precedent for a clinician-patient relationship premised on partnership,
not paternalism.[110] The
Australian Medical Association Code of Ethics explicitly adopts this view,
stating that ‘[t]he doctor-patient relationship
is a partnership based on
mutual respect, collaboration and
trust.’[111] A 2015 landmark
medical consent decision from the UK Supreme Court explicates the changing
context of the clinician-patient relationship
that is equally relevant to
Australia:
[Various] social and legal developments ... point away from a model of the
relationship between the doctor and the patient based upon
medical paternalism.
They also point away from a model based upon a view of the patient as being
entirely dependent on information
provided by the doctor. What they point
towards is an approach to the law which, instead of treating patients as placing
themselves
in the hands of their doctors (and thus being prone to sue their
doctors in the event of a disappointing outcome), treats them so
far as possible
as adults who are capable of understanding that medical treatment is uncertain
of success and may involve risks,
accepting responsibility for the taking of
risks affecting their own lives, and living with the consequences of their
decisions.[112]
Effective communication and shared decision making
The
law sets out what needs to happen and the principles that underlie the
legal standard; that is, to respect patients’ rights to autonomy and
choice
the practitioner must provide material information and advice. The law
does not prescribe how this should happen and the High Court acknowledges
that ‘the skill is in communicating the relevant information to the
patient’[113] in a way that
fosters understanding and informed decision making. To give meaning to a
partnership relationship and to meet legal
consent requirements, practitioners
must adopt ‘a consistent practice of involving patients in
decisions.’[114] As Gillett
and Walker argue, ‘[t]he patient and provider must partner in the
problem-solving exercise that is health care.
When this partnership functions
properly, informed consent remains in harmony with the therapeutic goal of
medicine, and the process
is generally much more satisfactory to both
parties.’[115]
Interestingly,
a recent US study of public views about Choosing Wisely and low value care
revealed that ‘most of the respondents
expected that if clinicians were
doing less testing and treatment, they might turn their attention to something
else more valuable—and
the majority anticipated that this would involve
more extensive or responsive interactions with
patients.’[116] The
respondents identified two benefits: ‘First, they expected that spending
less time ordering and reading tests would allow
clinicians more time to talk
with their patients. Second, they projected that taking a more mindful, less
routinized approach to
testing would encourage discussion of the benefits and
limitations of each approach and greater acknowledgment of clinical
uncertainty.’[117] These
findings suggest that, from the patient’s point of view, better
communication and decision making processes are clearly
connected to reducing
the problem of medical overuse.
Shared decision making (SDM), ‘the
crux of patient-centred
care,’[118] is a process by
which a patient makes a healthcare choice with their care provider and is
distinguished from an approach where a
practitioner more or less unilaterally
presents a course of action with little explanation and dialogue with the
patient. SDM involves
several key elements that correspond in large measure to
the requirements for sufficiently informed consent, including: defining
and
explaining the health problem; presenting options; discussing pros and cons;
eliciting the patients’ values and preferences;
checking the
patient’s understanding of the information; and reaching a
decision.[119]
Some
commentators – notably American – contend that SDM ultimately has a
different purpose than informed consent. They
characterise the aim of consent as
medico-legal protection through disclosure to patients while SDM aims to
meet patient needs through discussion with them about their
preferences.[120] This view,
perhaps influenced by American statutes that establish a physician-centred
disclosure standard for consent, represents
an impoverished view of consent and
runs counter to the goal of consent as ‘a two-way process in which the
patient is (or should
be) the active partner in giving consent to
treatment.’[121]
Indeed,
SDM is desirable for many reasons; it gives effect to the patient’s right
to choose what happens to them, can reduce
the overuse of low value
interventions, and improves the uptake of beneficial
care.[122] SDM is not just for
patients with higher literacy; suitably designed SDM tools improve knowledge and
informed decision making for
patients who experience disadvantage due to poor
literacy, lower socioeconomic status and older
age.[123] Despite these
advantages, SDM has not been widely adopted in practice and more work is needed
to eliminate the barriers to its
uptake.[124] To pre-empt
practitioners’ concern that SDM is not feasible in busy clinical settings,
it is important to note that SDM ‘does
not advocate deliberation in every
interaction or for every decision—that would be impractical. Rather, a
deliberative approach
is suggested where the existence of reasonable
alternatives’[125] requires
weighing information and making a choice.
SDM is premised on patients
having access to evidence and guidance to inform decisions. It involves specific
communication and engagement
behaviours on the part of both clinicians and
patients that can be learned and facilitated through tools such as decision
aids.[126] A variety of aids
targeted to patients, doctors or both, can assist with screening and treatment
decisions, including written information
sheets, videos and interactive
websites.[127] As
Légaré et al explain:
Decision aids can be used when there is more than one reasonable option, when
no option has a clear advantage in terms of health outcomes,
and when each
option has benefits and harms that patients may value differently. ... They make
the decision explicit, describe the
options available, and help people to
understand these options as well as their possible benefits and harms. This
helps patients
to consider the options from a personal view (e.g., how important
the possible benefits and harms are to them) and helps them to
participate with
their health practitioner in making a
decision.[128]
Some
practitioners perceive that SDM will require longer and more costly
appointments, however decision aids can support time-efficient
communication.[129] Further, the
task of conveying information to patients need not rest solely with medical
practitioners. Schenker and Meisel point
out that ‘[i]n reality,
physician-led informed consent discussions are often ill-timed or ineffective.
... A busy gastroenterologist,
for example, may perform 20 endoscopic procedures
(accompanied by 20 informed consent discussions) in one day. Is it any wonder
that
such discussions are less often individualized or patient centered, and
more often memorized and rushed
recitations...?’[130]
Trained health educators, such as nursing and allied health practitioners, can
deliver group information sessions for patients and
conduct individual
consultations with more time to discuss the patient’s concerns and
preferred care plan.[131]
Physician time can then be allocated to reviewing the plan with the patient to
address any outstanding issues. Carried out appropriately,
these
interprofessional collaborative models can improve patient care and reduce
liability risks.[132]
The
UK Montgomery decision is notable in recognising the potential
role for technology in facilitating informed decision making and supporting
patients as active
agents in their own healthcare:
it has become far easier, and far more common, for members of the public to obtain information about symptoms, investigations, treatment options, risks and side-effects via such media as the internet (where, although the information available is of variable quality, reliable sources of information can readily be found), patient support groups, and leaflets issued by healthcare institutions. ... It would therefore be a mistake to view patients as uninformed, incapable of understanding medical matters, or wholly dependent upon a flow of information from doctors. [133]
Interactive online aids can provide plain language information based on
current evidence, including details tailored to the patient’s
circumstances.[134] Mark Harris
recently argued that the MyHealth electronic health record
system,[135] available for all
Australians, can be used for patient engagement and communication, including
‘prompts for preventive care
and tools for health risk
assessment.’[136] In the US,
the computer-based iMedConsent program, used in the Department of Veterans
Affairs health system for over a decade, has
been found to increase
patients’ comprehension of treatment options, risks and benefits and
encourages their active participation
in healthcare
decisions.[137] With careful
patient-centred design and communication strategies to encourage uptake, people
are amenable to using online systems
for health related self-learning and
self-management.[138]
Decision aid tools can help overcome the challenges of dealing with risk
information and complex decision making in the clinical encounter.
