Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Law Students' Journal |
Last Updated: 17 November 2012
IS PREVENTION REALLY BETTER THAN CURE?
AN EXPLORATION OF PREDICTIVE GENETIC SCREENING AS A
FUTURE HEALTH SERVICE FOR NEW ZEALAND
EMILY HARRIS*
Introduction
Predictive genetic screening is a technology that can be applied to a population to determine each person’s risk of developing a particular genetic disease in the future. Whilst genetic screening has not yet been undertaken in New Zealand, the technology is already in use overseas.1
Currently, New Zealand has not made any specific legislative provision for
genetic screening, but the introduction of a new Public
Health Bill that might
deal with genetic screening is planned.2 The Bill has not yet been
drafted, which makes now the ideal time to consider the adequacy of New
Zealand’s existing legal
framework to deal with genetic
screening, and look at what guidance the regulation of genetic screening in
other jurisdictions
could provide in drafting the Public Health Bill.
This paper will examine the potential benefits and risks of genetic
screening in relation to the paradigm of a competent
adult, and briefly mention
some additional concerns that might arise if a genetic screening
programme were targeted
at newborns or children. The possibility of genetic
screening prior to birth will not be considered in this paper. Prenatal
screening
raises different concerns to postnatal screening, and therefore would
likely be regulated differently from postnatal screening.
* Candidate for LLB(Hons) BSc, University of Otago.
1 For example, Tay-Sachs carrier screening has been carried out since 1970 in Jewish
populations (See, eg, Paul Edelson, 'The Tay-Sachs Disease Screening Program in the U.S. As a Model for the Control of Genetic Disease: An Historical View' (1997) 7 Health Matrix 125); Premarital screening for thalessemia carrier status has been carried out in Cyprus since the 1970s (See, eg, Panayiotis Ioannou, ‘Thalessemia Prevention in Cyprus’ in Ruth Chadwick et al (eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999) pp. 55, 58).
2 Ministry of Health, Health Act Review and the Proposed Public Health Bill
http://www.moh.govt.nz/moh.nsf/wpg_Index/News+and+Issues-
Health+Act+review+and+the+proposed+Public+Health+Bill at 18 May
2006.
108
The New Zealand Law Students’ Journal (2006) 1 NZLSJ
108
The New Zealand Law Students’ Journal (2006) 1 NZLSJ
A: What is ‘Genetic Screening’?
The term ‘genetic screening’ can be used in different senses in
different contexts. In this paper, ‘genetic screening’
means testing
a large number of people, who do not necessarily have disease symptoms
or any indication that they are
at increased risk of disease, for their
genetic status in relation to a particular disease.3
Genetic screening can be used to detect disease-causing genes before
disease symptoms manifest. Screening for genes which
make an
individual very likely or almost certain to develop a disease is known as
pre-symptomatic screening. Pre-symptomatic screening must be
distinguished from susceptibility (or pre-disposition)
screening, which tests for genes that increase a person’s risk of
developing a disease but are not the sole determinant
of whether a person will
develop the disease. Environmental factors also play a role in the
development of these diseases,
known as multifactorial diseases. Most
cancers and some forms of diabetes are multifactorial diseases.
Genetic screening could also be used to determine whether a person is a
carrier of a recessive disease allele.4 A person who has a
recessive disease allele will not suffer from the disease, but their children
could be affected if their partner
also carries the same recessive allele. This
is called carrier screening, the unique implications of which
will not be covered in this paper.
B: The Benefits that Genetic Screening could bring to New Zealand
The broad aim of population screening is to reduce the morbidity and mortality associated with a disease.5 The population as a whole benefits from reduced incidence and severity of a disease because less of the limited healthcare budget needs to be spent on its treatment.
A: What is ‘Genetic Screening’?
The term ‘genetic screening’ can be used in different senses
in different contexts. In this paper, ‘genetic screening’
means
testing a large number of people, who do not necessarily have disease
symptoms or any indication that they are
at increased risk of disease, for
their genetic status in relation to a particular
disease.3
Genetic screening can be used to detect
disease-causing genes before disease symptoms manifest. Screening for
genes which
make an individual very likely or almost certain to develop a
disease is known as pre-symptomatic screening. Pre-symptomatic
screening must be distinguished from susceptibility (or
pre-disposition) screening, which tests for genes that increase a
person’s risk of developing a disease but are not the sole determinant
of
whether a person will develop the disease. Environmental factors also play a
role in the development of these diseases,
known as multifactorial
diseases. Most cancers and some forms of diabetes are multifactorial
diseases.
Genetic screening could also be used to determine whether a
person is a carrier of a recessive disease allele.4 A person who
has a recessive disease allele will not suffer from the disease, but their
children could be affected if their partner
also carries the same recessive
allele. This is called carrier screening, the unique implications
of which will not be covered in this paper.
B: The Benefits that Genetic Screening could bring to New Zealand
The broad aim of population screening is to reduce the morbidity and
mortality associated with a disease.5 The population as a whole
benefits from reduced incidence and severity of a disease because less of
the limited healthcare budget
needs to be spent on its treatment.
3 See Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours: The Protection of Human Genetic
Information in Australia, ALRC 96 (2003), ch. 24.
4 Genes can exist in different forms, called ‘alleles’. For example, the gene for eye colour
has a ‘blue’ allele and a ‘brown’ allele. In relation to disease-causing genes, a person could have a ‘normal’ allele or a ‘disease’ allele.
5 National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand: Criteria to Assess
Screening Programmes (2003), p. 6.
3 See Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours: The
Protection of Human Genetic
Information in Australia, ALRC 96
(2003), ch. 24.
4 Genes can exist in different forms, called
‘alleles’. For example, the gene for eye colour
has a
‘blue’ allele and a ‘brown’ allele. In relation to
disease-causing genes, a person could have a ‘normal’
allele or a
‘disease’ allele.
5 National Health Committee,
Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand: Criteria to
Assess
Screening Programmes (2003), p.
6.
Predictive Genetic Screening in New Zealand 109
Individuals may benefit from participation in a population genetic
screening programme in many ways. Knowledge of a risk
of disease could
allow the initiation of preventive strategies against the disease, such as
administering prophylactic drugs,
more frequent screening for the
manifestation of diseases like cancer, or lifestyle changes such as diet
alteration6 and avoiding exposure to disease-causing environmental
agents.7
Participation in genetic screening may be psychologically beneficial.
Those with negative results, showing they are not at
increased risk of a
disease, are likely to feel relief and reassurance. Where there is a family
history of the disease being screened
for, even a positive test result can be
psychologically beneficial, because it provides certainty as to the
individual’s disease
risk status.8 Knowledge of their
disease risk may prompt the individual to take steps to plan for their future
that they might not have taken
without that knowledge.9
Genetic screening programmes have several potential advantages over existing disease screening programmes. Genetic tests do not require any manifestation of disease symptoms to detect a risk of disease, so screening can be carried out at any age.10 DNA samples can be obtained by relatively non-invasive techniques like cheek swabs or saliva samples rather than invasive biopsies. It will usually be more
Predictive Genetic Screening in New Zealand
109
Individuals may benefit from participation in a
population genetic screening programme in many ways. Knowledge of a risk
of disease could allow the initiation of preventive strategies against the
disease, such as administering prophylactic drugs,
more frequent screening for
the manifestation of diseases like cancer, or lifestyle changes such as
diet alteration6 and avoiding exposure to disease-causing
environmental agents.7
Participation in genetic screening
may be psychologically beneficial. Those with negative results, showing they
are not at
increased risk of a disease, are likely to feel relief and
reassurance. Where there is a family history of the disease being screened
for,
even a positive test result can be psychologically beneficial, because it
provides certainty as to the individual’s disease
risk status.8
Knowledge of their disease risk may prompt the individual to take
steps to plan for their future that they might not have taken
without that
knowledge.9
Genetic screening programmes have several
potential advantages over existing disease screening programmes. Genetic tests
do not
require any manifestation of disease symptoms to detect a risk of
disease, so screening can be carried out at any
age.10 DNA
samples can be obtained by relatively non-invasive techniques like cheek
swabs or saliva samples rather than invasive
biopsies. It will usually
be more
6 Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Genetic Screening: Ethical Issues (1993), p. 5; Dorothy Wertz et al (for the World Health Organization), Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics (2003), p. 5.
7 World Health Organization, Genomics and World Health: Report of the Advisory Committee on
Health Research (2002), p. 55.
8 Studies have shown that this can reduce anxiety. See Marita Broadstock et al,
‘Psychological Consequences of Predictive Genetic Testing: A Systematic Review’ (2000)
8 European Journal of Human Genetics 731, p. 736.
9 For example, making a will or setting aside money for future treatment or care. See
generally, American Society for Human Genetics and American College of Medical Genetics, ‘Points to Consider: Ethical, Legal and Psychosocial Implications of Genetic Testing in Children and Adolescents’ (1995) 57 American Journal of Human Genetics 1233, p.
1236.
10 Angus Clarke, ‘The Genetic Testing of Children’ in Ruth Chadwick et al (eds), The
Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999) 231, p. 231.
6 Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Genetic Screening: Ethical
Issues (1993), p. 5; Dorothy Wertz et al (for the World Health
Organization), Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics (2003), p.
5.
7 World Health Organization, Genomics and World Health:
Report of the Advisory Committee on
Health Research (2002),
p. 55.
8 Studies have shown that this can reduce
anxiety. See Marita Broadstock et al,
‘Psychological
Consequences of Predictive Genetic Testing: A Systematic Review’
(2000)
8 European Journal of Human Genetics 731, p.
736.
9 For example, making a will or setting aside money for future
treatment or care. See
generally, American Society for Human
Genetics and American College of Medical Genetics, ‘Points to Consider:
Ethical,
Legal and Psychosocial Implications of Genetic Testing in Children and
Adolescents’ (1995) 57 American Journal of Human Genetics 1233,
p.
1236.
10 Angus Clarke, ‘The Genetic
Testing of Children’ in Ruth Chadwick et al (eds),
The
Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999) 231, p.
231.
cost-effective to predict the future risk of disease and take preventive
steps, than to diagnose and treat diseases when symptoms
manifest.11
Epidemiological data on genetic diseases gathered from population screening
would be invaluable to researchers. Better understanding
of the epidemiology
of genetic diseases is the first step towards understanding
their causes, which could
ultimately lead to better treatment and/or
preventive strategies.12
C: The Risks Associated With Population Genetic Screening
Like most medical tests, genetic tests can produce false results due to human
error and the unavoidable inherent limitations of
the test.13 A
false positive result indicates that an individual has the disease-causing
allele being tested for when in fact they do not. A false
positive result is
likely to cause unnecessary anxiety,14 and may lead to
unnecessary invasive diagnostic tests, treatment or preventive
measures.15 On the other hand, a false negative result indicates
that an individual does not have the disease-causing allele when in fact they
do. A false negative result might cause an individual to miss out on
beneficial preventive interventions,16 and to feel falsely
reassured about the state of their health.17
Genetic test results can be complex and uncertain. Predictive testing cannot determine when disease symptoms will manifest, or the severity of symptoms that will be experienced by an individual.18 Pre- disposition testing cannot determine whether an individual will develop
cost-effective to predict the future risk of disease and take preventive
steps, than to diagnose and treat diseases when symptoms
manifest.11
Epidemiological data on genetic diseases gathered
from population screening would be invaluable to researchers. Better
understanding
of the epidemiology of genetic diseases is the
first step towards understanding their causes, which could
ultimately lead to better treatment and/or preventive
strategies.12
C: The Risks Associated With Population Genetic Screening
Like
most medical tests, genetic tests can produce false results due to human error
and the unavoidable inherent limitations of
the test.13 A false
positive result indicates that an individual has the disease-causing allele
being tested for when in fact they do not. A false
positive result is likely to
cause unnecessary anxiety,14 and may lead to unnecessary
invasive diagnostic tests, treatment or preventive measures.15
On the other hand, a false negative result indicates that an individual
does not have the disease-causing allele when in fact they
do. A false negative
result might cause an individual to miss out on beneficial preventive
interventions,16 and to feel falsely reassured about the
state of their health.17
Genetic test results can be
complex and uncertain. Predictive testing cannot determine when disease
symptoms will manifest,
or the severity of symptoms that will be
experienced by an individual.18 Pre- disposition testing
cannot determine whether an individual will develop
11 See British Medical Association, Population Screening and Genetic Testing: A Briefing on
Current Programmes and Technologies (2005), p. 4.
