Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Public Interest Law Journal of New Zealand |
Last Updated: 21 October 2014
Does the Gillick Competency Test Apply in New Zealand, Given the Special Nature of Sexual Health Care Services?
Chantelle Murley[*]
This paper considers whether the watershed House of Lords decision in Gillick v West Norfolk and Wisbech Area Health Authority, which allowed mature minors to consent to medical treatment, can be incorporated into New Zealand jurisprudence in order to allow minors to consent to sexual health services. The paper frames sexual health services as necessary heath services for anyone who is sexually active, and examines the changing position of children in society, as well as the relationship between children and parents before the law. New Zealand’s legislative framework for consent and minors is also investigated. Ultimately, this paper argues that s 36 of the Care of Children Act (which allows a child over 16 years to consent to medical treatment which is in their best interests) can be interpreted consistently with Gillick, in order to allow mature minors under this threshold to consent. The traditional status--based interpretation of s 36 is rejected in favor for a competency-based consent test.
I Introduction
The view that any medical procedure, no matter
how trivial, is unlawful, unless authorised by valid consent, is of pivotal
importance
to the principle of autonomy. This dates back to 1914, when Cardozo J
proclaimed: [1]
Every human being of adult years and with sound mind has the right to determine what shall be done with his own body; and a surgeon who performs an operation without his patient’s consent commits an assault, for which he is liable in damages.
Recently, children in Western society have also been accorded such
rights, albeit the consent may come from a proxy. Sexual intercourse,
pregnancy
and termination are fundamentally personal experiences, which, when engaged in
by a minor, are often challenged, rightly
or wrongly, in a manner that threatens
to undermine the child’s autonomy and
confidentiality.[2] However, if the
child is engaging in sexual activity, contraception becomes a
necessity.
Given New Zealand’s unique medico-legal environment, the
legal position for minors’ capacity receives fleeting judicial
comment, as
the issue is not directly presented to the courts. The law is therefore
fragmented and inconsistent, resulting in unnecessarily
conservative medical
decision making.[3] New
Zealand’s diverse population requires the law to accommodate cultural and
religious differences, while protecting the child.
Media commentary shows that
society is not at idem on the issue, especially in balancing tensions between
parental and child
rights.[4]
Sexual health
services pose many issues. While not falling squarely under emergency treatment,
where the doctrine of necessity allows
doctors to proceed without obtaining
consent by lawful justification, such services can be deemed necessary, given
the potential
adverse outcomes. A study shows a sizeable minority, around
10–30 percent, of New Zealand teenagers are having sexual intercourse
before 16 years of age, an emerging trend that young women are engaging in
sexual intercourse earlier than in previous
generations.[5] This emphasises the
importance of considering contraceptive access for all adolescents, not just
those over 16.
Contraception is defined as a substance, device or
technique intended to prevent conception or
implantation.[6] Contraception may
serve the adolescent’s best interests but is an often disputed behavioural
choice. Commentators and industry
groups argue confidential distribution will
reach the most adolescents, especially those most at
risk.[7] Evidence exists that some
doctors, given the legal uncertainty, take a conservative
approach.[8] However, other groups
advocate a more liberal approach allowing competent minors to
consent.[9] Significantly, health
practitioners have the right to conscientiously object to providing
contraception related services, but are
obligated to inform the patient that
these services are available
elsewhere.[10] In practice, however,
normative opinions could influence clinical
judgment.[11]
The law must
strive to reach a balance between protecting the vulnerable and allowing safe
development. This paper focuses on the
extent to which New Zealand law allows
minors less than 16 years of age to consent to sexual health services; what
happens to the
proxy consent; and whether the current practice is legally
reconcilable. The focus will be on female minors, who have the possibilities
of
prescribed contraceptives beyond condoms available to them, although the
reasoning could be extended more generally to males.
II Importance
of Consent
Autonomy requires that the free and informed decisions of
competent patients are respected, as self-determination is the principle
justification requiring informed
consent.[12] The modern obligation
to obtain informed consent stems from the Nuremberg Code 1947, and the Helsinki
Declaration 1964. While healthcare’s
main mechanism of recognising
autonomy is through the right to refuse
treatment,[13] this paper is
concerned with the competency required to give positive
consent.
Autonomous individuals must have the capacity to envisage and
comprehend short and long term consequences of actions so as to be able
to
choose between possible futures in light of their own needs, desires and values.