Both doctors
and patients tend to have low comprehension of risk
information.[139] Clinicians
perceive that patients will not accept more cautious approaches, such as
watchful waiting, and report that ‘many
patients believe that more health
care is better than less health
care’.[140] However,
clinicians can adopt proven strategies to engage in brief conversations to help
patients understand risk
issues.[141] A nationally
representative survey in Australia shows that at least half the population has a
general understanding of the concept
of overdiagnosis, suggesting an
‘encouraging though limited reservoir of community recognition of the
potential dangers of
excess.’[142] Clinicians can
appeal to and develop this awareness in having conversations with patients about
the harms of screening and treatment.
A recent survey of primary care patients
in Canada found that Choosing Wisely educational materials improved their
knowledge about
low value services and a majority of participants indicated a
willingness to de-adopt low value medical
interventions.[143]
As a
final benefit of SDM to note, Posner and colleagues point out that healthcare
organisations currently expend significant sums
dealing with patient complaints
about poor practitioner
communication.[144] They make a
cogent argument that ‘complaint resolution represents an unrecognized cost
as well as an underappreciated opportunity
for reducing waste in
healthcare’ and advocate SDM to mitigate these costs and reduce the risk
of negligence actions following
from unresolved complaints. Existing studies of
SDM mostly assess shorter-term outcomes, such as increased knowledge and reduced
decisional conflict, and future work should examine a broader range of outcomes,
including improvements in patient experiences of
healthcare and fewer complaints
against practitioners.[145]
V. Conclusion
Adam Elshaug and colleagues argue
powerfully that there is ‘a moral imperative and a political duty’
to reduce the individual
and social harms of medical
overuse.’[146] They envision
a ‘transformed health system’ where ‘patients can expect to be
informed and involved in choices about
their care’ and clinicians
‘feel supported by health, political, and legal systems’ to provide
appropriate, evidence-informed
care.[147] Bringing a legal
perspective to this problem, I contend that a transformation of the law is not
needed. Legal principles provide
a solid foundation for wiser choices and change
instead is needed to align clinicians’ perceptions and practices with the
law.
Defensive medical practices and formalistic approaches to
“consenting” the patient are not the route to effective,
person-centred
care. A partnership model that uses shared decision making
techniques will improve patients’ experience of care, support informed
decision-making and reduce clinicians’ risk of legal claims. Educational,
communication and shared decision making strategies
can ultimately help bridge
the gap between legal principles and actual practice in the clinician-patient
relationship and, in doing
so, align the health system goals of reducing low
value and wasteful interventions with clinicians’ desire to deliver good
care and patients’ wishes to have the information and support they
need.
[*] Associate Professor, Faculty of
Law, University of Technology Sydney. The author undertook the research and
writing of this article
as part of a 2015-2016 Australian Fellowship in Health
Services Research and Policy. The ideas and arguments presented here benefited
from the insights of other Fellows, as well as Faculty members of the Centre for
Health Economics Research and Evaluation, University
of Technology Sydney.
Helpful research assistance was provided by Briony Johnston, PhD candidate,
School of Law, University of
Newcastle.
[1] NPS MedicineWise,
Media Release, ‘Choosing Wisely Australia launching in 2015’
<http://www.nps.org.au/media-centre/media-releases/repository/choosing-wisely-australia-launching-in-2015>
Wendy Levinson et al, ‘Choosing Wisely’: A Growing International
Campaign’ (2015) 24(2) BMJ Quality and Safety 167. Initiatives
similar to Choosing Wisely include the British Medical Journal’s
‘Too Much Medicine’ program
<http://www.bmj.com/too-much-medicine>
and the Slow Medicine movement
<http://www.slowmedicine.info>
.
[2]
Choosing Wisely Australia
<http://www.choosingwisely.org.au/home>
.
[3]
I adopt the definitions from Adam G Elshaug et al, ‘Levers for Addressing
Medical Overuse and Overuse: Achieving High-Value
Health Care’ (2017)
The Lancet, epub ahead of print
<http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0140673616325867>
(at p
2):
Overuse – Provision of a service that is unlikely to increase the quality or quantity of life, that poses more harm than benefit, or that patients who were fully informed of its potential benefits and harms would not have wanted.
Low-value care – An intervention in which evidence suggests it confers
no or very little benefit for patients, or risk of harm
exceeds probably
benefit, or, more broadly, the added costs of the intervention do not provide
proportional added benefits.
See also Shannon Brownlee et al, ‘Evidence
for Overuse of Medical Services Around the World’ (2017) Lancet,
epub ahead of print
<http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0140673616325855>
.
Overdiagnosis occurs ‘when a diagnostic label is applied to people with
mild symptoms or at very low risk of future illness,
for whom the label and
subsequent treatment may do more harm than good.’ Ray Moynihan, David
Henry and Karel GM Moons, ‘Using
Evidence to Combat Overdiagnosis and
Overtreatment: Evaluating Treatments, Tests, and Disease Definitions in the Time
of Too Much’
(2014) PLoS Medicine
<http://dx.doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001655>
.
There has been debate about defining ‘overdiagnosis’, a topic beyond
the scope of this paper, but see e.g. Stacy
M Carter, Chris Degeling, Jenny
Doust and Alexandra Barratt, ‘A Definition and Ethical Evaluation of
Overdiagnosis’ (2016)
42(11) Journal of Medical Ethics 705; Wendy A
Rogers and Yishai Mintzker, ‘Getting Clearer on Overdiagnosis”
(2016) 22(4) Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
580.
[4] Stephen Duckett &
Peter Breadon, Questionable Care: Avoiding Ineffective Treatment (Grattan
Institute, 2015),
<https://grattan.edu.au/wp-content/uploads/2015/08/828-Questionable-Care3.pdf>.
Examples of common,
inappropriate treatments include knee arthroscopy for
osteoarthritis, vertebroplasty for osteoporotic fractures in the spine, and
hyperbaric oxygen therapy for conditions such as
cancer.
[5] Australian National
Audit Office, Diagnostic Imaging Reforms (December 2014),
<https://www.anao.gov.au/work/performance-audit/diagnostic-imaging-reforms>.
[6]
National Coalition of Public Pathology, Encouraging Quality Pathology
Ordering in Australia’s Public Hospitals (February 2012),
<http://www.ncopp.org.au/UserFiles/file/NCOPP%20QUPP%20Project%20Final%20Report%20%28web%29.pdf>
.