12 See generally Sandrine Sabatier (for the Council of Europe), Report of the Working Party on Human Genetics (1997), ch. 1.
13 See Denise Goh Li Meng, Medical, Ethical, Legal and Social Issues in Genetic Testing and
Genetic Screening Programs (2005), ch. 5.
14 Darren Shickle, ‘The Wilson and Jungner Principles of Screening and Genetic Testing’
in Ruth Chadwick et al (eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999), pp. 1, 32.
15 See British Medical Association, supra n. 11, p. 3.
16 Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra n 3, ch. 24.
17 Shickle, supra n. 14, p. 33.
18 Lori Andrews and Erin Shaugnessy Zuiker, 'Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues in Genetic
Testing for Complex Genetic Diseases' (2003) 37 Valparaiso University Law Review 793, p.
807.
11 See British Medical Association, Population Screening and
Genetic Testing: A Briefing on
Current Programmes and
Technologies (2005), p. 4.
12 See generally Sandrine
Sabatier (for the Council of Europe), Report of the Working Party on Human
Genetics (1997), ch. 1.
13 See Denise Goh Li Meng,
Medical, Ethical, Legal and Social Issues in Genetic Testing
and
Genetic Screening Programs (2005), ch.
5.
14 Darren Shickle, ‘The Wilson and Jungner
Principles of Screening and Genetic Testing’
in Ruth Chadwick et
al (eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999), pp. 1,
32.
15 See British Medical Association, supra n. 11, p.
3.
16 Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra
n 3, ch. 24.
17 Shickle, supra n. 14, p. 33.
18
Lori Andrews and Erin Shaugnessy Zuiker, 'Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues in
Genetic
Testing for Complex Genetic Diseases' (2003) 37 Valparaiso
University Law Review 793, p.
807.
a disease. It can only show some increase in the probability of
developing the disease.19 This information is difficult for many
people to interpret.20 Based on pre-disposition test results,
individuals might undergo preventive interventions involving risk or
inconvenience
to them, when they would never have gone on to develop the
disease.21 A negative test result for a multifactorial disease like
cancer could falsely reassure a person about their health,22
because the absence of a mutation predisposing a person to cancer is
no guarantee that they will not develop cancer.
Some individuals experience worry and anxiety from participating in a screening programme and having to await the results.23 Those with positive test results often suffer distress and depression.24 People who are identified as susceptible to multifactorial diseases like cancer may become obsessively worried about the state of their health.25 This phenomenon, known as ‘the worried well’, can lead to increased absenteeism from work and increased feelings of ill health.26 However, several studies have shown that most emotional reactions tend to be short term, and most genetic testing participants do not suffer any long-term decrease in their quality of life.27 Genetic counselling that confers an accurate understanding of the disease, and the risk of getting it, could alleviate some of the adverse psychological reactions people have to genetic test results.28 People who decline to participate in
a disease. It can only show some increase in the probability of
developing the disease.19 This information is difficult for many
people to interpret.20 Based on pre-disposition test results,
individuals might undergo preventive interventions involving risk or
inconvenience
to them, when they would never have gone on to develop the
disease.21 A negative test result for a multifactorial disease like
cancer could falsely reassure a person about their health,22
because the absence of a mutation predisposing a person to cancer is
no guarantee that they will not develop cancer.
Some individuals
experience worry and anxiety from participating in a screening programme and
having to await the results.23 Those with positive test
results often suffer distress and depression.24 People who are
identified as susceptible to multifactorial diseases like cancer may become
obsessively worried about the state
of their health.25 This
phenomenon, known as ‘the worried well’, can lead to increased
absenteeism from work and increased feelings of ill
health.26
However, several studies have shown that most emotional reactions tend
to be short term, and most genetic testing participants
do not suffer
any long-term decrease in their quality of life.27 Genetic
counselling that confers an accurate understanding of the disease, and the risk
of getting it, could alleviate some of
the adverse psychological reactions
people have to genetic test results.28 People who decline to
participate in
19 Ibid.
20 Loane Skene, ‘Patients’ Rights or Family Responsibilities? – Two Approaches to
Genetic Testing’ (1998) 6 Medical Law Review 1, p. 7.
21 National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand, supra n. 5, p. 10
22 Alice McEwen and Alice Christian, ‘Circumstances, Pitfalls and Limitations of Genetic
Testing’ (Paper presented at the Screening Symposium, Wellington, 2005).
23 See British Medical Association, supra n. 11, p. 4.
24 Neil Sharpe, 'Reinventing the Wheel? Informed Consent and Genetic Testing for
Breast Cancer, Cystic Fibrosis and Huntington Disease' (1997) 22 Queen’s Law Journal 389, p. 396.
25 See Lori Andrews, ‘A Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy: Comparing the Medical, Public Health and Fundamental Rights Models’ (2001) 79 Washington University Law Quarterly 221, p. 242.
26 See Wylie Burke et al, ‘Public Health Strategies to Prevent the Complications of
Hemochromatosis’ in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and Public Health in the 21st Century
(2000) pp. 447, 456.
27 See Judith Benkendorf, Beth Peshkin and Caryn Lerman, ‘Impact of Genetic Information and Genetic Counseling on Public Health’ in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and Public Health in the 21st Century (2000) pp. 361, 376.
28 See Burke et al, supra n. 26, p. 456.
19 Ibid.
20 Loane Skene, ‘Patients’ Rights
or Family Responsibilities? – Two Approaches to
Genetic
Testing’ (1998) 6 Medical Law Review 1, p. 7.
21 National
Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand, supra n. 5,
p. 10
22 Alice McEwen and Alice Christian,
‘Circumstances, Pitfalls and Limitations of Genetic
Testing’
(Paper presented at the Screening Symposium, Wellington, 2005).
23
See British Medical Association, supra n. 11, p. 4.
24 Neil
Sharpe, 'Reinventing the Wheel? Informed Consent and Genetic Testing
for
Breast Cancer, Cystic Fibrosis and Huntington Disease' (1997) 22
Queen’s Law Journal 389, p. 396.
25 See Lori
Andrews, ‘A Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy: Comparing the
Medical, Public Health and Fundamental Rights Models’
(2001) 79
Washington University Law Quarterly 221, p. 242.
26 See Wylie
Burke et al, ‘Public Health Strategies to Prevent the Complications
of
Hemochromatosis’ in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and
Public Health in the 21st Century
(2000) pp. 447,
456.
27 See Judith Benkendorf, Beth Peshkin and Caryn
Lerman, ‘Impact of Genetic Information and Genetic Counseling on Public
Health’
in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and Public Health in the
21st Century (2000) pp. 361, 376.
28 See Burke et al,
supra n. 26, p. 456.
testing experience the highest levels of distress,29 suggesting
that knowledge of genetic status is generally better than uncertainty.
The familial nature of genetic information means that when an
individual undergoes genetic testing, the psychological
effects discussed above
can extend to other family members. The stress and anxiety associated with a
positive genetic test
result can cause conflict in families, especially
where some family members have the allele and others do not.30
One person’s genetic screening result may reveal genetic
information about other members of their family. Some family
members could see
this as beneficial, but others might not want to know about their future
risk of genetic disease.31 There is also a chance that a genetic
test might reveal a genetic abnormality other than the one being tested
for,32 or other non-medical information, such as
paternity.33 Whether or not this extraneous information
should be revealed to the participant is ethically
controversial.34
There is widespread concern that people might be discriminated against by
insurers and employers because of their genetic
susceptibility to
disease. Genetic discrimination has happened in the past. For example,
African-American carriers of the sickle-cell
anaemia allele were discriminated
against in the United States in the 1960s and 1970s.35
Genetic screening may cause people to focus on the genetic factors that contribute to multifactorial disease and detract attention from the role of environmental factors.36 This skewed focus may act as a disincentive to taking action to reduce or eliminate environmental factors that
testing experience the highest levels of distress,29 suggesting
that knowledge of genetic status is generally better than
uncertainty.
The familial nature of genetic information means
that when an individual undergoes genetic testing, the psychological
effects
discussed above can extend to other family members. The stress and anxiety
associated with a positive genetic test
result can cause conflict in
families, especially where some family members have the allele and
others do not.30 One person’s genetic screening result
may reveal genetic information about other members of their family. Some family
members could see this as beneficial, but others might not want to know
about their future risk of genetic disease.31 There is also a chance
that a genetic test might reveal a genetic abnormality other than the one being
tested for,32 or other non-medical information, such
as paternity.33 Whether or not this extraneous information
should be revealed to the participant is ethically
controversial.34
There is widespread concern that people might
be discriminated against by insurers and employers because of their
genetic
susceptibility to disease. Genetic discrimination has happened in the
past. For example, African-American carriers of the sickle-cell
anaemia allele
were discriminated against in the United States in the 1960s and
1970s.35
Genetic screening may cause people to focus on the
genetic factors that contribute to multifactorial disease and detract attention
from the role of environmental factors.36 This skewed focus may act
as a disincentive to taking action to reduce or eliminate environmental
factors that
29 Ibid.
30 See Skene, supra n. 21, p. 8.
31 See generally Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra n. 3, ch. 24;
ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9, p. 1236.
32 Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 809-810.
33 Dorothy Wertz, 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric Genetics: Views of Geneticists, Parents and
Primary Care Physicians' (1998) 6 Health Law Journal 3, p. 3.
34 See, eg, Nuffield Council on Bioethics, supra n. 6, p. 41; Wertz et al Review of Ethical
Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, pp. 48-49; Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 810.
35 See Mary Davidson et al, ‘Consumer Perspectives on Genetic Testing: Lessons
Learned’ in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and Public Health in the 21st Century (2000), pp.
579, 589.
36 See Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 821.
29 Ibid.
30 See Skene, supra n. 21, p.
8.
31 See generally Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially
Yours, supra n. 3, ch. 24;
ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9, p.
1236.
32 Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 809-810.
33
Dorothy Wertz, 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric Genetics: Views of
Geneticists, Parents and
Primary Care Physicians' (1998) 6 Health Law
Journal 3, p. 3.