In a healthcare context, this requires comprehension
of the relevant health
related ideas, general decision-making capacities, the ability to weigh options
and preferences and to have
deliberately formed
values.[14] The law has
traditionally assumed that, by virtue of their immaturity, young people lack
capacity. Inability to consent can be perceived
as a barrier to service
accessibility, especially if the minor is opposed to parental involvement.
Traditionally, parents are considered
the most appropriate person to determine
what is in their incompetent child’s best interests, given their proximity
to, and
intimate knowledge of their child. However, this is increasingly
challenged with the growing independence of
children.[15] The Care of Children
Act 2004 (CoCA) uses a proxy framework where a guardian or court can consent on
a child’s
behalf.[16]
Autonomy granted
to competent patients peaked when Lord Donaldson MR claimed that medical
treatment refusal is legally effective even
if the patient will likely
die.[17] Informed consent is a
process rather than a single act and has three elements:
[18] voluntariness, information and
competence. Voluntariness is also explicitly required in the HDC Code of Health
and Disability Consumers’
Rights Regulations 1996 (The
Code).[19] Subtle external pressures
such as parental religious beliefs can overcome free will required to
consent.[20] Young girls, especially
if pregnant, are vulnerable to such
pressures.[21] Information concerns
the nature and quality of information communicated by the doctor to the patient.
Informed consent often blurs
with competency, which focuses on the quality of
the patient’s understanding of the proposed
treatment.[22] Competence forms the
greatest obstacle for young people and hence is the current
focus.
Consent is sought by the doctor to prevent liability. However,
given the Accident Compensation Corporation legislation bars civil
actions for
personal injury,[23] consent is
ill-defined in New Zealand.[24]
Given that keys can unlock, but also lock, Lord Donaldson MR uses an analogy of
a “flak jacket” protecting the doctor
from litigious
claims.[25] This flak jacket of
consent can arguably be provided either by the Gillick-competent child or
the guardian. Importantly, it can be revoked, but the doctor only needs single
consent to be protected, provided
he has this, the doctor can proceed legally.
Exemplary damages are preserved
[26] only in instances amounting to
“outrageous conduct”[27]
or flagrant disregard”[28] for
the patient’s rights. Criminal sanction is also remotely
possible.[29] However, such
prosecution is unlikely, as a doctor customarily performs professional
obligations in good faith, negating the requisite
mental
elements.[30] More pertinent is the
ability of aggrieved patients, concerned parties, or parents, to complain to the
Health and Disability Commissioner
(HDC). This can lead to professional
discipline if found to breach a right within The
Code.[31]
Research on New
Zealand doctors found that a functionally competent fourteen-year-old girl was
considered unable to consent to the
removal of a prominent mole on her face by
83.5 per cent of the sample, whose patients regularly included
adolescents.[32] The majority
responded that an aggrieved parent would be more likely to complain at the
mole’s removal than a competent minor
in regards to it not being removed,
therefore highlighting the risk-adverse approach medical professionals take. The
law requires
greater clarity to guide healthcare providers who are not legal
experts.[33] This view of a parent
being more likely to complain is not without merit. Complaining to the HDC, a
mother objected that her competent
son, at age 14, had consented to a tetanus
injection for which she would have refused
consent.[34]
III
Children, Society and Medicine
There is no universal definition of a
“child,” as childhood is contextually defined and influenced by
class, gender and
ethnicity.[35]
This fuels debate that age is insufficient to determine maturity. For the
purposes of this paper, the focus is on girls aged 12 to
16. This is because
CoCA allows for proxy consents of the guardian on the child’s behalf but
also allows a child over 16 to
grant consent, as if an
adult.[36] In contemporary liberal
society, parents have legal rights to raise their minor children according to
their values.[37] While European
cultures value independence, collectivist decision-making is embraced by Maori
and Pacific peoples.[38]
A
Children’s Position in Society
Historically, a legitimate
child was treated as the father’s property, as a mother had no independent
legal status.[39] This view was
considered a “historical curiosity” by Lord Fraser in Gillick v
West Norfolk and Wisbech Area Health Authority
(Gillick).[40] Parental
rights of control are no longer perceived as existing for the parents’
benefit, but conversely held to exist for the
child’s benefit and
justified only insofar as they enable performance of duties owed to the
child.[41] These parental duties
derive from multiple sources within the law and beyond, enshrined in religious
and ethical principles.[42] However,
these conferred “rights” are better termed responsibilities, being
not absolute, but limited by the child’s
needs.