[7]
Peter C Gøtzsche and Karsten Juhl Jørgensen,
‘Screening for Breast Cancer with Mammography’ (2013) 6 Cochrane
Database of Systematic Reviews, DOI: 10.1002/14651858.CD001877.pub5; D Ilic
et al, ‘Screening for Prostate Cancer’ (2013) 1 Cochrane Database
of Systematic Reviews, DOI: 10.1002/14651858.CD004720.pub3. Salvatore
Vaccarella et al, ‘Worldwide Thyroid-Cancer Epidemic? The Increasing
Impact
of Overdiagnosis’ (2016) 375(7) New England Journal of Medicine
614. The authors note (at 617) that a ‘vast majority of patients who
received a diagnosis of thyroid cancer in the countries [they]
studied underwent
total thyroidectomy, and a high proportion also received other harmful
treatments’ such as radiation therapy.
Afshin Aslani et al, ‘The
Impact of Recent Screening Recommendations on Prostate Cancer Screening in a
Large Health Care System’
(2014) 191(6) Journal of Urology 1737;
Luis Furuya-Kanamori et al, Prevalence of Differentiated Thyroid Cancer in
Autopsy Studies Over Six Decades: A Meta-Analysis
(2016) 34(3) Journal of
Clinical Oncology 3672 (reporting a three- to 15-fold increase in thyroid
cancer cases in recent decades due to overdiagnosis; a majority of such cancers
will not produce symptoms in the patient’s lifetime).
[8] Ruth E Hubbard et al,
‘Polypharmacy Among Inpatients aged 70 Years or Older in Australia’
(2015) 202(7) Medical Journal of Australia 373.
[9] K Anderson, C Freeman, D
Stowasser and I Scott, ‘Prescriber Barriers and Enablers to Minimising
Potentially Inappropriate Medications
in Adults: A Systematic Review and
Thematic Synthesis’ (2014) 4 BMJ Open
e006544.
[10] Lisa M Kalisch et
al, ‘Prevalence of Preventable Medication-Related Hospitalizations in
Australia: An Opportunity to Reduce
Harm’ (2012) 24 International
Journal for Quality in Health Care
239.
[11] M Cardona-Morrell et
al, ‘Non-beneficial Treatments in Hospital at the End of Life: A
Systematic Review on the Extent of the
Problem’ (2016) International
Journal for Quality in Health Care 1. Non-beneficial treatments included the
administration of antibiotics, dialysis, radiation therapy and various other
interventions.
[12] Stephen
Duckett and Peter Breadon, Controlling Costly Care: A Billion-Dollar Hospital
Opportunity (Grattan Institute, 2014)
<https://grattan.edu.au/wp-content/uploads/2014/03/806-costly-care.pdf>.
[13]
Diana J Mason, ‘Choosing Wisely: Changing Clinicians, Patients, or
Policies?’ (2015) 313(7) Journal of the American Medical
Association 657.
[14] Jeanne
Lenzer, ‘Choosing Wisely: Setbacks and Progress’ (2015) 351
British Medical Journal h6760; Amanda Kost, Inginia Genao, Jay W Lee and
Stephen R Smith, ‘Clinical Decisions Made in Primary Care Clinics Before
and
After Choosing Wisely’ (2015) 28 Journal of the American Board of
Family Medicine 471.
[15]
Levinson et al, above n 1.
[16]
See Choosing Wisely recommendation of the Royal Australian and New Zealand
College of
Radiologists:
<http://www.choosingwisely.org.au/recommendations/ranzcr>
.
[17]
See Choosing Wisely recommendation of the Australasian Society for Infectious
Diseases:
<http://www.choosingwisely.org.au/recommendations/asid>
.
[18]
James D Reschovsky, Eugene C Rich and Timothy K Lake, ‘Factors
Contributing to Variations in Physicians’ Use of Evidence
at the Point of
Care: A Conceptual Model’ (2015) 30(Suppl3) Journal of General Internal
Medicine S555. Behavioural researchers have distilled the factors that
influence and drive behaviour into key domains that include knowledge,
skills,
social and professional role and identity, beliefs about one’s
capabilities, beliefs about consequences, environmental
context and resources,
and social influences. See e.g. James Cane, Denise O’Connor and
Susan Michie, Validation of the Theoretical
Domains Framework for Use in
Behaviour Change and Implementation Research’ (2012) 7(37)
Implementation Science
<https://implementationscience.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/1748-5908-7-37>.
[19]
V Saini et al, ‘Drivers of Poor Medical Care’ (2017) The
Lancet doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(16)30947-3.
[20] Reschovsky et al discuss
the need to identify and target ‘malleable factors in clinical decision
making’: above n 18,
S559. Colla et al write that ‘understanding the
drivers of overuse is ... needed to inform interventions targeting these
services”’:
Carrie H Colla et al, ‘Physician Perceptions of
Choosing Wisely and Drivers of Overuse’ (2016) 22(5) American Journal
of Managed Care 337.
[21]
Note that defensive medicine includes ‘assurance’ and
‘avoidance’ behaviours. Assurance behaviours, which
are the focus of
this paper, involve ordering tests, treatments and referrals to reduce the risk
of complaints or lawsuits. Avoidance
behaviour occurs when clinicians avoid
particular practice areas or patients perceived as high risk. Jonathan Buron,
‘Defensive
Medicine and Clinical Risk Management’ in Legal and
Forensic Medicine, Roy G Beran, ed (Springer, 2013), pp 621-628. One US
study asked a small sample of hospital physicians (n=36) to rate orders they
made on one day on a scale from completely defensive to not at all defensive.
Nearly 30% of orders (amounting to 13% of costs for
the patient involved) were
at least partly defensive. Completely defensive practices accounted for 3% of
costs. Larger scale studies
of this nature could help provide more nuanced
understanding of how fears of legal liability interact with other drivers of
unnecessary
care. See Michael B Rothberg et al, ‘The Cost of Defensive
Medicine on 3 Hospital Medicine Services’ (2014) 174(11) JAMA Internal
Medicine 1867.
[22] Rogers
v Whitaker [1992] HCA 58, para 14. The practitioner who carries out
treatment without adequately advising and informing the patient of material
risks may
face liability in negligence. A practitioner who interferes with a
patient’s body without any consent at all may be liable
in battery.
[23] Chappel v Hart
[1998] HCA 55, per Kirby J, para
93.