34 See, eg, Nuffield Council on
Bioethics, supra n. 6, p. 41; Wertz et al Review of
Ethical
Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, pp. 48-49;
Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 810.
35 See Mary
Davidson et al, ‘Consumer Perspectives on Genetic Testing:
Lessons
Learned’ in Muin Khoury et al (eds), Genetics and
Public Health in the 21st Century (2000), pp.
579, 589.
36
See Andrews and Zuiker, supra n. 18, pp. 821.
contribute to disease.37 For example, genetically vulnerable
employees might be excluded from hazardous work environments rather than
employers being forced
to make their workplaces safer,38 which seems
unfair and illogical.
Mäori have cultural concerns about the collection and protection
of health information, and the use, storage and
disposal of body tissue
samples.39 If these concerns were to discourage
Mäori from participating in future genetic screening
programmes,
this could increase existing health inequalities between
Mäori and other New Zealanders.
While genetic screening programmes have the potential to decrease
long-term health costs by preventing disease or reducing
its severity, the
costs of setting up a programme may place an excessive burden on the health
system in the short term.40
Genetic screening of minors raises additional concerns. These concerns are important because there is a good chance that future genetic screening programmes will target newborns. The infrastructure for newborn disease screening is already established, and screening newborns would maximise the opportunity for preventive interventions against disease. Minors generally lack legal competence to consent to medical services, so their parents must make the decision for them. This practice is generally seen as acceptable in relation to genetic testing where the disease being tested for manifests during childhood or adolescence, and treatment or preventive measures are available.41 In
contribute to disease.37 For example, genetically vulnerable
employees might be excluded from hazardous work environments rather than
employers being forced
to make their workplaces safer,38 which seems
unfair and illogical.
Mäori have cultural concerns about the
collection and protection of health information, and the use, storage
and
disposal of body tissue samples.39 If these concerns
were to discourage Mäori from participating in future
genetic screening programmes,
this could increase existing health
inequalities between Mäori and other New Zealanders.
While genetic
screening programmes have the potential to decrease long-term health
costs by preventing disease or reducing
its severity, the costs of setting up
a programme may place an excessive burden on the health system in the short
term.40
Genetic screening of minors raises additional
concerns. These concerns are important because there is a good chance
that
future genetic screening programmes will target newborns. The
infrastructure for newborn disease screening is already
established,
and screening newborns would maximise the opportunity for preventive
interventions against disease. Minors generally
lack legal competence to
consent to medical services, so their parents must make the decision
for them. This practice
is generally seen as acceptable in relation to genetic
testing where the disease being tested for manifests during childhood or
adolescence,
and treatment or preventive measures are available.41
In
37 See, eg, Mairi Levitt, ‘A Sociological Perspective on Genetic Screening’ in Ruth
Chadwick et al (eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999), pp. 157, 162.
38 See, eg, Richard Sharp, 'The Evolution of Predictive Genetic Testing: Deciphering
Gene-Environment Interactions' (2001) 41 Jurimetrics 145, p. 162.
39 National Health Committee, Molecular Genetic Testing in New Zealand (2003), p. 23.
40 Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra n. 3, ch. 24.
41 See, eg, Clarke, supra n. 10, 233; Clinical Genetics Society, The Genetic Testing of Children
(1994) http://www.bshg.org.uk/documents/official_docs/testchil.htm at 20 December
2005; National Health Committee, Molecular Genetic Testing in New Zealand (2003) 24; Wertz et al, Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, p. 58; Genetics Interest Group, Genetics Interest Group Response to the Clinical Genetics Society Report "The Genetic Testing of Children" (1995) 3. The Genetics Interest Group would allow testing for child-onset conditions where no treatment or prevention is available because they believe that the benefits associated with knowledge of genetic status justify this. However, it is unlikely
37 See, eg, Mairi Levitt, ‘A Sociological
Perspective on Genetic Screening’ in Ruth
Chadwick et al
(eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening (1999), pp. 157,
162.
38 See, eg, Richard Sharp, 'The Evolution of
Predictive Genetic Testing: Deciphering
Gene-Environment Interactions'
(2001) 41 Jurimetrics 145, p. 162.
39 National
Health Committee, Molecular Genetic Testing in New Zealand (2003), p.
23.
40 Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours,
supra n. 3, ch. 24.
41 See, eg, Clarke, supra n. 10, 233;
Clinical Genetics Society, The Genetic Testing of Children
(1994)
http://www.bshg.org.uk/documents/official_docs/testchil.htm
at 20 December
2005; National Health Committee, Molecular Genetic
Testing in New Zealand (2003) 24; Wertz et al, Review of Ethical Issues
in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, p. 58; Genetics Interest Group, Genetics
Interest Group Response to the Clinical Genetics Society Report "The Genetic
Testing of Children" (1995) 3. The Genetics Interest Group would allow
testing for child-onset conditions where no treatment or prevention is available
because they believe that the benefits associated with knowledge of genetic
status justify this. However, it is unlikely
this situation, the results will be of immediate relevance and direct benefit to the child. However, if the disease is unlikely to manifest until adulthood, most commentators believe that the decision whether to participate in testing should be left up to the child when they reach maturity, unless there is potential for immediate intervention to prevent, delay the onset of or decrease the severity of the disease.42 The objection to testing children for adult-onset diseases is that it exposes them to risks and abrogates their future rights. Testing for adult-onset diseases during childhood takes away a child’s right to decide whether to be tested, which is seen as a violation of their future autonomy.43
When children are tested, the results are disclosed to their
parents, which deprives them of the right to confidentiality
that they would
have if they were tested as an adult.44 By being tested
during childhood, children are also deprived of the right to participate in and
benefit from genetic counselling
at an adult level.45 Children are
unlikely to be able to adequately understand the implications of undergoing
genetic screening, and are unlikely
to understand the probabilistic nature of
the test results.46
If parents find out that their child is at risk for a genetic disease, they might treat them differently, and could restrict their participation in
this situation, the results will be of immediate relevance and
direct benefit to the child. However, if the disease is unlikely
to manifest
until adulthood, most commentators believe that the decision whether to
participate in testing should be left up to
the child when they reach
maturity, unless there is potential for immediate intervention to
prevent, delay the onset
of or decrease the severity of the disease.42
The objection to testing children for adult-onset diseases is that it
exposes them to risks and abrogates their future rights. Testing
for adult-onset
diseases during childhood takes away a child’s right to decide whether to
be tested, which is seen as a violation
of their future
autonomy.43
When children are tested, the results are
disclosed to their parents, which deprives them of the right to
confidentiality
that they would have if they were tested as an
adult.44 By being tested during childhood, children are also
deprived of the right to participate in and benefit from genetic counselling
at
an adult level.45 Children are unlikely to be able to adequately
understand the implications of undergoing genetic screening, and are
unlikely
to understand the probabilistic nature of the test
results.46
If parents find out that their child is at risk for
a genetic disease, they might treat them differently, and could restrict
their participation in
that these benefits would justify population genetic screening for conditions with no treatment or preventive strategy.
42 See, eg, American Medical Association, Testing Children for Genetic Status (1995) 4; ASHG
and ACMG, supra n. 9, 1233; Laura Arbour, Guidelines for Genetic Testing of Healthy Children
– Canadian Paediatric Society Position Statement (2002)
http://www.cps.ca/English/statements/B/b03-01.pdf at 30 May 2006, p. 4; Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41; Genetics Interest Group, supra n. 41, p. 5; Governo Italiano (National Bioethics Committee), Bioethical Guidelines for Genetic Testing (1999) http://www.governo.it/bioetica/eng/opinions/genetictest.html at 20 December 2005; Human Genetics Commission (UK), Whose Hands on Your Genes? (2000), p. 9; Human Genetics Society of Australasia, Predictive Testing in Children and Adolescents (2005); Meng, supra n. 13, p. 7; National Health Committee, Molecular Genetic Testing in New Zealand, supra n. 39, p. 24; Nuffield Council on Bioethics, supra n 6, 38; Provincial Advisory Committee on New Predictive Genetic Technologies, Genetic Services in Ontario: Mapping the Future (2001), p. 36 Wertz 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric Genetics', supra n. 33, p. 23; Wertz et al, Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, p. 59; World Medical Association, Statement on Genetics and Medicine (2005).
43 Wertz, 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric Genetics', supra n. 33, p. 9.
44 See, eg, Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41, p. 3.
45 Clarke, supra n. 10, p. 234.
46 American Medical Association, supra n. 42, p. 2.
that these benefits would justify population genetic screening for conditions
with no treatment or preventive strategy.
42 See, eg, American Medical
Association, Testing Children for Genetic Status (1995) 4;
ASHG
and ACMG, supra n. 9, 1233; Laura Arbour, Guidelines for
Genetic Testing of Healthy Children
– Canadian Paediatric
Society Position Statement (2002)
http://www.cps.ca/English/statements/B/b03-01.pdf
at 30 May 2006, p. 4; Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41; Genetics
Interest Group, supra n. 41, p. 5; Governo Italiano
(National Bioethics
Committee), Bioethical Guidelines for Genetic Testing (1999)
http://www.governo.it/bioetica/eng/opinions/genetictest.html at 20
December 2005; Human Genetics Commission (UK), Whose Hands on Your Genes?
(2000), p. 9; Human Genetics Society of Australasia, Predictive Testing
in Children and Adolescents (2005); Meng, supra n. 13, p. 7; National Health
Committee, Molecular Genetic Testing in New Zealand, supra n. 39, p. 24;
Nuffield Council on Bioethics, supra n 6, 38; Provincial Advisory Committee on
New Predictive Genetic Technologies,
Genetic Services in Ontario: Mapping the
Future (2001), p. 36 Wertz 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric Genetics', supra n.
33, p. 23; Wertz et al, Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics,
supra n. 6, p. 59; World Medical Association, Statement on Genetics
and Medicine (2005).
43 Wertz, 'Ethical Issues in Pediatric
Genetics', supra n. 33, p. 9.
44 See, eg, Clinical Genetics Society,
supra n. 41, p. 3.
45 Clarke, supra n. 10, p.
234.
46 American Medical Association, supra n. 42, p.
2.
life.47 Knowledge of their risk of developing a genetic
disease might damage a child’s self-esteem48 and impair their
social interaction.49 In addition, screening for adult-onset
diseases exposes children to the risk of future genetic discrimination by
employers and insurers.50 Therefore, screening children for genes
for adult-onset diseases, especially where no treatment or prevention is
available, is
unlikely to be acceptable.51
D: Should New Zealand use Genetic Screening?
At some time in the future New Zealand will have to decide whether and to what extent to utilise genetic screening technology. The substantial health benefits genetic screening could generate, and the possibility of mitigating many of the risks, militate against ruling it out completely. Some method of balancing the numerous and weighty considerations both in favour of and against a particular genetic screening programme will be required. Currently, proposed population disease screening programmes in New Zealand are assessed against a set of criteria developed by the National Health Committee.52 The criteria are based on criteria developed by the World Health Organization that underlie screening programmes in most countries.53
The criteria ‘are intended to inform judgment and are not absolute, as
no existing or potential screening programme fulfils
every criterion
entirely.’54 Below are the eight criteria and a brief
assessment of how well various types of genetic screening fulfil them.