[43] In terms of medical treatment,
they include making healthcare decisions based on the child’s best
interests, as generally the
parents are best positioned to understand those
interests. [44]
While this
right is to protect, not control, these are hard to differentiate between. The
child must be able to express their views
and have them
respected.[45] The United Nations
Convention of the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) provides for children to be heard
before major decisions are taken
involving their person, so their view aids
determination of their best
interests.[46] Incorporated into the
CoCA in s 6(2)(a) and (b) is the requirement that the child is to have a
reasonable opportunity to express
their views on matters affecting them and that
these views must be taken into account. The Ministry of Social Development
further
advocates for the child to take responsibility and participate in
decisions when and to the extent
capable.[47] Therefore, incompetent
children are still entitled to give or withhold
assent.[48] However, traditional
paternalism that views minors as vulnerable, regardless of their proven capacity
to understand, remains pervasive,
despite redefining ‘parental
rights’ as ‘parental responsibilities’ to prevent the
family’s rights
subsuming the
child’s.[49]
Provision
of contraceptive or abortion advice and treatment is fraught with tension
between the child’s autonomy interest, and
the interests of parents and
state.[50] Adolescence can be
tumultuous, commonly involving conflict with parents, and family relationships
can dilute the effect of self-determination.
Even in supportive family
relationships, some young people feel uncomfortable talking to their parents
about sexuality, creating
conflict as the young person seeks to assert autonomy.
This is particularly so for young people with cultural or religious backgrounds
that disapprove of premarital intercourse.
[51] Arguably, parents may not be in
the best position to assess their adolescent child’s best sexual health
interests.
B Determining Capacity
The extent of a
child’s right to choose, ultimately rests upon whether one adopts a
traditional status-based approach founded
on age, or a capacity-based approach
premised on individual capacity to understand, requiring individualised
contextual determination
of capacity.
[52] Capacity, as discussed above, sets a
minimum standard of decision-making skills, developed through maturity and
experience, required
to recognise a decision’s
validity.[53] Most children under 10
years lack the deliberative competence and maturity needed to make important
decisions. In contrast, adult
status automatically confers the presumption of
capacity to choose
treatment.[54]
Status-based
tests provide the certainty desired by the medical profession, being easy to
administer across the
population.[55] A status-based test
whereby after a fixed age one is presumed competent, or a presumption of
incompetence under a fixed age, is tempting
because of certainty but can prove
inflexible, arbitrary and
irrational.[56] Kennedy argues that
status-based tests are invalid, as merely belonging to a given class does not
entail incapacity unless that
class is defined by a lack of
capacity.[57] Statutes provide
deemed capacity for discrete tasks, recognising the maturation process: for
example, determining criminal
responsibility,[58] consenting to
sexual intercourse[59] and voting.
For these functions arbitrary ages are acceptable. Ascertaining competence for
electoral votes would otherwise be administratively
impossible.[60] This difficulty is
absent from medical decisions. Arbitrary ages, below which even mature minors
require parental consent to receive
sexual healthcare, both therapeutic and
preventative, are frequently dysfunctional, as they prejudice both the
girl’s health
and wellbeing and that of her partner. Further, this
approach is incompatible with the progression of society’s views,
recognising
children’s rights and increasing
independence.[61]
An
understanding-based model acknowledges that, while legally minors, some youths
have sufficient maturity to be accorded practical
autonomy.[62] This approach
encumbers the doctor with arbitrating competence while maintaining integrity.
This requires a mechanism to ensure doctors
actually pursue the enquiry with
maturity as the primary determinant.
[63] Using a presumption, despite
rejecting status-based approaches, only serves to readopt an age criterion in
forming the presumption.
However, no test will universally distinguish competent
minors from incompetent ones.[64]
Furthermore, as a legal framework that radically departs from current or ideal
practice is unhelpful, a competency-based model is
preferable to ensure sexual
health service access. However, a competency-based approach requires the girl to
satisfy an evidential
test, demonstrating to the doctor that she has achieved
the requisite degree of competence. Further, this threshold must be ascertained
so as not to be set at an unattainable
level.[65]
III Gillick:
The Watershed Case
The House of Lords in Gillick
recognised (3:2) a child’s legal competence in making decisions
provided that she had sufficient understanding and intelligence
to enable full
understanding of the
proposition.[66] Mrs Gillick, a
Catholic, sought two declarations, responding to a Health Authority’s
circular allowing discretionary contraceptive
treatment and advice for minors.