[24] System level reforms are
not the focus of this paper, however other analysts argue that the fear of
lawsuits could be addressed by
a no-fault compensation system: see e.g. Elshaug
et al, above n 3 who discuss a suite of strategies to reduce overuse and suggest
that ‘reducing the fear of litigation through so-called no fault systems
provides important opportunities to enable clinical
decision making to be about
the patient and nothing else.’ The merits of a no-fault system for
Australia have been canvassed
elsewhere: see e.g., David Weisbrot and Kerry J
Breen, ‘A No-Fault Compensation System For Medical Injury is Long
Overdue’
(2012) 197(5) Medical Journal of Australia 296. Other law
reforms can arguably make it more difficult for patients to sue doctors or limit
the compensation they can receive, however
some research questions the extent to
which these reforms actually shift doctors’ behaviour away from medical
overuse: Daniel
A Waxman et al, ‘The Effect of Malpractice Reform on
Emergency Department Care’ (2014) 371 New England Journal of
Medicine 1518 (statutory reforms which limited malpractice claims to
situations of ‘gross negligence’ had little impact on emergency
physician behaviours, including use of imaging and admitting patients to
hospital). For analysis of statutory caps on damages in
the US, see X Xu, SJ
Spurr, B Nan and AM Fendrick, ‘The Effect of Medical Malpractice Liability
on Rate of Referrals Received
by Specialist Physicians’ (2013) 8(4)
Health Economics, Policy and Law 453 and R Smith-Bindman et al,
‘Diagnostic Imaging Rates for Head Injury in the ED and States’
Medical Malpractice Tort Reforms’
(2011) 29(6) American Journal of
Emergency Medicine 656.
[25]
For a recent comprehensive analysis, see V Saini et al, above n
19.
[26] Amnon Sonneberg and
Charles R Boardman, ‘Costs of Fear’ (2013) 108 American Journal
of Gastroenterology 173.
[27]
David Casarett, ‘The Science of Choosing Wisely – Overcoming the
Therapeutic Illusion’ (2016) 374(13) New England Journal of
Medicine 1203.
[28] Financial
incentives are acknowledged as an important influence on practitioner behaviour.
A 2012 study identified over 150 services
on the Medicare Benefits Schedule that
are potentially ineffective or unsafe according to research evidence: Adam G
Elshaug, Amber
M Watt, Linda Mundy and Cameron D Willis, ‘Over
150 Potentially Low-value Health Care Practices: An Australian Study’
(2012) 197(1) Medical Journal of Australia 556. Concurrent to the
Choosing Wisely Australia launch, the federal government announced a review of
the Medicare Benefits Schedule,
emphasising the need to ensure that services on
the Schedule – which amount to over $20 billion dollars in spending
–
are supported by sound evidence. See Department of Health, Medicare
Benefits Schedule Review:
<http://www.health.gov.au/internet/main/publishing.nsf/Content/MBSReviewTaskforce>
.
The final report and recommendations are anticipated in December
2017.
[29] Mike Moynihan and Bob
Birrell, GP Oversupply – Ignoring the Evidence (Australian
Population Research Institute, 2016)
<http://tapri.org.au/wp-content/uploads/2016/04/GP-oversupply-ignoring-the-evidence-12-Dec-2016.pdf>
.
[30]
Casarett, above n 27; Sonnenberg and Boardman, above n
26.
[31] Buron, above n 21,
622.
[32] Adrian O’Dowd,
‘Doctors Increasingly Practise “Defensive” Medicine for Fear
of Litigation, Says Regulator’
(2015) 350 British Medical Journal
h87.
[33] O Ortashi et al,
‘The Practice of Defensive Medicine among Hospital Doctors in the United
Kingdom’ (2013) 14 BMC Medical Ethics 42; BV Nahed et al,
‘Malpractice Liability and Defensive Medicine: A National Survey of
Neurosurgeons’ (2012) 7(6) PLoS One e39237; DM Studdert et al,
‘Defensive Medicine among High-Risk Specialist Physicians in a Volatile
Malpractice Environment’
(2005) 293(21) Journal of the American Medical
Association 2609.
[34]
Choosing Wisely Australia, Choosing Wisely in Australia, 2016 Report,
<http://www.choosingwisely.org.au/news-and-media/media-centre/choosing-wisely-australia-report>
.
[35]
Louise M Nash et al, ‘Perceived Practice Change in Australian Doctors as a
Result of Medicolegal Concerns’ (2010) 193(1) Medical Journal of
Australia 579.
[36] See
survey data reviewed in Katherine Baicker, Bill J Wright & Nicole A Olson,
‘Reevaluating Reports of Defensive Medicine’
(2015) 40(6) Journal
of Health Politics, Policy and Law
1157.
[37] Ortashi et al,
above n 33.
[38] Toru Hiyama et
al, ‘Defensive Medicine Practices among Gastroenterologists in
Japan’ (2006) 12(47) World Journal of Gastroenterology
7671.
[39] Alex Jingwei He,
‘The Doctor–Patient Relationship, Defensive Medicine and
Overprescription in Chinese Public Hospitals:
Evidence from a Cross-Sectional
Survey in Shenzhen City’ (2015) 123 Social Science & Medicine
64.
[40] E Asher et al,
‘Defensive Medicine in Israel - A Nationwide Survey’ (2012) 7(8)
PLoS One e42613.
[41]
Michael Osti and Johannes Steyrer, ‘A National Survey of Defensive
Medicine among Orthopaedic Surgeons, Trauma Surgeons and
Radiologists in
Austria: Evaluation of Prevalence and Context’ (2015) 21 Journal of
Evaluation in Clinical Practice
278.
[42] See e.g. Ann G
Lawthers et al, ‘Physicians’ Perceptions of the Risk of Being
Sued’ (1992) 17(3) Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 463
and JF Dick et al, ‘Predictors of Radiologists’ Perceived Risk of
Malpractice Lawsuits in Breast Imaging (2009) 192(2)
American Journal of
Roentgenology 327. Both these studies found that doctors overestimated by
threefold their risk of being sued. ER Carrier et al, ‘Physicians’
Fears of Malpractice Lawsuits are not Assuaged by Tort Reforms’ (2010)
29(9) Health Affairs
1585.
[43] Seham Tawfick Girgis,
Colin Thomson and Jeanette Ward, ‘“The Courts Expect the
Impossible”: Medico-legal Issues
as Perceived by New South Wales General
Practitioners’ (2000) 7 Journal of Law and Medicine 273. Almost 90%
of the respondents agreed that GPs recommend tests or treatments due to
medico-legal fears.
[44] Omar
Salem and Christine Forster, ‘Defensive Medicine in General Practice:
Recent Trends and the Impact of the Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW)’ (2009)
17 Journal of Law and Medicine 235, 247. The authors summarise the
statutory reforms made in response to a perceived litigation
crisis.
[45] See Rogers v
Whitaker above n 22 and civil liability statutes: e.g., Civil Liability
Act 2002 (NSW) s 5O; Civil Liability Act 2003 (Qld), s 22; Wrongs
Act (Vic), s 59.