1. The condition is a suitable candidate for screening. The condition must be an important health problem in terms of incidence and prognosis, and be well understood.55 This criterion weighs against population screening for rare genetic diseases, genetic conditions that are not serious, and genetic diseases that we currently know little about.
life.47 Knowledge of their risk of developing a genetic
disease might damage a child’s self-esteem48 and impair their
social interaction.49 In addition, screening for adult-onset
diseases exposes children to the risk of future genetic discrimination by
employers and insurers.50 Therefore, screening children for genes
for adult-onset diseases, especially where no treatment or prevention is
available, is
unlikely to be acceptable.51
D: Should New Zealand use Genetic Screening?
At some time in
the future New Zealand will have to decide whether and to what extent to
utilise genetic screening technology.
The substantial health benefits
genetic screening could generate, and the possibility of mitigating many of the
risks, militate
against ruling it out completely. Some method of balancing the
numerous and weighty considerations both in favour of and against
a
particular genetic screening programme will be required. Currently, proposed
population disease screening programmes in
New Zealand are assessed against
a set of criteria developed by the National Health Committee.52
The criteria are based on criteria developed by the World
Health Organization that underlie screening programmes
in most
countries.53
The criteria ‘are intended to inform judgment
and are not absolute, as no existing or potential screening programme fulfils
every criterion entirely.’54 Below are the eight criteria and
a brief assessment of how well various types of genetic screening fulfil
them.
1. The condition is a suitable candidate for screening. The
condition must be an important health problem in terms of
incidence
and prognosis, and be well understood.55 This criterion weighs
against population screening for rare genetic diseases, genetic conditions
that are not serious, and genetic
diseases that we currently know little
about.
47 See, e.g., Governo Italiano (National Bioethics Committee), supra n. 42 .
48 See, e.g., ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9, p. 1236; Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41, p. 3.
49 See Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41, p. 3.
50 Ibid.
51 Although the concerns raised and positions discussed related to genetic testing, they are equally applicable to genetic screening.
52 National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand, supra n. 5, p. 3.
53 Ibid., p. 17.
54 Ibid., p. 3.
55 Ibid., p. 24.
47 See, e.g., Governo Italiano (National Bioethics Committee),
supra n. 42 .
48 See, e.g., ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9, p. 1236;
Clinical Genetics Society, supra n. 41, p. 3.
49 See Clinical
Genetics Society, supra n. 41, p. 3.
50 Ibid.
51
Although the concerns raised and positions discussed related to genetic
testing, they are equally applicable to genetic screening.
52
National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New
Zealand, supra n. 5, p. 3.
53 Ibid., p. 17.
54
Ibid., p. 3.
55 Ibid., p. 24.
2. There is a suitable test. The safety, simplicity, reliability, and
accuracy of the test are relevant considerations.56 Genetic tests
are generally non- invasive, but, as discussed above, predictive and
susceptibility tests are not very informative.
It would only be
appropriate to screen the population if the test to be used had
an acceptable level
of informativeness.
3. There is an effective and accessible treatment or intervention for the
condition. This criterion would rule out genetic
screening for
conditions that have no effective treatment or preventive strategy.
4. There is high quality evidence that a screening programme is
effective in reducing mortality or morbidity.
For most genetic
conditions, there is a lack of evidence that genetic screening is effective in
reducing mortality or morbidity,
as insufficient research has been
carried out to date. There is evidence to suggest that susceptibility screening
may not
be effective in reducing the incidence of multifactorial
diseases because many people fail to comply with the recommended
lifestyle
changes.57 More research and pilot programmes would need to be
carried out prior to implementing genetic screening programmes to evaluate
their
effectiveness.
5. The potential benefit from the screening programme should
outweigh the potential physical and psychological
harm. Our current lack
of knowledge about the effects of genetic screening would make it difficult to
weigh the potential
benefits of a genetic screening programme
against its risks. Pilot programmes would help to determine the balance of
benefits
and harms for a proposed genetic screening programme.
6. The health care system is capable of supporting all necessary elements of the screening pathway. The screening pathway involves identification of the target population, counselling and informed consent, the test itself, the communication and explanation of the results, further diagnostic tests, and treatment or prophylactic
2. There is a suitable test. The safety, simplicity, reliability, and
accuracy of the test are relevant considerations.56 Genetic tests
are generally non- invasive, but, as discussed above, predictive and
susceptibility tests are not very informative.
It would only be
appropriate to screen the population if the test to be used had
an acceptable level
of informativeness.
3. There is an effective
and accessible treatment or intervention for the condition. This criterion
would rule out genetic
screening for conditions that have no effective
treatment or preventive strategy.
4. There is high quality evidence
that a screening programme is effective in reducing mortality or
morbidity.
For most genetic conditions, there is a lack of evidence that
genetic screening is effective in reducing mortality or morbidity,
as
insufficient research has been carried out to date. There is evidence to
suggest that susceptibility screening may not
be effective in
reducing the incidence of multifactorial diseases because many people fail
to comply with the recommended
lifestyle changes.57 More research
and pilot programmes would need to be carried out prior to implementing genetic
screening programmes to evaluate their
effectiveness.
5. The
potential benefit from the screening programme should outweigh the
potential physical and psychological
harm. Our current lack of knowledge
about the effects of genetic screening would make it difficult to weigh
the potential
benefits of a genetic screening programme against its
risks. Pilot programmes would help to determine the balance of benefits
and
harms for a proposed genetic screening programme.
6. The health
care system is capable of supporting all necessary elements of the
screening pathway. The screening pathway
involves identification of the
target population, counselling and informed consent, the test itself,
the communication
and explanation of the results, further diagnostic
tests, and treatment or prophylactic
56 Ibid.
57 See Benkendorf, Peshkin, and Lerman, supra n. 27, p. 375.
56 Ibid.
57 See Benkendorf, Peshkin, and Lerman, supra
n. 27, p. 375.
interventions where indicated.58 Funding all of these elements
would be expensive, and could be unaffordable under New Zealand’s already
stretched healthcare
budget.
7. There is a consideration of social and ethical issues. Genetic
screening raises numerous ethical and social issues,
some of which were
mentioned above, especially where screening of newborns or children is
proposed.
8. There is a consideration of cost-benefit issues. The cost of
a screening programme must be justified by the benefits
it is expected to bring.
A proposed screening programme must be compared with other possible
interventions to ensure that it represents
the best use of resources.59
For rare genetic diseases, testing the extended families of affected
individuals is likely to be more cost-effective than population
screening.60 Strategies aimed at reducing risk for the whole
population may turn out to be more cost-effective than genetic screening for
multifactorial
diseases like diabetes, heart disease and
cancer.61
The deficiencies in our current knowledge about the effects of genetic
screening make it difficult to assess whether genetic screening
would meet
New Zealand’s current screening programme assessment criteria. The
criteria do not seem to rule out genetic screening
for a disease that is
serious, not rare, reasonably well understood, where some form of treatment or
intervention is available,
and pilot programmes show that screening would be
affordable and effective in reducing mortality or morbidity.
The existing NHC criteria would not necessarily have to be used to assess proposed genetic screening programmes. The existing criteria appear to apply to genetic screening as well as they do to disease screening, but refinements and additional criteria might be necessary for genetic screening. For example, it should be made explicit that for
interventions where indicated.58 Funding all of these elements
would be expensive, and could be unaffordable under New Zealand’s already
stretched healthcare
budget.
7. There is a consideration of social
and ethical issues. Genetic screening raises numerous ethical and social
issues,
some of which were mentioned above, especially where screening of
newborns or children is proposed.
8. There is a consideration of
cost-benefit issues. The cost of a screening programme must be justified
by the benefits
it is expected to bring. A proposed screening programme must be
compared with other possible interventions to ensure that it represents
the best
use of resources.59 For rare genetic diseases, testing the extended
families of affected individuals is likely to be more cost-effective than
population
screening.60 Strategies aimed at reducing risk for the
whole population may turn out to be more cost-effective than genetic screening
for multifactorial
diseases like diabetes, heart disease and
cancer.61
The deficiencies in our current knowledge about the
effects of genetic screening make it difficult to assess whether genetic
screening
would meet New Zealand’s current screening programme assessment
criteria. The criteria do not seem to rule out genetic screening
for a disease
that is serious, not rare, reasonably well understood, where some form of
treatment or intervention is available,
and pilot programmes show that screening
would be affordable and effective in reducing mortality or
morbidity.
The existing NHC criteria would not necessarily have to
be used to assess proposed genetic screening programmes. The
existing
criteria appear to apply to genetic screening as well as they do to
disease screening, but refinements and
additional criteria might be
necessary for genetic screening. For example, it should be made explicit that
for
58 National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in New Zealand, supra n. 5, p. 30.
59 Ibid., p. 27.
60 Shickle, supra n. 14, p. 24.
61 Patricia Baird, ‘Opportunity and Danger: Medical, Ethical and Social Implications of Early DNA Screening for Identification of Genetic Risk of Common Adult-Onset Disorders’ in Bartha Knoppers and Claude Laberge (eds), Genetic Screening: From Newborns to DNA Typing (1990), p. 320.
58 National Health Committee, Screening to Improve Health in
New Zealand, supra n. 5, p. 30.
59 Ibid., p. 27.
60
Shickle, supra n. 14, p. 24.
61 Patricia Baird,
‘Opportunity and Danger: Medical, Ethical and Social Implications of Early
DNA Screening for Identification
of Genetic Risk of Common Adult-Onset
Disorders’ in Bartha Knoppers and Claude Laberge (eds), Genetic
Screening: From Newborns to DNA Typing (1990), p. 320.
the health system to be capable of supporting all necessary elements of the
screening pathway, adequate genetic counselling resources
must be available, and
a process should be in place for dealing with secondary, unexpected findings
such as nonpaternity.62
E: New Zealand regulation relevant to Genetic Screening
If a genetic screening programme or programmes were found to be acceptable for New Zealand, some form of regulation would need to be put in place to ensure that the potential benefits of genetic screening were maximised and the risks minimised. New Zealand has no generic regulatory framework for population screening that could cover genetic screening. Existing New Zealand law that is relevant to genetic screening includes the Code of Health and Disability Services Consumers’ Rights 1996 and the Health Information Privacy Code
1994. The Code of Health and Disability Services Consumers’ Rights makes it essential for informed consent to be obtained before a health service is provided in New Zealand, and sets out some specific information that a participant would be entitled to receive.63 The Code would not require written consent to participate in genetic screening.64
The Health Information Privacy Code restricts the disclosure of health information and requires an agency holding health information to take reasonable precautions to protect that information.65 Disclosure of health information generally requires the authorisation of the individual, but there are exceptions. Rule 11 (2) (d) allows disclosure of health information without the authorisation of the individual where
‘disclosure is necessary to prevent or lessen a serious and imminent threat to... another individual.’ It is possible that this exception might be used by health agencies to try to justify disclosing genetic risk information to an individual’s family members. However, it is unlikely that the ‘serious and imminent threat’ test would be met by genetic information, because an individual’s genetic information is rarely informative of what a relative’s precise disease risk is. Under the Privacy Act 1993, the privacy rules in the Health Information Privacy
the health system to be capable of supporting all necessary elements of the
screening pathway, adequate genetic counselling resources
must be available, and
a process should be in place for dealing with secondary, unexpected findings
such as nonpaternity.62
E: New Zealand regulation relevant to Genetic Screening
If a
genetic screening programme or programmes were found to be acceptable for
New Zealand, some form of regulation would need
to be put in place to ensure
that the potential benefits of genetic screening were maximised and the risks
minimised. New Zealand
has no generic regulatory framework for population
screening that could cover genetic screening. Existing New Zealand law
that is relevant to genetic screening includes the Code of Health
and Disability Services Consumers’ Rights
1996 and the Health
Information Privacy Code
1994. The Code of Health and Disability Services
Consumers’ Rights makes it essential for informed consent to be obtained
before a health service is provided in New Zealand, and sets out some
specific information that a participant would be
entitled to receive.63
The Code would not require written consent to participate in genetic
screening.64
The Health Information Privacy Code restricts the
disclosure of health information and requires an agency holding health
information
to take reasonable precautions to protect that
information.65 Disclosure of health information generally
requires the authorisation of the individual, but there are
exceptions.