Firstly, that contraceptive advice was unlawful and amounted to encouragement of
doctors to commit
offences, by causing or encouraging unlawful sexual
intercourse with girls under 16. Secondly, which is more relevant to this paper,
that such advice was inconsistent with parental rights and duties.
Woolf
J in the first instance dismissed both actions, holding that if the child had
sufficient maturity to understand the advantages
and disadvantages of the
proposed treatment, she was competent to
consent.[67] The Court of Appeal
held to the traditional nuclear family model, where the child remains under
parental control until 16.[68]
However this archaic viewpoint is unrealistic and necessitates a status-based
test.[69] Furthermore, the
case[70] relied upon was later held
“horrendous” given vast social
changes.[71]
The majority of
the House of Lords, professed the view that parental rights are instrumental
only in facilitating the fulfilment of
duties. Proclaiming that children are
individuals who grow in intelligence, competence and autonomy as they move
towards adulthood,
the mature minor doctrine or Gillick-competency was
conceived.[72]
Lord Scarman
states that when the child is a competent minor, the doctor need not inquire
further into wider interests.[73]
His Lordship adopts Lord Denning’s dissent that the parental right of
control is a “dwindling right”, which begins
with a right and ends
with only the ability to give
advice.[74] Naturally, the degree of
parental control practically exercised will
vary.[75] Not divesting parents of
all guardianship rights, his Lordship clarifies that these rights exist only so
as to enable parents to
discharge their obligations to the child. They must
thereby be exercised with the child’s interests in mind, rather than the
parents’, and do not wholly disappear until the age of
majority.[76] As parental rights
must be exercised in the child’s interests, if capable, the child must be
allowed to determine their own
interests.[77] Under Lord
Scarman’s formulation; once the child reaches requisite legal capacity so
as to have sufficient maturity to understand,
and intelligence to enable full
understanding of a proposition, parental rights to determine healthcare for
their child “terminate”,
yielding to the competent minor. Lord
Scarman’s judgment is the clearest and is unequivocal in respect of
parental rights;
later retreats from this position were met by vociferous
commentator complaints.
Public policy and changing social customs
underpinned all judgments, especially Lord Fraser’s speech, which was
tailored specifically
towards contraception
provision.[78] That said, given that
statutory provisions for minor consent do not differentiate between
contraceptives and other treatment, Lord
Fraser infers that minors either have
potential capacity to assent to all treatments or
none.[79] However, cautious in
requiring some legal constraint, Lord Fraser provided guiding criteria to
regulate appropriate circumstances
for a doctor to prescribe contraception to
girls under 16 years, by vesting the doctor with authority to determine the
girl’s
best interests. Thus, the girl’s consent is necessary to
protect bodily integrity, but not sufficient, as the doctor must inquire
into
her best interests beyond the purely medical, including wider social and moral
factors. By requiring a doctor to judge the girl’s
best interests, as well
as the minor’s self-evaluation, Lord Fraser could be saying that public
policy requires the final decision
to be the doctor’s rather than the
parents’.[80] This exception
is justified, as children are notoriously reluctant to confide in parents on
sexual matters and doctors are often
entrusted with discretion beyond strict
clinical judgment. Further, doctors are best positioned to discharge this
inquiry.[81] Attempting to find a
practical solution, Lord Fraser requires bona fide medical judgment of best
interests. However, by giving doctors
this discretion, he fails to accord the
level of autonomy a competent child would have under Lord Scarman’s
formulation. One
difficulty arising under Lord Fraser’s formulation is,
should the doctor think treatment is not in the child’s best interests
without parental consent, the girl may require parental involvement.
Contraceptives treatment is held to be in the tiny minority
of healthcare where
the best judge of an incompetent child’s welfare is not the
parent.[82]
Accordingly,
doctors should try to persuade the minor to tell her parents about the advice
sought, or receive permission to inform,
but proceeding can be justified without
parental consent or knowledge, provided the following satisfy the
doctor:[83]
(1) The minor will understand medical advice; and
(2) She cannot be persuaded to inform parents; and
(3) She is likely to begin or continue to have sexual intercourse with or without contraceptive treatment; and
(4) Unless receiving contraceptive treatment, her physical or mental health, or both, are likely to suffer; and
(5) Best interests require contraceptive advice and treatment without parental consent.