[46]
Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW), s 5D(1); Wrongs Act 1958 (Vic) s
51(1)(b); Civil Liability Act 1936 (SA) s 34(1)(b); Civil Liability Act 2002
(WA) s 5D(1)(b); Civil Liability Act 2003 (Qld) s 11(1)(b); Civil
Law (Wrongs)
Act 2002 (ACT) s 45(1)(b): Civil Liability Act 2002 (Tas) s 13(1)(b).
[47] Tabet v Gett [2010]
HCA 12, para 114.
[48] Civil
Liability Act 2002 (NSW), s
5D(1)(b).
[49] For example, in
Paul v Cooke, [2013] NSWCA
311, the Court rejected the arguments that liability should flow
because ‘[i]t was said that Dr Cooke was relatively blameworthy,
and
insured, and performed his duty for commercial profit, and that the consequences
for Ms Paul were serious and life-changing.
All that is true, but to my mind is
misdirected.” (para 133)
[50] Medical Board Of Western
Australia and Richards [2010] WASAT 94, para
27.
[51] Ibid, para
28.
[52] Civil Liability Act
2002 (NSW), s 5B. See also Civil Liability Act 2003 (Qld), s 9,
Wrongs Act 1958 (Vic), s
48.
[53]
Ibid.
[54] Rothonis v
Lattimore [2016] NSWSC
1409.
[55] Ibid, para
60.
[56] Coote v Kelly;
Northam v Kelly [2016] NSWSC 1447. This was a retrial ordered following an
appeal of an earlier trial decision: Coote v Kelly [2013] NSWCA
357.
[57] Above n
50.
[58] Ibid, para 55 (Professor
Bernard PearnRowe).
[59]
Ibid, para 56.
[60] Ibid, para 54
(Dr Peter Maguire). This expert gave an example:
To take an extreme example as an illustration, tuberculosis (TB) is very rare
in Australia in 2010. One of its symptoms is productive
cough. Thousands of
people are treated every day in Australia for productive cough, and in most
cases the diagnosis of TB is not
considered by the doctor because of its very
low probability. There are a few cases of TB occurring each year in Australia,
and there
is often significant delay in diagnosis, since the attending doctors
do not include TB as a probable diagnosis. This does not imply
that every
patient who presents with a cough should be tested for
TB.
[61] Le Brun v Joseph
& Ors [2006] WADC 200, para 331, aff’d Le Brun v Joseph
[No 2] [2010] WASCA 52.
[62] Dobler v
Kenneth Halverson and Ors; Dobler v Kurt Halverson (by his
tutor) [2007] NSWCA
335, para 86.
[63] Ibid,
para 88.
[64] Schiller v
Connah [2002] NSWSC 1264, para
80.
[65] Ibid, para 89,
92.
[66] Healthcare providers
could face liability if patients suffer harm due to undergoing a procedure that
a provider knew to be unnecessary
or where the provider fails to adequately
inform the patient that there is not an urgent need for invasive or risky
procedures. See
Redzepovic v Western Health [2016] VSCA 251 as an example
where such a claim failed. The plaintiff, who underwent surgical removal of his
parotid gland, argued that the surgery
was unnecessary and that he suffered
serious lingering pain following the procedure that could have been avoided. The
action was
dismissed as medical evidence established that a “wait and
see” approach was not a reasonable course of action in this
case as there
was a risk that the lump in the plaintiff’s neck could not be definitively
diagnosed without removal, there was
a risk it was a malignant tumour and, if
left, could grow and become more difficult and risky to
remove.
[67] Above n
62.
[68] Halverson v
Dobler, [2006]
NSWSC 1307, para 186.
[69] [2012] NSWSC
840, appeal dismissed [2013] NSWCA 311; High Court dismissed the special
leave application.
[70] Tabet
v Gett, above n 47. The question put to the Court was: “Does the
common law of negligence in Australia recognise a less than even
chance of
avoiding an adverse health outcome as an interest of value to a patient, the
loss of which by reason of a doctor’s
negligence, can be compensated as
damage suffered by that patient?”
[71] Ibid, para 43, per
Gummow ACJ.
[72] Ibid,
para 68, per Hayne and Bell
JJ.
[73]
Ibid.
[74] Marie M Bismark
et al, ‘Identification of Doctors at Risk of Recurrent Complaints: A
National Study of Healthcare Complaints
in Australia’ (2013) 22(7) BMJ
Quality and Safety 532.
[75]
See e.g., Wendy Reschovsky et al, ‘Physician-Patient Communication: The
Relationship With Malpractice Claims Among Primary
Care Physicians and
Surgeons’ (1997) 277(7) Journal of the American Medical Association
553 (identifies specific communication behaviours associated with fewer
malpractice claims against primary care practitioners); RA Barragry
et al,
‘An Analytic Observational Study on Complaints Management in the General
Practice Out of Hours Care Setting: Who Complains,
Why, and What Can We Do About
It?’ (2016) 17 BMC Family Practice 87 (poor communication
identified as a factor in a majority of complaints against GPs in an Irish
general practice study); A Ernesäter
et al, ‘A Comparison of Calls
Subjected to a Malpractice Claim Versus 'Normal Calls' Within The Swedish
Healthcare Direct:
A Case-Control Study’ (2014) 4(10) BMJ Open
e005961 (use of open-ended questioning techniques elicited more medical details
and reduced malpractice risks for tele-nurses in
Sweden). The fact that
communication and openness can reduce legal risks also informs open disclosure
initiatives, whereby practitioners
inform patients of incidents or mistakes that
occurred in their care, particularly when the patient has experienced harm as a
consequence.
See e.g. Malcolm Parker, ‘A Fair Dinkum Duty of Open
Disclosure Following Medical Error’ (2012) 20(1) Journal of Law and
Medicine 34-43: ‘There is strong evidence that comprehensive
communication, including genuine apology and consistent with the medical ethical
principle of veracity, is associated with reduced levels of litigation.’
See also Angus Finlay, Cameron Stewart and Malcolm
Parker, ‘Open
Disclosure: Ethical, Professional and Legal Obligations, and the Way Forward for
Regulation’ (2013) 198(8) Medical Journal of Australia 445 and
Australian Open Disclosure Framework,
<https://www.safetyandquality.gov.au/wp-content/uploads/2013/03/Australian-Open-Disclosure-Framework-Feb-2014.pdf>.
Open disclosure is reactive, however, and involves open communication after a
problem has been identified. Initiatives like Choosing
Wisely are proactive and
urge communication with patients as to whether particular interventions are
warranted and to discuss the
potential harms of overdiagnosis and
overtreatment.
[76] See comment
on negligent diagnosis in Paul v Cooke, above n 49, para
95.
[77] Buron, above n 21,
621.
[78] David M Studdert et al,
‘Prevalence and Characteristics of Physicians Prone to Malpractice
Claims’ (2016) 374(4) New England Journal of Medicine 354 and
Matthew J Spittal, Marie M Bismark and David M Studdert, ‘The PRONE Score:
An Algorithm for Predicting Doctors' Risks of
Formal Patient Complaints Using
Routinely Collected Administrative Data’ (2015) 24(6) BMJ Quality and
Safety 360.