Rule 11 (2) (d) allows disclosure of health information without
the authorisation of the individual where
‘disclosure is necessary
to prevent or lessen a serious and imminent threat to... another
individual.’ It is possible
that this exception might be used by health
agencies to try to justify disclosing genetic risk information to an
individual’s
family members. However, it is unlikely that the
‘serious and imminent threat’ test would be met by genetic
information,
because an individual’s genetic information is rarely
informative of what a relative’s precise disease risk is.
Under
the Privacy Act 1993, the privacy rules in the Health Information
Privacy
62 See Deborah Baird et al, Whose Genes Are They Anyway? (Report from the HRC Conference on Human Genetic Information, Wellington, July 1995), p. 6.
63 The Health and Disability Commissioner Code of Health and Disability Services
Consumers' Rights Regulations 1996 , Right 7(1), Right 6.
64 Code of Health and Disability Services Consumers’ Rights, Right 7(6).
65 Health Information Privacy Code 1994, Rule 11 and Rule 5.
62 See Deborah Baird et al, Whose Genes Are They
Anyway? (Report from the HRC Conference on Human Genetic Information,
Wellington, July 1995), p. 6.
63 The Health and Disability
Commissioner Code of Health and Disability Services
Consumers' Rights
Regulations 1996 , Right 7(1), Right 6.
64 Code of Health
and Disability Services Consumers’ Rights, Right 7(6).
65 Health
Information Privacy Code 1994, Rule 11 and Rule 5.
Code do not create legally enforceable privacy rights.66 Thus, if
an individual’s privacy is breached, their only available legal redress
is to make a complaint to the Privacy Commissioner.67
New Zealand’s cervical screening programme has been regulated by the
Health Act 1956 since March 2005. New Zealand’s newborn metabolic
screening and breast screening programmes are not covered by any
specific legislation, but are controlled by the National Screening Unit
(NSU). The NSU has put in place quality standards for
the breast and cervical
cancer screening programmes, which are intended to apply to future screening
programmes.68 The quality standards are aimed at ensuring
equity of access to screening services, safety, efficiency and
effectiveness
of screening programmes.69 Quality assurance
activities include developing nationally consistent policy and quality
standards and auditing providers
against the standards.70
Quality and policy standards for the newborn metabolic
screening programme are currently being developed.71
A new Public Health Bill is expected to be introduced to Parliament in
2006 to replace the Health Act 1956.72 The creation of a generic regulatory framework for population screening is proposed.73 The Bill has not yet been drafted, but, according to a Ministry of Health Representative, the provision for population screening is likely to be similar to the provision made for the National Cervical Screening Programme (NCSP) in Part 4A of the Health Act 1956.74 The Act
Code do not create legally enforceable privacy rights.66 Thus, if
an individual’s privacy is breached, their only available legal redress
is to make a complaint to the Privacy Commissioner.67
New
Zealand’s cervical screening programme has been regulated by the Health
Act 1956 since March 2005. New Zealand’s newborn metabolic screening and
breast screening programmes are not covered by any
specific legislation,
but are controlled by the National Screening Unit (NSU). The NSU has put in
place quality standards for
the breast and cervical cancer screening programmes,
which are intended to apply to future screening programmes.68
The quality standards are aimed at ensuring equity of access to
screening services, safety, efficiency and effectiveness
of screening
programmes.69 Quality assurance activities include developing
nationally consistent policy and quality standards and auditing providers
against the standards.70 Quality and policy standards for
the newborn metabolic screening programme are currently being
developed.71
A new Public Health Bill is expected to be
introduced to Parliament in
2006 to replace the Health Act 1956.72
The creation of a generic regulatory framework for population
screening is proposed.73 The Bill has not yet been drafted, but,
according to a Ministry of Health Representative, the provision for population
screening
is likely to be similar to the provision made for the National
Cervical Screening Programme (NCSP) in Part 4A of the Health Act
1956.74 The Act
66 Privacy Act 1993, section 11. The Health Information Privacy Code was made under section 46 of the Privacy Act.
67 Privacy Act 1993, section 67.
68 National Screening Unit, Improving Quality: A Framework for Screening Programmes in New
Zealand (2005), p. iii.
69 Ibid., p. 10.
70 Ibid., p. 12.
71 Ministry of Health, Newborn Metabolic Screening Programme http://www.moh.govt.nz/moh.nsf/wpg_index/About+Newborn+Metabolic+Screening
+Programme at 18 May 2006.
72 Ministry of Health, Health Act Review and the Proposed Public Health Bill
http://www.moh.govt.nz/moh.nsf/wpg_Index/News+and+Issues- Health+Act+review+and+the+proposed+Public+Health+Bill at 28 August 2006
73 Louise Delany, 'Screening and Legislation' (Paper presented at Screening Symposium
2005, Wellington, 3-4 October 2005).
74 Email from Andrew Forsyth, Ministry of Health, to Emily Harris, 19 May 2006. Forsyth suggested that it will be at least six months before the Bill is introduced.
66 Privacy Act 1993, section 11. The Health Information Privacy
Code was made under section 46 of the Privacy Act.
67 Privacy Act 1993,
section 67.
68 National Screening Unit, Improving
Quality: A Framework for Screening Programmes in New
Zealand
(2005), p. iii.
69 Ibid., p. 10.
70 Ibid., p.
12.
71 Ministry of Health, Newborn Metabolic Screening
Programme
http://www.moh.govt.nz/moh.nsf/wpg_index/About+Newborn+Metabolic+Screening
+Programme
at 18 May 2006.
72 Ministry of Health, Health Act Review and
the Proposed Public Health Bill
http://www.moh.govt.nz/moh.nsf/wpg_Index/News+and+Issues-
Health+Act+review+and+the+proposed+Public+Health+Bill at 28 August
2006
73 Louise Delany, 'Screening and Legislation' (Paper
presented at Screening Symposium
2005, Wellington, 3-4 October
2005).
74 Email from Andrew Forsyth, Ministry of Health,
to Emily Harris, 19 May 2006. Forsyth suggested that it will be at least six
months
before the Bill is introduced.
states the objectives of the NCSP, which include ‘reducing
the incidence and mortality rate of cervical cancer’,
informing
women about the risks and potential benefits of participation, and improving
the quality of the programme by providing
for evaluation.75 The
Act sets out the duties of the NCSP management, which include providing
information to participants76 and the public.77
Disclosure of information that identifies a participant requires the
consent of the participant, unless one of the listed exceptions
applies. The
exceptions mostly relate to disclosure to other health professionals to allow
them to provide health services to participants,
but access to information for
cancer research and statistical purposes is also provided
for.78
If the Public Health Bill were to include a generic regulatory framework for
population screening that were based on the Health Act regulation of cervical
screening, it would be insufficient to regulate genetic screening. The
quality assurance and
information provision requirements, and the
restrictions placed on the disclosure of information, apply equally
well to genetic screening. However, as discussed above, additional
issues such as genetic discrimination, genetic
counselling, and
complexities associated with the familial nature of genetic information arise in
the context of genetic screening.
Some guidance on how to provide for
these and other additional issues associated with genetic screening can be
obtained
from examining the regulation of genetic testing and screening in other
jurisdictions.
F: International Regulation of Genetic Screening and Testing
Whilst many countries regulate population disease screening, and a number of countries are beginning to regulate the use of genetic tests, legislation aimed specifically at genetic screening is rare.
states the objectives of the NCSP, which include ‘reducing
the incidence and mortality rate of cervical cancer’,
informing
women about the risks and potential benefits of participation, and improving
the quality of the programme by providing
for evaluation.75 The
Act sets out the duties of the NCSP management, which include providing
information to participants76 and the public.77
Disclosure of information that identifies a participant requires the
consent of the participant, unless one of the listed exceptions
applies. The
exceptions mostly relate to disclosure to other health professionals to allow
them to provide health services to participants,
but access to information for
cancer research and statistical purposes is also provided
for.78
If the Public Health Bill were to include a generic
regulatory framework for population screening that were based on the Health Act
regulation of cervical screening, it would be insufficient to regulate
genetic screening. The quality assurance and
information provision
requirements, and the restrictions placed on the disclosure of
information, apply equally
well to genetic screening. However, as
discussed above, additional issues such as genetic discrimination,
genetic
counselling, and complexities associated with the familial nature of
genetic information arise in the context of genetic screening.
Some guidance on
how to provide for these and other additional issues associated with
genetic screening can be obtained
from examining the regulation of genetic
testing and screening in other jurisdictions.
F: International Regulation of Genetic Screening and
Testing
Whilst many countries regulate population disease
screening, and a number of countries are beginning to regulate the use of
genetic tests, legislation aimed specifically at genetic screening is
rare.
75 Health Act 1956, sections 112D (a), (b), (d).
76 Health Act 1956, section 112F.
77 Health Act 1956, section 112S.
78 Health Act 1956, section 112J.
75 Health Act 1956, sections 112D (a), (b), (d).
76
Health Act 1956, section 112F.
77 Health Act 1956, section
112S.
78 Health Act 1956, section 112J.
1. The common law jurisdictions
Like New Zealand, Australia,79 the United Kingdom,80
the United States81 and Canada82 have bodies that
regulate population screening and/or bodies to advise the government on the use
of human genetic technology, but
no specific legislative regulation of
population genetic screening.
In 2002, an Australian Law Reform Commission, Australian Health
Ethics Committee and National Health & Medical Research
Council
report recommended that nationally consistent policies and practices were
needed for obtaining informed consent,
genetic counselling, and approval of
screening tests for genetic screening,83 but, as yet, no
regulation has been put in place.
In the United States, a Bill has been introduced that would protect against the discriminatory use of genetic information by insurers and employers.84
1. The common law jurisdictions
Like New Zealand,
Australia,79 the United Kingdom,80 the United
States81 and Canada82 have bodies that regulate population
screening and/or bodies to advise the government on the use of human genetic
technology, but
no specific legislative regulation of population genetic
screening.
In 2002, an Australian Law Reform Commission,
Australian Health Ethics Committee and National Health & Medical
Research
Council report recommended that nationally consistent policies
and practices were needed for obtaining informed consent,
genetic counselling,
and approval of screening tests for genetic screening,83 but,
as yet, no regulation has been put in place.