These guidelines apply Gillick-competency
specifically to contraceptive treatment. The emphasis on health suffering
without treatment, in Lord Fraser’s criteria,
frames the situation as an
access issue and creates an argument for the basis of this extension from the
doctrine of necessity, as
otherwise health will
suffer.[84] This view contrasts with
Lord Brandon’s thinking that young girls demanding contraception was
“tantamount to blackmail”
and that the law should reply with
abstinence until 16
years.[85]
Lord Bridge opined
that the criminal law seeks to protect young women from untoward consequences of
sexual intercourse. In circumstances
where criminal sanction will not afford
protection it is not contrary to public policy to provide contraception as the
sole effective
means of protection and avoidance of STIs and undesired
pregnancy. [86] Thus provision of
contraceptives effectively fills the lacuna that legal protections provide to
young females to prevent harm from
sexual activities.
Within the
majority, there is inconsistency on the standard required to be
Gillick-competent. They agree that rather than total inability to
consent, there is a presumption of incompetence that the girl can rebut
by
demonstrating capacity.[87] However,
Lord Fraser’s standard of competence requires the young woman’s and
the doctor’s view of her best interests
to coincide, whereas Lord Scarman
bases the test on full comprehension of medical issues, without mentioning best
interests.
The minority judgments indicate a difference between ordinary
medical and contraceptive treatment. While agreeing that a mature minor
could
consent to an ordinary therapeutic operation, opposed by parents and
acknowledging a dwindling parental right, Lord Templeman
differentiates between
provision of medical services, and sexual health services, as a lifestyle choice
rather than a treatment.[88] A
girl’s decision to practice sexual intercourse requires not only factual
knowledge of the dangers of pregnancy and disease,
but also comprehension of
emotional consequences on all involved, and daily discipline in the oral
contraceptive pill’s case,
to ensure efficacy. His Lordship expressed
doubt in a minor’s ability to balance such
considerations.[89] Further, he
expressed concern that Lord Fraser’s formulation can be reduced to
replacing parental consent with that of the
doctor.
[90] However, Lord Templeman
clarified that parental rights may have been renounced if the girl is discovered
not to be living with a
parent and is allowed in a dangerous environment with
sexual intercourse, or if parental rights are abused, such as when there is
sexual abuse in the home
environment.[91] However, a girl may
desist from obtaining contraceptive treatment if aware that an investigation
into abuse would ensue.
Autonomous adults and Gillick-competent
minors must bear the consequences of their choices, including those not made in
their objective best interests. Gillick requires the health practitioner
to determine whether the child possesses the understanding and maturity to form
a balanced judgment
regarding proposed treatment, so as to be treated without
needing parental consent. This accords a wide discretionary basis for
determining
maturity but provides little guidance. With cases like contraceptive
treatment, it is now arguable that the doctor is a better judge
of the advice
and treatment conducive to a girl’s
welfare.[92] However, a mature minor
upholding bodily freedom is diametrically opposed to traditional parental
rights, which remains a pervasive
view.[93] However, attempting to
balance interests, and prevent a licence for doctors disregarding parental
wishes, the law Lords stressed
that practitioners should encourage the
child’s involvement of a parent or trusted adult in medical decisions.
Nevertheless,
refusal to do so should not preclude treatment if the practitioner
is satisfied of their maturity.[94]
This allows the common law to acknowledge developing maturity and autonomy, and
diminishing parental control, rather than a stringent
arbitrary age which until
reached is subject to the decision making authority of, parents or guardians.
Gillick has been adopted in Canada and
Australia.[95] In a Canadian case,
Kerans JA dismissed an appeal which sought an injunction to prevent their mature
minor child’s abortion.
Confirming parental rights do not wholly
disappear until the age of majority, the termination of parental rights for
medical decisions
occurs upon achieving full
understanding.[96]
In Re
A, Bodey J considered the bounds of a vulnerable adult’s understanding
on which to refuse contraceptive
treatment.[97] He considered that a
capacity test should ascertain the woman’s ability to understand and weigh
up immediate medical issues.
This shows a narrower scope than that considered in
Gillick, where full understanding and recognition of the impact on
relationships was mentioned.[98]
Immediate medical issues included (i) reasons for requiring contraceptive
treatment and its purpose, (ii) the different types of
available contraception
and their methods of use, (iii) advantages and disadvantages of each type, (iv)
possible side effects of
each and how to deal with them, (v) the relative ease
of changing methods of contraception and finally (vi) the generally accepted
effectiveness of each type.[99]
Obiter indicates that consideration regarding the woman’s understanding of
the practicalities of child rearing is not required,
as this is subjective, and
reality can materially
change.[100] If appreciation of
what is involved for caring and raising a child is required, this gets close to
requiring woman to make sensible
decisions and take minimal risks. It was held
that this would blur the requirements of capacity and best interests, therefore
limiting
to immediate medical issues surrounding contraception.