[79] The
communication and education process requires the practitioner to explain why
some interventions are considered “do not
do” by the weight of
current evidence and to discuss other interventions that are among reasonable
alternatives for the patient
in light of their symptoms, history and other
relevant considerations. It is worth noting here that some clinicians say they
provide
low value care in order to placate patient demands or expectations:
Donna J Mason, ‘Choosing Wisely: Changing Clinicians, Patients,
or
Policies?’ (2015) 313(7) Journal of the American Medical
Association 657. To the extent that patients demand tests, treatments or
referrals, the Choosing Wisely recommendations give practitioners an external
source of guidance to explain the evidentiary basis for their clinical judgment.
Moreover, the law does not give patients the right
to demand services that are
not clinically indicated. Being person-centred does not mean delivering services
of doubtful or no clinical
benefit.
[80] Paul Glasziou et al,
‘Too Much Medicine; Too Little Care’ (2013) 346 British Medical
Journal f4247.
[81] (1914)
211 NY 125, 129.
[82] Wallace
v Kam, [2013] HCA 19 para 8; see also Rosenberg v Percival [2001] HCA
18 and Hunter and New England Area Health Service [2009] NSWSC 761; (2009) 74 NSWLR 88 for
endorsement of Cordozo J’s statement. For analysis of the Wallace
decision, see e.g. Tracey Carver and Malcolm K Smith, ‘Medical
Negligence, Causation and Liability for Non-Disclosure of Risk:
A
Post-Wallace Framework and Critique’ [2014] UNSWLawJl 35; (2014) 37(3) UNSW Law
Journal 972.
[83] Rogers v
Whitaker, above n 22.
[84]
Ibid, para 16.
[85] For
elaboration, see Gummow J in Rosenberg v Percival, above n 82, paras
75-82.
[86] Daniel E Hall, Allan
V Prochazka and Aaron S Fink, ‘Informed Consent for Clinical
Treatment’ (2012) 184(5) Canadian Medical Association Journal 533.
See also Christine Grady, ‘Enduring and Emerging Challenges for Informed
Consent’ (2015) 372 New England Journal of Medicine 855, who writes
(at 856): ‘A substantial body of literature corroborates a considerable
gap between the practice of informed consent
and its theoretical construct or
intended goals and indicates many unresolved conceptual and practical
questions.’ In 1999,
Braddock and colleagues published a now classic study
reporting that only 9% of decisions in over 1,000 primary care and surgical
consultations could be considered fully informed: CH Braddock et al,
‘Informed Decision Making in Outpatient Practice: Time
to Get Back to
Basics’ (1999) 282 Journal of the American Medical Association
2313. Clinicians were mostly likely to discuss the nature of the proposed
intervention, such as a lab test or a medication, but often did
not elicit
patient questions or preferences. See also discussion in Eric B Bass,
‘Jump Forward to Get Back to Basics’
(2015) 30(11) Journal of
General Internal Medicine
1577.
[87] Erica S Spatz,
Harlan M Krumholz and Benjamin W Moulton, ‘The New Era of Informed
Consent: Getting to a Reasonable-Patient
Standard Through Shared Decision
Making’ (2016) 315(19) Journal of the American Medical Association
2063 who state (at 2064) that the mere existence of legal rules has
‘not been successful in achieving a high-value, patient-centred
approach
to informed decision
making.’
[88] Casarett,
above n 27. Studies of consent conversations found that ‘uncertainty was
communicated only 5% of the time when obtaining
informed consent. This lack of
communication was particularly true in discussions for decisions of high
complexity; only 0.5% of
such decisions were fully informed.’ See Wendy Z
Tao, Lawrence H Brenner and B Sonny Bal, ‘The Law and Social Values:
Medical Uncertainty’ (2017) 475 Clinical Orthopaedics and Related
Research 27.
[89] FJ Fowler,
BS Gerstein and MJ Barry, ‘How Patient Centered are Medical Decisions?:
Results of a National Survey’ (2013)
173(13) JAMA Internal Medicine
1215.
[90] Ray Moynihan et al,
‘Public Opinions about Overdiagnosis: A National Community Survey’
(2015) 10(5) PLoS
ONE.
[91] Anne
Sutkowski-Hemstreet et al, ‘Adult Patients’ Perspectives on the
Benefits and Harms of Overused Screening Tests:
A Qualitative Study’
(2015) 30:11 Journal of General Internal Medicine 1618. In interviews
with 50 patients, over two-thirds could not state a harm of screening when asked
to do so. Those that did mostly
described harms related directly to preparing
for or having a screening test, such as not eating prior to a colonoscopy. Few
people
identified harms related to the outcome of the screening and follow-up
procedures.
[92] Ibid,
9.
[93] Moynihan et al, above n
90.
[94] Loane Skene and Richard
Smallwood, ‘Informed Consent: Lessons from Australia’ (2002)
324(7328) British Medical Journal 39. An update to this survey would be
timely to determine whether knowledge and attitudes have changed. In a similar
vein, a survey undertaken
by Salem and Forster, above n 44, found very low
knowledge among general practitioners of NSW Civil Liability Act reforms
that aimed to reduce exposure to medical negligence
claims.
[95] Minna Johansson,
Karsten Juhl, Linn Getz and Ray Moynihan, ‘ “Informed Choice”
in a Time of Too Much Medicine –
No Panacea for Ethical
Difficulties” (2016) 353 British Medical Journal 2230,
2230.
[96] Ibid,
2231.
[97] Chappel v Hart
[1998] HCA 55, para 96.
[98]
Wallace v Kam, above n 82. In regard to the duty to warn, the Court
stated (at para 36) that ‘[t]he underlying policy is ... to protect the
patient from the occurrence of physical injury the risk of which is unacceptable
to the patient’. This implies that some risks
are acceptable and it is up
to the patient to weigh medical information with their own values and
preferences and make a choice.
If the purposes, risk and benefits of screening
are communicated appropriately, members of the public are willing to accept that
some cases of disease may be missed and that legal culpability should not
automatically follow each case of missed disease: J Cockburn,
S Redman, D Hill
and E Henry, ‘Public Understanding of Medical Screening’ (1995) 2(4)
Journal of Medical Screening 224.
[99] Allison Lipitz-Snyderman
et al, ‘Physician-Driven Variation in Nonrecommended Services Among Older
Adults Diagnosed with Cancer’
(2016) 176 (10) JAMA Internal
Medicine 1541.
[100] Hall
et al, above n 86.
[101]
Ibid.
[102] Ibid,
1547.
[103] Carole Doherty,
Charitini Stavropoulou, Mark NK Saunders and Tracey Brown, ‘The Consent
Process: Enabling or Disabling Patients’
Active Participation?’