In the United States,
a Bill has been introduced that would protect against the discriminatory
use of genetic information
by insurers and
employers.84
79 The Human Genetics Advisory Committee advises the Australian government on technical, social, ethical and legal implications of human genetic technology (see Human Genetics Advisory Committee. http://www.nhmrc.gov.au/about/committees/hgac/index.htm)
80 The Human Genetics Commission is an independent multi-disciplinary group that
advises the government on ethical, legal, social and economic issues related to human genetics. The National Screening Committee oversees population screening programmes in a similar way to New Zealand’s National Screening Unit. (see Human Genetics Commission, Profiling the Newborn: A Prospective Gene Technology (2005)).
81 The National Bioethics Advisory Commission, the Secretary’s Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing and the Ethical, Legal and Social Implications Committee of the Human Genome Project all provide advice to the government on aspects of human genetic technology (see OECD, Regulatory Developments in Genetic Testing in the United States http://www.oecd.org/document/47/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2674095_1_1_1_1,00.htm l). Independent professional bodies such as the American Society for Human Genetics and the American College of Medical Genetics produce guidelines and policy statements for the use of genetic testing and screening in clinical practice (see ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9).
82 The Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee provides independent advice to the
government on all aspects of biotechnology (see Canadian Biotechnology Advisory
Committee – Home http://cbac-cccb.ca/epic/internet/incbac-cccb.nsf/en/Home).
83 Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra n. 3, ch. 24.
84 Genetic Information Non-Discrimination Act 2005, section 306 .
79 The Human Genetics Advisory Committee advises the
Australian government on technical, social, ethical and legal implications of
human
genetic technology (see Human Genetics Advisory Committee.
http://www.nhmrc.gov.au/about/committees/hgac/index.htm)
80 The
Human Genetics Commission is an independent multi-disciplinary group
that
advises the government on ethical, legal, social and economic
issues related to human genetics. The National Screening Committee oversees
population screening programmes in a similar way to New Zealand’s
National Screening Unit. (see Human Genetics Commission,
Profiling the
Newborn: A Prospective Gene Technology (2005)).
81 The
National Bioethics Advisory Commission, the Secretary’s Advisory Committee
on Genetic Testing and the Ethical, Legal and
Social Implications Committee of
the Human Genome Project all provide advice to the government on aspects of
human genetic technology
(see OECD, Regulatory Developments in Genetic
Testing in the United States http://www.oecd.org/document/47/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2674095_1_1_1_1,00.htm
l). Independent professional bodies such as the American Society for Human
Genetics and
the American College of Medical Genetics produce guidelines and
policy statements for the use of genetic testing and screening in
clinical
practice (see ASHG and ACMG, supra n. 9).
82 The Canadian Biotechnology
Advisory Committee provides independent advice to the
government on
all aspects of biotechnology (see Canadian Biotechnology
Advisory
Committee – Home http://cbac-cccb.ca/epic/internet/incbac-cccb.nsf/en/Home).
83
Australian Law Reform Commission, Essentially Yours, supra n. 3,
ch. 24.
84 Genetic Information Non-Discrimination Act 2005, section 306
.
The Canadian College of Medical Geneticists and Canadian Paediatric Society
have produced policy statements and professional guidelines
for the provision of
genetic services.85 Both organisations recommend that children
should generally not be tested for adult-onset genetic conditions,
and
that they should only be tested where some medical intervention is
available.86
2. Other jurisdictions
Some other jurisdictions have made more specific provision for genetic
screening and testing than the common law jurisdictions.
Sweden has a specific law regulating genetic screening. Act (SFS 1991:
114) concerning the use of gene technology in medical screening requires that permission be obtained from the National Board of Health and Welfare to carry out a genetic screening programme.87
Participation in a genetic screening programme must be voluntary, and
written consent must be obtained.88 Important factors in
deciding whether a screening programme is approved are whether
the programme has a medically
justifiable aim and whether confidentiality of
genetic information will be protected.89
Austria enacted a Gene Technology Law in 1994, which allows genetic tests to be carried out for medical and research purposes.90 Informed consent is a prerequisite of participation.91 Testing of a minor requires the authorisation of their guardian,92 but there is no explicit restriction on what a minor can be tested for.93 Pre- and post-test counselling is
The Canadian College of Medical Geneticists and Canadian Paediatric Society
have produced policy statements and professional guidelines
for the provision of
genetic services.85 Both organisations recommend that children
should generally not be tested for adult-onset genetic conditions,
and
that they should only be tested where some medical intervention is
available.86
2. Other jurisdictions
Some other jurisdictions have made more specific provision for genetic
screening and testing than the common law jurisdictions.
Sweden has a
specific law regulating genetic screening. Act (SFS 1991:
114) concerning
the use of gene technology in medical screening requires that
permission be obtained from the National
Board of Health and Welfare
to carry out a genetic screening
programme.87
Participation in a genetic screening programme
must be voluntary, and
written consent must be obtained.88
Important factors in deciding whether a screening programme is
approved are whether the programme has a medically
justifiable aim and
whether confidentiality of genetic information will be
protected.89
Austria enacted a Gene Technology Law in 1994,
which allows genetic tests to be carried out for medical and research
purposes.90 Informed consent is a prerequisite of
participation.91 Testing of a minor requires the authorisation of
their guardian,92 but there is no explicit restriction on what a
minor can be tested for.93 Pre- and post-test counselling
is
85 See, eg, Canadian College of Medical Geneticists, http://ccmg.medical.org/policy.html at 20 January 2006; Laura Arbour (for the Canadian Paediatric Society), supra n. 42.
86 Ibid.
87 OECD, Regulatory Developments in Genetic Testing in Sweden http://www.oecd.org/document/13/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2430925_1_1_1_1,00.htm l at 20 January 2006.
88 Ibid.
89 Ibid.
90 'Austria's Gene Technology Law' (1995) 46 International Digest of Health Legislation 42.
91 The Gene Technology Law, secton 65(2).
92 Ibid., section 65(4).
93 Marie Hirtle, 'Children and Genetics: A Comparative Study of International Policy
Positions' (1998) 6 Health Law Journal 43, p. 56.
85 See, eg, Canadian College of Medical Geneticists, http://ccmg.medical.org/policy.html
at 20 January 2006; Laura Arbour (for the Canadian Paediatric Society), supra n.
42.
86 Ibid.
87 OECD, Regulatory Developments
in Genetic Testing in Sweden http://www.oecd.org/document/13/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2430925_1_1_1_1,00.htm
l at 20 January 2006.
88 Ibid.
89 Ibid.
90
'Austria's Gene Technology Law' (1995) 46 International Digest of Health
Legislation 42.
91 The Gene Technology Law, secton
65(2).
92 Ibid., section 65(4).
93 Marie Hirtle,
'Children and Genetics: A Comparative Study of International
Policy
Positions' (1998) 6 Health Law Journal 43, p.
56.
required for predisposition testing.94 The disclosure
of results is prohibited, and there is an express obligation
to ensure the confidentiality
of data collected.95 The law
incorporates a mandatory licensing scheme for laboratories undertaking genetic
testing.96
France’s Law No. 94-653 of 29 July 1994 on respect for the human
body states that ‘genetic studies of an individual’s
characteristics can only be carried out for medical purposes or scientific
research’ and that consent must first be obtained.97
Genetic testing in Israel is regulated by the Genetic Information Law.98
Under the Law, testing laboratories must be licensed.99
Informed consent is a prerequisite to testing.100
The Law protects the confidentiality of genetic information101
and prohibits genetic discrimination.102 Children under 16
years of age can only be tested for diagnostic purposes and to ascertain carrier
status, and parental consent is
required.103
In 1998, the Italian Government adopted National Guidelines for Genetic Testing.104 The requirements include test safety, quality assurance of laboratories, and the informed consent of test participants based on genetic counselling.105
required for predisposition testing.94 The disclosure
of results is prohibited, and there is an express obligation
to ensure the confidentiality
of data collected.95 The law
incorporates a mandatory licensing scheme for laboratories undertaking genetic
testing.96
France’s Law No. 94-653 of 29 July 1994 on
respect for the human body states that ‘genetic studies of an
individual’s
characteristics can only be carried out for medical
purposes or scientific research’ and that consent must first be
obtained.97
Genetic testing in Israel is regulated by the
Genetic Information Law.98
Under the Law, testing laboratories
must be licensed.99 Informed consent is a prerequisite
to testing.100 The Law protects the confidentiality of
genetic information101 and prohibits genetic discrimination.102
Children under 16 years of age can only be tested for diagnostic purposes
and to ascertain carrier status, and parental consent is
required.103
In 1998, the Italian Government adopted
National Guidelines for Genetic Testing.104 The requirements
include test safety, quality assurance of laboratories, and the informed
consent of test participants based
on genetic
counselling.105
94 The Gene Technology Law, section 69.
95 The Gene Technology Law, sections 67, 70, 71.
96 Ibid., section 68.
97 OECD, Regulatory Developments in Genetic Testing in France http://www.oecd.org/document/16/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2405136_1_1_1_1,00.htm l at 20 January 2006.
98 Genetic Information Law 5761-2000,
http://www.jewishvirtuallibrary.org/jsource/Health/GeneticInformationLaw.pdf> at 30
May 2006.
99 Genetic Information Law, section 4.
100 Ibid., section 11.
101 Ibid., section 18.
102 Ibid., sections 29, 30.
103 Ibid., section 24.
104 Beatrice Godard et al, 'Genetic Screening Programmes: Principles,Techniques,
Practices and Policies' (2003) 11 European Journal of Human Genetics, S49, S79.
94 The Gene Technology Law, section 69.
95 The
Gene Technology Law, sections 67, 70, 71.
96 Ibid., section
68.
97 OECD, Regulatory Developments in Genetic Testing
in France http://www.oecd.org/document/16/0,2340,en_2649_201185_2405136_1_1_1_1,00.htm
l at 20 January 2006.
98 Genetic Information Law 5761-2000,
http://www.jewishvirtuallibrary.org/jsource/Health/GeneticInformationLaw.pdf>
at 30
May 2006.
99 Genetic Information Law, section
4.
100 Ibid., section 11.
101 Ibid., section
18.
102 Ibid., sections 29, 30.
103 Ibid., section
24.
104 Beatrice Godard et al, 'Genetic Screening Programmes:
Principles,Techniques,
Practices and Policies' (2003) 11 European
Journal of Human Genetics, S49, S79.