IV
Great Britain’s Response to Gillick
Axon was a judicial
review application contesting the Health Authority guidance on confidential
advice on sexual health matters, the decision
discussed confidentiality bounds
for mature minors.[101] Silber J
confirmed that ordinarily parents are the best judges of a young person’s
welfare.[102] It is inherent
within application of the Gillick mature minor test that the medical
practitioner in some circumstances need not notify parents as loss of confidence
would deter some
young people and would run contrary to the public policy
factors and autonomy foundations of the Gillick
principle.[103] Importantly,
Silber J acknowledged that Gillick is the litmus test covering all
medical treatment scenarios without parental knowledge or consent.
[104] However, the high knowledge
standard is maintained, requiring full
understanding.[105] This suggests
a higher competency threshold, in terms of understanding, for minors than for
adults.
In Re L, L, who was 14, required gangrene preventative
blood transfusions.[106] However,
as a Jehovah’s Witness, she refused. Rigid religious convictions were
distinguished from the kind of formulated opinion
one constructs through
experience.[107] Given that
experience and its consequent wisdom is a requirement, this means that the
threshold may not be met by minors. Therefore,
L was found not to have capacity
and a court order was granted, as it was deemed in her best interests to receive
a blood transfusion.
This indicating that when a minor chooses to proceed in a
manner not in her objective best interests, she may be classed
incompetent.
P, a competent 15 year old sought an abortion against her
father’s the wishes, and the court found that the father’s objection
did not override her consent, despite other cases where parental objections
prevail.[108] Paternalistic
notions continue to exist as the court retained protective power, stating that
it may veto if this is considered as
in the child’s best interests.
However, medical opinion viewed the abortion as in her best
interests.
Logically, Gillick competency may be thought to extend
to consent refusal, but in subsequent cases the English Court of Appeal in Re
R and Re W held that Gillick meant a competent child could
consent, but that refusal did not have the same force, and so could be
countermanded by the court or
parents.[109] This retreat is
based on society’s unwillingness to trust teenagers in decisions that will
irreparably damage their long term
interests requiring a higher threshold of
capacity for life-threatening
refusals.[110] However, surely
this is invalid for contraceptive treatment. Provision of contraceptives could
require a lower threshold as inherently
seeks to prevent pregnancy and STIs that
carry long term consequences so to be potentially in what the doctors and courts
collectively
consider to be in the woman’s best interests.
In Re
R, a 15 year old with psychosis indicated unwillingness to consent to
antipsychotic drugs whilst lucid. Lord Donaldson MR stated that
a child’s
right to consent is not exclusive but runs concurrently to the parents’
several and joint right to give valid
consent.[111] Given their
concurrency, only single consent is needed to continue, as both keys turn the
lock.[112] Therefore the court,
parents, or mature minor can consent to treatment. So for a
Gillick-competent minor, despite attaining their own legal capacity to
consent, the parents also retain their right to consent, but cannot
veto their
competent minor’s consent. This parental right is significant because if a
competent minor refuses, the parental
consent enables lawfully rendered
treatment.
Gillick was further diluted in a case regarding a 16
year old’s anorexia nervosa
treatment.[113]
While affirming the Court’s virtually limitless inherent powers under
parens patriae which extend beyond rights of parents and
include ability to
override competent minors, the court allowed parents to also effectively
override a refusal.[114] Grubb and
Kennedy heavily criticise Re W and question how reconcilable it
is, given that a competent child is entitled to have their confidences
respected, if a child refuses, how can a parent consent to treatment
without
undermining this
confidentiality.[115] There may be
a public interest exception allowing disclosure but this would severely
undermine the essence of competence.
Although the retreat is inherently
paternalistic, McDowell acknowledges that, from a policy perspective, the
justification of a stringent
test is the protection of the minor from unwise
decisions and saving of the child when a refusal could lead to death or
disability.