(2017) 21(2) Health 205. See also M Habiba et al, ‘Women’s
Accounts of Consenting to Surgery: Is Consent a Quality Problem?’ (2004)
13 Quality and Safety in Health Care
422.
[104] For discussion
see e.g. Grady, above n
86.
[105] Colla et al, above n
20, 338.
[106] Cane et al,
above n 18.
[107] In an
analysis of cases following Rogers v Whitaker, Addison summarises:
A patient’s need for treatment necessarily involves consideration of
the alternative measures available. The more alternatives
available to a
patient, the less the need for the patient to undergo a specific procedure or
treatment. Patients are therefore more
likely to attach significance to the
risks of one treatment if an alternaive treatment is available that does not
entail such risks.
Thomas Addison, ‘Negligent Failure to Inform:
Developments in the Law since Rogers v Whitaker’ (2003) 11 Torts Law
Journal 165, 177.
[108]
Analysis of the use of professionally developed guidelines in litigation is
beyond the scope of this article but for discussion,
see e.g. Jonathan Davies,
‘Clinical Guidelines as a Tool for Legal Liability: An International
Perspective’ (2009) 28(4) Medicine and Law 603; Allen
Kachalia and Michelle M Mello, ‘Breast Cancer Screening: Conflicting
Guidelines and Medicolegal Risk’ (2013) 309(24) Journal of the American
Medical Association 2555; and RA Fearnley, MDD Bell and AR Bodenham,
‘Status of National Guidelines in Dictating Individual Clinical Practice
and Defining
Negligence’ (2012) 108(4) British Journal of Anaesthesia
557.
[109] Beth A Ripley,
David Tiffany, Lisa S Lehmann and Stuart G Silverman, ‘Improving the
Informed Consent Conversation: A Standardized
Checklist that Is Patient Centred,
Quality Driven, and Legally Sound’ (2015) 26(11) Journal of Vascular
and Interventional Radiology 1639, 1642. The authors point out: ‘In
fact, the elements that render a consent conversation patient-centred and
quality-driven,
such as respect for patient autonomy and clear communication,
are the same elements that render a consent conversation legally sound.’
Gillett and Walker make a similar point, arguing that the therapeutic
relationship ‘is undermined if the criteria of informed
consent are taken
as indicating a defensive restriction of the health care provider’s role,
whereby her duty is to provide
the relevant information, ensure that it is
understood, and then leave the patient alone to make her or his decision.’
Grant
Gillett and Simon Walker, ‘The Evolution of Informed Consent’
(2012) 19 Journal of Law and Medicine 673,
675.
[110] For discussion, see
Gillett and Walker, ibid. They criticise a formalistic depiction of consent as a
‘tick-box’ exercise:
Consent can function as a relatively shallow gloss on a forced choice ...
Autonomy in such circumstances can be a sham and no substitute
for free,
responsive and rational cooperation with a clinician. Real empowerment actually
enables a patient to be part of the development
of a management plan that leads
to an outcome he or she can accept. That way a person can properly take some
responsibility for her
or his own health care rather than merely being loaded
with a great deal of complex information [and] little in the way of guidance
in
understanding it...’ (at
676).
[111] Australian Medical
Association, Code of Ethics 2004. Editorially Revised 2006. Revised 2016,
para 1.5
<https://ama.com.au/position-statement/code-ethics-2004-editorially-revised-2006-revised-2016>.
[112]
Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board [2015] UKSC 11, para 81. The Court
further comments on the way in which ‘law contributes to the incidence of
litigation’ and posits:
an approach which results in patients being aware that the outcome of
treatment is uncertain and potentially dangerous, and in their
taking
responsibility for the ultimate choice to undergo that treatment, may be less
likely to encourage recriminations and litigation,
in the event of an adverse
outcome, than an approach which requires patients to rely on their doctors to
determine whether a risk
inherent in a particular form of treatment should be
incurred (para 93).
For commentary on this decision, see e.g. A Coulter, A
Hopkins and B Moulton, ‘Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board:
Transforming Informed Consent’ (2017) 99(1) Royal College of Surgeons
Bulletin 36.
[113]
Rogers v Whitaker, above n 22, para
14.
[114] Hall et al, above n
86.
[115] Gillett and Walker,
above n 109, 675.
[116] Mark
Schlesinger and Rachel Grob, ‘Treating, Fast and Slow: Americans’
Understanding of and Responses to Low-Value Care’
(2017) 95(1) Milbank
Quarterly 70, 82 (emphasis
added).
[117]
Ibid.
[118] France
Légaré et al, ‘Interventions for Improving the Adoption of
Shared Decision Making by Healthcare Professionals’
(2014) 15(9)
Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews CD006732. doi:
10.1002/14651858.CD006732.pub3. See also MJ Barry and S Edgman-Levitan,
‘Shared Decision-Making – Pinnacle
of Patient-Centred Care’
(2012) 366 New England Journal of Medicine
780.
[119]
Ibid.
[120] Rachel A Lindor et
al, ‘Liability and Informed Consent in the Context of Shared Decision
Making’ (2016) 23(12) Academic Emergency Medicine 1428. See also
Marleen Kunneman and Victor M Montori, ‘When Patient-Centred Care is Worth
Doing Well: Informed Consent or Shared
Decision-Making’ (2016) BMJ
Quality & Safety
<http://qualitysafety.bmj.com/content/early/2016/09/26/bmjqs-2016-005969.long>
who write that while SDM ‘requires a human connection of careful and kind
care, informed consent procedures call for a
more technical and mechanical
approach, a formal one-way provision of information in which boxes of topics
addressed are to be actually
or metaphorically ticked for administrative and
legal purposes.’
[121]
Doherty et al, above n 102, 207. See also Kunneman and Montori, above n 118, and
DK Sokol, “Let’s Stop Consenting Patients”
(2014) 348
British Medical Journal g2192.
[122] Ibid.
[123] MA Durand et al,
‘Do Interventions Designed to Support Shared Decision-Making Reduce Health
Inequalities? A Systematic Review
and Meta-Analysis’ (2014) 9(4) PLoS
One e94670; Julia CM van Weert et al, ‘Decision Aids to Help Older
People Make Health Decisions: A Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis’
(2016) 16 BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making
45.
[124] France
Légaré and Philippe Thompson-Leduc, ‘Twelve Myths about
Shared Decision Making’ (2014) 96 Patient Education and Counseling
281.
[125] Glyn Elwyn,
Dominick L Frosch and Sarah Kobrin, ‘Implementing Shared
Decision-Making: Consider All the Consequences’
(2016) 11:114
Implementation Science DOI:
10.1186/s13012-016-0480-9.