The Netherlands’ Population Screening Act 1996 encompasses genetic
screening.106 Central government approval is required before
screening programmes can be implemented.107 For approval to be
granted, the potential benefits of the programme must outweigh the
risks.108 It is unlikely that screening for serious,
untreatable diseases would be acceptable under the
law.109
Norway’s Law No. 56 of 5 August 1994 on the medical use of biotechnology specifies that ‘genetic tests may only be carried out for medical purposes with diagnostic and/or therapeutic objectives.’110
Tests must be approved for use by the Ministry of Health.111
Testing requires written consent, and parent/guardian consent
must be obtained to test children under 16 years of age.112
Children under 16 years of age can only undergo pre-symptomatic
or pre-disposition testing if a beneficial treatment
or preventive
intervention is available.113 Comprehensive counselling is
mandatory.114 The law places a prohibition on the use of genetic
information by third parties.115
In Switzerland, the Federal Law on the Genetic Testing of Humans was approved by the Swiss parliament in October 2004. The Law allows genetic investigations only for medical purposes.116 Testing labs need government approval.117 Genetic counselling is required before and after pre-symptomatic testing, and the Law specifies a list of things that
The Netherlands’ Population Screening Act 1996 encompasses genetic
screening.106 Central government approval is required before
screening programmes can be implemented.107 For approval to be
granted, the potential benefits of the programme must outweigh the
risks.108 It is unlikely that screening for serious,
untreatable diseases would be acceptable under the
law.109
Norway’s Law No. 56 of 5 August 1994 on the
medical use of biotechnology specifies that ‘genetic tests may only be
carried
out for medical purposes with diagnostic and/or therapeutic
objectives.’110
Tests must be approved for use by the
Ministry of Health.111 Testing requires written consent, and
parent/guardian consent must be obtained to test children under 16 years
of age.112 Children under 16 years of age can only undergo
pre-symptomatic or pre-disposition testing if a beneficial treatment
or preventive intervention is available.113 Comprehensive
counselling is mandatory.114 The law places a prohibition on the use
of genetic information by third parties.115
In Switzerland,
the Federal Law on the Genetic Testing of Humans was approved by the Swiss
parliament in October 2004. The Law
allows genetic investigations only for
medical purposes.116 Testing labs need government
approval.117 Genetic counselling is required before and after
pre-symptomatic testing, and the Law specifies a list of things
that
106 Rogeer Hoedemaekers, ‘Genetic Screening in the Netherlands’ in Ruth Chadwick et al
(eds), The Ethics of Genetic Screening, pp. 105, 117.
107 Ibid.
108 Ibid.
109 Ibid.
110 'Norway Law No. 56 of 5 August 1994 on the Medical Use of Biotechnology' (1995)
46 International Digest of Health Legislation 51, p. 53.
111 Ibid.
112 Ibid.
113 Ibid.
114 Ibid.
115 Ibid.
116 Federal Office of Justice, Genetic Testing of Humans. http://www.ejpd.admin.ch/ejpd/en/home/themen/gesellschaft/ref_gesetzgebung/ref_ genetische_untersuchungen.html at 29 August 2006.
106 Rogeer Hoedemaekers, ‘Genetic Screening in the
Netherlands’ in Ruth Chadwick et al
(eds), The Ethics of
Genetic Screening, pp. 105, 117.
107 Ibid.
108
Ibid.
109 Ibid.
110 'Norway Law No. 56 of 5
August 1994 on the Medical Use of Biotechnology' (1995)
46
International Digest of Health Legislation 51, p. 53.
111
Ibid.
112 Ibid.
113 Ibid.
114
Ibid.
115 Ibid.
116 Federal Office of
Justice, Genetic Testing of Humans.
http://www.ejpd.admin.ch/ejpd/en/home/themen/gesellschaft/ref_gesetzgebung/ref_
genetische_untersuchungen.html at 29 August 2006.
must be covered in genetic counselling.118 The Law makes explicit
the right to make an informed decision.119 The Law provides
protection from genetic discrimination by prohibiting employers from
requesting genetic tests or using the results
of previous genetic tests except
where the job is associated with a risk of occupational illness.120
Insurers are prohibited from requesting genetic tests, and from using
genetic test results in deciding whether to provide life
or disability cover
where the level of cover sought is below a threshold.121
3. Guidance from international bodies
The World Health Organization produced ‘Proposed Ethical
Guidelines for Genetic Screening and Testing’
in
2003.122 The guidelines state that participation in screening must
be voluntary,123 participants must be informed before
participating, and given genetic counselling.124 Treatment or
preventive measures that are likely to benefit participants’ health
must be available to justify
population screening programmes.125
Test results should not be disclosed to third parties without the
individual’s consent.126 The WHO advises deferring genetic
testing of children until adulthood where possible.127
UNESCO’s Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights sets out some general principles that should ‘guide States in the formulation of their legislation, policies or other instruments in the field of bioethics.’128 Of particular relevance to genetic screening is the general
must be covered in genetic counselling.118 The Law makes explicit
the right to make an informed decision.119 The Law provides
protection from genetic discrimination by prohibiting employers from
requesting genetic tests or using the results
of previous genetic tests except
where the job is associated with a risk of occupational illness.120
Insurers are prohibited from requesting genetic tests, and from using
genetic test results in deciding whether to provide life
or disability cover
where the level of cover sought is below a threshold.121
3. Guidance from international bodies
The World Health
Organization produced ‘Proposed Ethical Guidelines for Genetic
Screening and Testing’
in 2003.122 The guidelines
state that participation in screening must be voluntary,123
participants must be informed before participating, and given genetic
counselling.124 Treatment or preventive measures that are
likely to benefit participants’ health must be available to
justify
population screening programmes.125 Test results should not
be disclosed to third parties without the individual’s consent.126
The WHO advises deferring genetic testing of children until adulthood
where possible.127
UNESCO’s Universal Declaration on
Bioethics and Human Rights sets out some general principles that should
‘guide States
in the formulation of their legislation, policies or
other instruments in the field of bioethics.’128 Of
particular relevance to genetic screening is the general
118 EuroGentest – National Regulation of Genetic Counselling (2005)
http://www.eurogentest.org/web/info/public/unit3/regulations.xhtml at 29 August
2006.
119 Munich Re – Switzerland Passes Law on Genetic Testing (2004) http://www.munichre.com/pages/03/biosciences/gentec_news/2004/2004_02_gentec_ news_0007_en.aspx at 29 August 2006.
120 Federal Office of Justice, supra n. 116.
121 Ibid.
122 See Wertz et al, Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, p. 42.
123 Except for newborn screening where early diagnosis and treatment will benefit the newborn, ibid.
124 Ibid.
125 Ibid., p. 39. Also at p. 46: “It is unethical to screen for disorders that cannot be treated
or prevented.”
126 Ibid., p. 42.
127 Ibid., pp. 59-60.
128 UNESCO, Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights (2005) art. 2.
118 EuroGentest – National
Regulation of Genetic Counselling (2005)
http://www.eurogentest.org/web/info/public/unit3/regulations.xhtml
at 29 August
2006.
119 Munich Re –
Switzerland Passes Law on Genetic Testing (2004)
http://www.munichre.com/pages/03/biosciences/gentec_news/2004/2004_02_gentec_
news_0007_en.aspx at 29 August 2006.
120 Federal Office of Justice,
supra n. 116.
121 Ibid.
122 See Wertz et al,
Review of Ethical Issues in Medical Genetics, supra n. 6, p.
42.
123 Except for newborn screening where early diagnosis
and treatment will benefit the newborn, ibid.
124
Ibid.
125 Ibid., p. 39. Also at p. 46: “It is unethical to
screen for disorders that cannot be treated
or
prevented.”
126 Ibid., p. 42.
127 Ibid., pp.
59-60.
128 UNESCO, Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human
Rights (2005) art. 2.
requirement for informed consent,129 the recommendations for
protection of the confidentiality of personal information,130
and the recommendations for protection against discrimination and
stigmatisation.131
The World Medical Association Statement on Genetics and Medicine
recommends that informed consent should be required for
genetic testing,
the confidentiality of genetic information should be protected, and laws should
be enacted to protect people from
genetic discrimination.132
Predisposition testing should not be carried out on children unless it
will facilitate the earlier instigation of treatment.133
The Council of Europe’s Convention on Human Rights and
Biomedicine restricts the use of predictive genetic testing
to where it is for
health or scientific research purposes.134 Informed consent
is required for health interventions.135 Medical interventions on
children must be for their direct benefit, and may only be carried
out with parental consent.136 The Convention bans genetic
discrimination.137
The Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences created the Declaration of Inuyama on Human Genome Mapping, Genetic Screening and Gene Therapy in 1990. According to the Declaration, consent to participate must be truly voluntary, participants should be provided with counselling, and privacy and confidentiality of genetic information should be protected.138
requirement for informed consent,129 the recommendations for
protection of the confidentiality of personal information,130
and the recommendations for protection against discrimination and
stigmatisation.131
The World Medical Association Statement
on Genetics and Medicine recommends that informed consent should be
required for
genetic testing, the confidentiality of genetic information
should be protected, and laws should be enacted to protect people from
genetic
discrimination.132 Predisposition testing should not be carried
out on children unless it will facilitate the earlier instigation of
treatment.133
The Council of Europe’s Convention
on Human Rights and Biomedicine restricts the use of predictive genetic
testing
to where it is for health or scientific research purposes.134
Informed consent is required for health interventions.135
Medical interventions on children must be for their direct benefit,
and may only be carried out with parental consent.136 The
Convention bans genetic discrimination.137
The Council for
International Organizations of Medical Sciences created the Declaration
of Inuyama on Human Genome
Mapping, Genetic Screening and Gene Therapy in
1990. According to the Declaration, consent to participate must be truly
voluntary,
participants should be provided with counselling, and privacy and
confidentiality of genetic information should be
protected.138
129 Ibid., art. 6.
130 Ibid., art. 9.
131 Ibid., art. 11.
132 World Medical Association, Statement on Genetics and Medicine (2005).
133 Ibid.
134 Council of Europe, Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine (1997) art. 12.
135 Ibid., art. 5.
136 Ibid., art. 6(1).
137 Ibid., art. 11.
138 Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, The Declaration of Inuyama
(1990).
129 Ibid., art. 6.
130 Ibid., art. 9.
131
Ibid., art. 11.
132 World Medical Association, Statement
on Genetics and Medicine (2005).
133 Ibid.
134
Council of Europe, Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine
(1997) art. 12.
135 Ibid., art. 5.
136 Ibid.,
art. 6(1).
137 Ibid., art. 11.
138 Council for
International Organizations of Medical Sciences, The Declaration of
Inuyama
(1990).
4. Summary and analysis of international guidance in relation to
New Zealand’s existing regulation
An analysis of the regulation of genetic testing and screening in other
jurisdictions, and the recommendations made by international
bodies, reveals
several common features. Features that have been considered important enough
to be included in regulatory instruments
in multiple jurisdictions are likely
to also be relevant in the regulation of genetic screening in New Zealand.
Most of the
legislation examined above is directed at genetic testing, but
the general principles appear to apply equally well to population
genetic
screening.
Informed consent is universally required. Informed consent would undoubtedly
be a prerequisite of participation in genetic screening
in New Zealand
under the Code of Health and Disability Services Consumers’
Rights.139
The jurisdictions that have established comprehensive regulatory
regimes for genetic testing all require the
provision of
genetic counselling. In the context of genetic testing and screening,
‘informed consent’ and ‘genetic
counselling’ have some
overlap. The term ‘genetic counselling’ can be used to refer to the
provision of information
prior to participation to allow the individual to
make an informed decision (pre-test counselling), and also to the
communication
and explanation of results after the test (post-test
counselling). It may be desirable to prescribe the precise information
provision
requirements for informed consent and genetic counselling in
legislation or professional guidelines, to ensure consistency and a
high
standard of counselling.