[116] Given the
intimate nature of contraceptives and controversy around abortion, it would seem
a greater invasion of autonomy if parents
could enforce contraceptive treatment
or pregnancy termination. Lord Donaldson MR opined the possibility of an
abortion being enacted
by doctors upon parental consent despite the
child’s refusal, stating the court’s jurisdiction was open to
protect the
child should the abortion not be in her best
interests.[117] While stating that
this is a hair raising possibility, the law may allow terminations upon parental
consent despite ethical objections.
If there is no consensus between the young
woman, parents and doctors as to her best interests, there is the possibility
that a parental
consent could suffice. New Zealand’s Family Court and High
Court have similar jurisdictions. However in CoCA s 38(1)(b), the
abortion
specific section, it is stated a refusal is effective as if she were of full
age. Further, s 36(1) includes “refusal”
for minor’s consent
generally, potentially signalling that any retreat from Gillick by Re
R and Re W is not an intended part of the New Zealand jurisprudence.
V The Law in New Zealand
The HDC and ACC regimes have
effectively reduced litigation on consent in New Zealand, resulting in little
direct authority. The Family
Court has observed the change of perception of a
child’s worth consistently with majority’s reasoning in
Gillick in guardianship
disputes.[118]
Judge
Ullrich held that a 15 year old was competent to consent to vaccination against
parental wishes and should be permitted to make
their own decision so that the
consent prevailed over parental
views.[119] This is consistent
with the Gillick-competent minor doctrine where such minors are accorded
rights to positive consent.
The idea of competency and expressing views
often arises in guardianship disputes. Gillick-competency has
been used in resolving a conflict over the doctor consulted by a 14 year old
girl in a guardianship dispute, as she
was competent to form her own
decision.[120] Judge Ullrich also
came close to declaring Gillick as applying in New Zealand; after quoting
Lord Scarman’s sufficient understanding test, she stated that this
principle has been
applied in New
Zealand.[121]
The most
authoritative case is Re J, which concerned a 3 year old with
Jehovah’s Witness parents who refused consent for blood transfusions for a
life-threatening
nose bleed. [122]
The authority is limited, not directly being applicable to minors formulating
their own decisions; however, Gillick reasoning that the parental right
was never absolute was applied by the Court of
Appeal.[123] In the High Court,
Ellis J applied Gillick as stating the correct position for infant
minors; a parent having custody and responsibility for the infant is entitled to
consent
or reject treatment on the infant’s behalf, if the parent
considers it not in the child’s best interests.
[124] Further, if doctor and
parent disagree, the court has jurisdiction and is not tardy in
response.[125]
A
Contraception, Sterilisation and Abortion Act 1977
The only statutory
section referring to provision of contraceptives to children under 16 years was
repealed in 1990.[126] Section 3
of the Contraception, Sterilisation and Abortion Act 1977 made it illegal to
provide services for advice or access to contraceptives
to anyone under 16,
unless the provider fell within an exception, severely limiting contraceptive
access. The exceptions included
parents, registered medical practitioners,
pharmacists, social workers and counsellors. Both a friend persuading a peer to
practice
safe sex, or a child knowingly procuring or attempting to procure
contraceptives, from anyone but an authorised person would have
committed an
offence.[127]
Today,
unlike abortion services, there is no specific statutory right to access or
ability to consent to contraceptive
treatment.[128] This means that
contraceptive supply to minors is subject to the general rules governing
consent. Parliamentary intention of reducing
barriers to contraception could be
seen as inviting the common law to develop in parallel as opposed to at
odds.[129]
While condoms,
a barrier method of contraception, are now openly available, as a method they
rely on cooperation, access and use in
each instance of intercourse. They are
insufficient, as use can be erratic or denied, especially if the young girl is
subject to
abuse. Friedman-Ross argues that this over-the-counter access is
pragmatic, allowing accessibility while neither attempting to override
parental
moral values, nor condone adolescent sexual
activity.[130] However, this does
not help to determine competency.
The previous HDC Commissioner referred
favourably to Gillick.[131]
In a presentation, the Commissioner discussed a complaint from a parent
concerned about her lack of knowledge of the contraceptive
advice and
prescriptions received by her 15 year old daughter from a Family Planning
Association (FPA) clinic. The response emphasised
that there is no statutory
restriction on advice or contraception prescription supply to people of any age.
[132]
B Care of Children
Act 2004
Young males and females under 16 years have no statutory
capacity to consent to medical
treatment.[133] Prior to 1 July
2005, the law was contained in the Guardianship Act 1968. CoCA poses the
greatest obstacle for adopting Gillick, as it encroaches on common law
except where otherwise
expressed.[134] If it was not for
section 36, “without doubt” people under 16 would have capacity to
give legally effective consent for
criminal and tortious liability.