[126]
McCartney et al argue that ‘[u]sable decision aids should now be seen as
one of the most important end products for evidence
based medicine’:
Margaret McCartney et al, ‘Making Evidence Based Medicine Work for
Individual Patients’ (2016)
353 British Medical Journal
i2452.
[127] Dawn Stacey et
al, ‘Decision Aids for People Facing Health Treatment or Screening
Decisions’ (2017) Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews
<http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/14651858.CD001431.pub5/full>;
Anna R Gagliardi et al, ‘Patient-Mediated Knowledge Translation (PKT)
Interventions for Clinical Encounters: A Systematic
Review’ (2016) 11(26)
Implementation Science doi: 10.1186/s13012-016-0389-3. Note that a recent
Canadian study concluded that most patient materials developed for Choosing
Wisely
Canada do not meet all the decision aid criteria established by the
International Patient Decision Aid Standards: France Légaré
et al,
‘Do Choosing Wisely Tools Meet Criteria for Patient Decision Aids? A
Descriptive Analysis of Patient Materials’
(2016) 6(8) British Medical
Journal Open e011918.
[128] France
Légaré et al, ‘Interventions for Improving the
Adoption of Shared Decision Making by Healthcare Professionals’ (2014)
15(9) Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews CD006732. This review could
not determine the superiority of any particular intervention but concluded that
strategies targeted at
patients, practitioners or both are better than doing
nothing to promote SDM.
[129]
See e.g., D Stacey et al, above n 127 (reporting: ‘The effect of decision
aids [for SDM] on length of consultation varied from
8 minutes shorter to 23
minutes longer (median 2.55 minutes longer) with 2 studies indicating
statistically-significantly longer,
1 study shorter, and 6 studies reporting no
difference in consultation
length.’)
[130] Yael
Schenker and Alan Meisel, ‘Informed Consent in Clinical Care –
Practical Considerations in the Effort to Achieve
Ethical Goals’ (2011)
305(11) Journal of the American Medical Association 1130,
1131.
[131] E Grunfeld et al,
‘Improving Chronic Disease Prevention and Screening in Primary Care:
Results of the BETTER Pragmatic Cluster
Randomized Controlled Trial’
(2013) 14 BMC Family Practice 175 (patients had a one-hour consultation
with a Prevention Practitioner, which was found to be cost-effective in
improving prevention
education and appropriate
screening)
[132] Lucio
Naccarella, Louise N Greenstock and Peter M Brooks, ‘A Framework to
Support Team-Based Models of Primary Care Within
the Australian Health Care
System’ (2012) 1(Suppl 3) Medical Journal of Australia Open 22;
Nola M Ries, ‘Innovation in Healthcare, Innovation in Law: Does the Law
Support Interprofessional Collaboration in Canadian
Health Systems?’
(2016) 54 Osgoode Hall Law Journal
87.
[133] Above n 112, para
76.
[134] See e.g. AH Krist et
al, “MyPreventive Care: Implementation and Dissemination of an Interactive
Preventive Health Record in
Three Practice-Based Research Networks Serving
Disadvantaged Patients - A Randomized Cluster Trial” (2014) 9
Implementation Science 181; Schenker and Meisel, above n 128, cite the
iMedConsent software used by the US Department of Veterans Affairs health system
<https://www.ethics.va.gov/activities/espd.asp>.
[135]
See <https://myhealthrecord.gov.au/>. Around 4.6 million Australians have
registered for a personally controlled electronic
health
record.
[136] Mark Harris,
‘The Interface Between Primary Health Care and Population Health:
Challenges and Opportunities for Prevention’
(2016) 26(1) Public Health
Research & Practice
e2611601.
[137] Daniel E Hall
et al, ‘The Impact of iMedConsent on Patient Decision-Making Regarding
Cholecystectomy and Inguinal Herniorrhaphy’
(2012) 175(2) Journal of
Surgical Research
227.
[138] L Hanna et al,
‘Patient Perspectives on a Personally Controlled Electronic Health Record
Used in Regional Australia: “I
Can Be Like My Own
Doctor”’(2016) Health Information Management Journal pii:
1833358316661063.
[139] Mona
Krouss, Lindsay Croft and Daniel J Morgan, ‘Physician Understanding and
Ability to Communicate Harms and Benefits of Common
Medical Treatments’
(2016) 176(10) JAMA Internal Medicine 1565; O Wegwarth et al, ‘Do
Physicians Understand Cancer Screening Statistics? A National Survey of Primary
Care Physicians
in the United States’ (2012) 156(5) Annals of Internal
Medicine 340.
[140]
Brian J Zikmund-Fisher et al, ‘Perceived Barriers to Implementing
Individual Choosing Wisely Recommendations in Two National
Surveys of Primary
Care Providers’ (2016) 32(2) Journal of General Internal Medicine
211. ER Carrier et al, ‘High Physician Concern about Malpractice Risk
Predicts More Aggressive Diagnostic Testing in Office-Based
Practice’
(2013) 32(8) Health Affairs
1383.
[141] Zikmund-Fisher et
al, ibid. The authors express concern (at 215) that practitioners might
anticipate ‘patient barriers to acceptance
of recommendations to reduce
service utilization that either do not exist or could be easily overcome.’
[142] Ray Moynihan et al,
‘What Do You Think Overdiagnosis Means? A Qualitative Analysis of
Responses From a National Community Survey
of Australians’ (2015) 5(5)
BMJ Open e007436 doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2014-007436, at
6.
[143] William Silverstein et
al, ‘A Survey of Primary Care Patients’ Readiness to Engage in the
De-Adoption Practices Recommended
by Choosing Wisely Canada’ (2016) 9
BMC Research Notes
301.
[144] Karen L Posner,
Julie Severson and Karen B Domino, ‘The Role of Informed Consent in
Patient Complaints: Reducing Hidden Health
System Costs and Improving Patient
Engagement Through Shared Decision Making” (2015) 35(2) Journal of
Healthcare Risk Management
38.
[145] Elwyn and colleagues
have recently proposed a research agenda to examine the effects of SDM, above
note 123. Durand et al conclude
that there is currently insufficient evidence to
determine whether SDM reduces medical malpractice claims, but some studies
indicate
that clinicians face greater liability risk when they fail to elicit or
ignore patient preferences: M Durand et al, “Can Shared
Decision-Making
Reduce Medical Malpractice Litigation? A Systematic Review” (2015) 15
BMC Health Services Research 167. American commentators suggest that a
shift to SDM ‘will bring contract principles to the fore of
patient-physician interactions’
and legal disputes, when they arise, may
be framed more often in contract than tort law: Edward P Monico, Arthur Calise
and Joseph
Calabro, ‘Torts to Contract? Moving from Informed Consent to
Shared Decision-making’ (2008) 28(4) Journal of Healthcare Risk
Management 7.
[146]
Elshaug et al, above n 3,
1.
[147] Ibid, 3.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UTSLRS/2017/16.html