The regulation of genetic screening in other jurisdictions and by international bodies recognises the importance of the confidentiality of genetic information to participants by prohibiting or placing strong restrictions on the disclosure of genetic information. The prohibition or restriction of disclosure of genetic test results would serve to prevent genetic discrimination. In New Zealand, the Health Information Privacy Code provides some protection for health information, but
4. Summary and analysis of international guidance in relation to
New Zealand’s existing regulation
An analysis of the regulation of genetic testing and screening in other
jurisdictions, and the recommendations made by international
bodies, reveals
several common features. Features that have been considered important enough
to be included in regulatory instruments
in multiple jurisdictions are likely
to also be relevant in the regulation of genetic screening in New Zealand.
Most of the
legislation examined above is directed at genetic testing, but
the general principles appear to apply equally well to population
genetic
screening.
Informed consent is universally required. Informed consent
would undoubtedly be a prerequisite of participation in genetic screening
in
New Zealand under the Code of Health and Disability Services
Consumers’ Rights.139
The jurisdictions that have
established comprehensive regulatory regimes for genetic testing all
require the
provision of genetic counselling. In the context of genetic
testing and screening, ‘informed consent’ and ‘genetic
counselling’ have some overlap. The term ‘genetic counselling’
can be used to refer to the provision of information
prior to participation to
allow the individual to make an informed decision (pre-test counselling), and
also to the communication
and explanation of results after the test (post-test
counselling). It may be desirable to prescribe the precise information
provision
requirements for informed consent and genetic counselling in
legislation or professional guidelines, to ensure consistency and a
high
standard of counselling.
The regulation of genetic screening in other
jurisdictions and by international bodies recognises the importance of the
confidentiality
of genetic information to participants by prohibiting or placing
strong restrictions on the disclosure of genetic information. The
prohibition or
restriction of disclosure of genetic test results would serve to prevent
genetic discrimination. In New Zealand,
the Health Information
Privacy Code provides some protection for health information,
but
139 The Health and Disability Commissioner Code of Health and Disability Services
Consumers' Rights Regulations 1996 , Right 7(1).
139 The Health and Disability Commissioner Code of Health and
Disability Services
Consumers' Rights Regulations 1996 , Right
7(1).
there is a risk, albeit small, that the exceptions allowing disclosure might
be abused, as discussed above
Some regulation restricts the purposes for which genetic screening or
testing can be carried out to medical and scientific
purposes. This
would prevent insurers and employers from requiring prospective policyholders
or employees to undergo genetic
screening. Such a restriction is
desirable as an extra layer of protection against genetic
discrimination.
Several jurisdictions explicitly restrict genetic screening or testing
to where treatment or preventive interventions are
available. Under the
National Health Committee Criteria to Assess Screening Programmes140
this would also be the position in New Zealand.
Most of the jurisdictions that have comprehensive regulatory regimes for
genetic testing require the licensing or accreditation
of laboratories that
carry out the testing. While there is no formal process of approval for genetic
tests before they are able
to be used in New Zealand,141 all
publicly funded clinical laboratories in New Zealand must be accredited by
International Accreditation New Zealand.142
Positions on the genetic testing and screening of minors vary.143 As discussed above, the predominant view of commentators is that children should not be tested or screened for genetic conditions unless something beneficial can be done. If nothing can be done, and the disease will not manifest until adulthood, there is a strong ethical argument that minors should be able to decide whether they want to participate in screening when they reach maturity, so that their future autonomy and rights are protected. More consideration of the position of minors is needed. It may be that regulation expressly restricting genetic screening of minors is unnecessary, because the criteria for assessing a proposed screening programme should only approve a
there is a risk, albeit small, that the exceptions allowing disclosure might
be abused, as discussed above
Some regulation restricts the purposes for
which genetic screening or testing can be carried out to medical and
scientific
purposes. This would prevent insurers and employers from requiring
prospective policyholders or employees to undergo genetic
screening.
Such a restriction is desirable as an extra layer of protection against
genetic discrimination.
Several jurisdictions explicitly restrict
genetic screening or testing to where treatment or preventive
interventions
are available. Under the National Health Committee Criteria
to Assess Screening Programmes140 this would also be the position
in New Zealand.
Most of the jurisdictions that have comprehensive
regulatory regimes for genetic testing require the licensing or accreditation
of laboratories that carry out the testing. While there is no formal process of
approval for genetic tests before they are able
to be used in New
Zealand,141 all publicly funded clinical laboratories in New Zealand
must be accredited by International Accreditation New
Zealand.142
Positions on the genetic testing and
screening of minors vary.143 As discussed above, the
predominant view of commentators is that children should not be tested or
screened for genetic
conditions unless something beneficial can be done. If
nothing can be done, and the disease will not manifest until
adulthood, there is a strong ethical argument that minors should be able
to decide whether they want to participate in screening
when they reach
maturity, so that their future autonomy and rights are protected. More
consideration of the position of minors
is needed. It may be that
regulation expressly restricting genetic screening of minors is unnecessary,
because the criteria
for assessing a proposed screening programme should
only approve a
140 See criterion 3 in the National Health Committee criteria, supra n. 5, p. 3.
141 Diana Sarfati, Some Practical Aspects of Genetic Testing in New Zealand: A Report for the
National Health Committee (2002), p. 8.
142 Ibid., p. 13.
143 See discussion supra under “The Risks Associated with Population Genetic
Screening”.
140 See criterion 3 in the National Health Committee criteria,
supra n. 5, p. 3.
141 Diana Sarfati, Some Practical Aspects of
Genetic Testing in New Zealand: A Report for the
National Health
Committee (2002), p. 8.
142 Ibid., p. 13.
143
See discussion supra under “The Risks Associated with
Population Genetic
Screening”.
genetic screening programme where the benefits clearly outweigh the
harms.
Conclusion: The Future Of Genetic Screening In New Zealand
Analysis of the regulation of genetic screening and testing in other
jurisdictions revealed a trend toward creating a broad regulatory
regime
containing generic requirements that could apply to many different
genetic tests or screening programmes. This approach
is preferable to
regulating each screening programme separately as New Zealand
currently does for our disease screening
programmes, because it would be more
efficient and would promote the development of forward- looking policies
that could
be applied and adapted to new technologies as they arose.144
Strong central regulation is preferable to weaker guidance with
room for self-regulation, as a lack of strong central regulation
for New
Zealand’s disease screening programmes in the past led to low quality
screening in some locations.145 The development of a generic
regulatory framework for genetic screening would have the added benefit
of providing the best
opportunities for public debate and participation.146
If particular screening programmes had specific requirements, these could
be dealt with by regulation additional to the main generic
framework.
Comparison of New Zealand’s regulation of disease screening and other law relevant to genetic screening, with regulation of genetic screening and testing in other jurisdictions, identifies several key elements that would need to be included in genetic screening regulation in New Zealand. Provision of genetic counselling for pre-symptomatic and pre-disposition screening would need to be made mandatory, and minimum requirements for counselling specified. Insurers and employers should be prohibited from requiring people to undergo pre- symptomatic and pre-dispositional screening. Whether insurers or employers should be able to utilise the results of genetic tests carried out for medical purposes requires further consideration.
genetic screening programme where the benefits clearly outweigh the
harms.
Conclusion: The Future Of Genetic Screening In New
Zealand
Analysis of the regulation of genetic screening and testing
in other jurisdictions revealed a trend toward creating a broad regulatory
regime containing generic requirements that could apply to many
different genetic tests or screening programmes. This approach
is preferable
to regulating each screening programme separately as New Zealand
currently does for our disease screening
programmes, because it would be more
efficient and would promote the development of forward- looking policies
that could
be applied and adapted to new technologies as they arose.144
Strong central regulation is preferable to weaker guidance with
room for self-regulation, as a lack of strong central regulation
for New
Zealand’s disease screening programmes in the past led to low quality
screening in some locations.145 The development of a generic
regulatory framework for genetic screening would have the added benefit
of providing the best
opportunities for public debate and participation.146
If particular screening programmes had specific requirements, these could
be dealt with by regulation additional to the main generic
framework.
Comparison of New Zealand’s regulation of disease
screening and other law relevant to genetic screening, with
regulation
of genetic screening and testing in other jurisdictions, identifies
several key elements that would need
to be included in genetic screening
regulation in New Zealand. Provision of genetic counselling for pre-symptomatic
and pre-disposition
screening would need to be made mandatory, and minimum
requirements for counselling specified. Insurers and employers should
be
prohibited from requiring people to undergo pre- symptomatic and
pre-dispositional screening. Whether insurers or employers should
be able to
utilise the results of genetic tests carried out for medical purposes requires
further consideration.
144 See: Andrews, 'Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy' supra n. 25, pp. 227-228.
145 See, e.g., National Screening Unit, Improving Quality, supra n. 68, p. 8.
146 Ibid.
144 See: Andrews, 'Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy' supra
n. 25, pp. 227-228.
145 See, e.g., National Screening Unit,
Improving Quality, supra n. 68, p. 8.
146
Ibid.
The existing NHC criteria for assessing proposed screening programmes
should be utilised for genetic screening
with the modifications
suggested above regarding genetic counselling and secondary findings.
These criteria should
provide sufficient protection to prevent screening of
children or adults for serious, untreatable diseases. However, it
may be
seen as desirable by the public to explicitly prohibit such screening.
Informed consent and confidentiality of
genetic information are
already covered to some extent by New Zealand’s Code of Health
and Disability Services
Consumers’ Rights and Health Information
Privacy Code respectively. To improve the existing protection, genetic
screening
regulation should specify that informed consent must be in writing.
There should be a provision to the effect that the Rule 11(2)(d)
exception in
the Health Information Privacy Code does not authorise disclosure of
information about an individual’s
genetic status to his or her family
members, and sanctions should be put in place for breaches of the Code.
Genetic screening holds the potential to improve the health of our nation. However, the risks associated with genetic screening are currently uncertain and the costs difficult to quantify. Now is the time to carry out further research into the effects of genetic screening to allow New Zealand to approach the regulation of genetic screening armed with full information. In this way, the introduction of genetic screening programmes in the future can be managed to provide maximal benefits with minimal risks for all New Zealanders, so that prevention really is better than cure.
The existing NHC criteria for assessing proposed screening programmes
should be utilised for genetic screening
with the modifications
suggested above regarding genetic counselling and secondary findings.
These criteria should
provide sufficient protection to prevent screening of
children or adults for serious, untreatable diseases. However, it
may be
seen as desirable by the public to explicitly prohibit such screening.
Informed consent and confidentiality of
genetic information are
already covered to some extent by New Zealand’s Code of Health
and Disability Services
Consumers’ Rights and Health Information
Privacy Code respectively. To improve the existing protection, genetic
screening
regulation should specify that informed consent must be in writing.
There should be a provision to the effect that the Rule 11(2)(d)
exception in
the Health Information Privacy Code does not authorise disclosure of
information about an individual’s
genetic status to his or her family
members, and sanctions should be put in place for breaches of the
Code.
Genetic screening holds the potential to improve the health
of our nation. However, the risks associated with
genetic
screening are currently uncertain and the costs difficult to quantify. Now is
the time to carry out further research
into the effects of genetic
screening to allow New Zealand to approach the regulation of genetic
screening armed with
full information. In this way, the introduction of
genetic screening programmes in the future can be managed to provide
maximal benefits with minimal risks for all New Zealanders, so that
prevention really is better than cure.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZLawStuJl/2006/9.html