[135] This would not mean all
children could consent, as even for adults consent is not an all or nothing
matter, but could depending upon
ability and understanding of the
decision’s significance.
Only two changes were made from s 25 Guardianship Act to
the new s 36; firstly s 36(1) was clarified to include consent
refusal[136] and s 36(2) applies
also where that child is living as a de facto partner. The lack of clarification
regarding children under 16
has been held as a lost opportunity, there being no
indication that proxy consent is always required so the position of under 16
year olds remains unclear.[137]
The first change is critical, explicitly including positive consent and refusal,
so minors over 16 years do not have the implications
of Post-Gillick,
whereby parents can countermand a competent minor’s refusal of
consent.[138]
Some
commentators held that by not mentioning the legal position of those under 16,
such people, by implication, cannot give effective
consent.[139] This is based on the
canon of construction expressio unius est exlusio alterius, so the express
mention of ability to consent if
over 16 years, excludes the ability of those
below. Section 38 purports to override s 36 allowing abortion consent at any age
as
if s 36 prevents legal validity. Burrows warns that, while a valuable guide,
such canons need not be “slavishly” adhered
to.[140] Section 36 can be
interpreted as continuing an orthodox status-based test whereby all minors below
16, by reason of their age are
incapable of giving legally effective consent.
Parents’ right to control, manifest through their right to consent, could
be
construed as implying that the child’s consent is unnecessary. Tompkins
J in the High Court supported the orthodox view that
consent must be obtained
from persons other than the child aged under 16 before treatment is
administered, given lack of explicit
reference in s25(3) Guardianship Act 1968.
[141] However, this position is
not universally held. The Court has acknowledged that it is positioned to take
into account a 12-year-old’s
views; however the child and parents
expressed similar
wishes.[142]
By allowing a
purposive interpretation of s 36 which accommodates Gillick, the common
law can fill the lacuna for children aged under
16.[143] The modern trend has been
towards purposive interpretation which is mandated by s 5(1) Interpretation Act
1999, so that words are
read in their fullest context thereby working in the
intended manner of the
legislation.[144] The meaning of a
provision must always be cross checked against the purpose of the provision
itself and the Act’s wider social
objectives.[145] This is
advantageous if arguing that Gillick should be applied in New Zealand, as
a purposive interpretation holds that an Act’s interpretation should not
obstruct its own
purpose[146]
unless it is clear in doing so. It is not explicit and refusal of consent
capacity consent is not necessarily
implied.[147] Further, obiter in a
guardianship dispute is notable, as Health J sought to apply parental duties
rather than rights, holding Gillick philosophy as consistent with
CoCA’s
purpose.[148]
One
interpretation is that there is a presumption of consent for those above the set
age of 16, but given the silence on the matter,
those below 16 have a
presumption of incompetence, subject to rebuttal, by way of Gillick
mature minor competence in relation to the
procedure.[149] Tiered approaches
are already contained within CoCA. Section 16 adopts a tiered approach for the
guardian’s powers regarding
important matters affecting the child,
including non-routine medical treatment. This means, a guardian can sometimes
determine the
matter for the child, but can also assist the older child’s
decision making by proffering information and
advice.[150] This is consistent
with parental control being neither exclusive nor complete and reflective of the
duties owed by the parent to
the
child[151] and the purposes of
CoCA.[152]
Section 36 does
not purport to place children aged 16 to 17 years in an adult position, there is
an important qualification in s36
(1)(b); that the health service must be in the
child’s best interests. Best interests are held to be the first and
paramount
consideration in s 4. Section 5 contains principles relevant to
determining these paramount best interests. Arguably, it is consistent
with the
overall purpose of the Act that this restriction would also apply if ability to
consent is extended to under-sixteen-year-olds.
However, if a child is sexually
active, contraception is doubtless in his and her best interests. However, s 5
does raise issues,
as it provides that:
a) the child’s parents and guardians should have the primary
responsibility, and should be encouraged to agree to their own
arrangements, for
the child’s care, development, and upbringing
...
d) relationships between the child and members of his or her family, family
group, whānau, hapu, or iwi should be preserved and
strengthened, and those
members should be encouraged to participate in the child’s care,
development, and upbringing
This has potential use in strengthening
claims of parental involvement, negating minors’ need for capacities to
consent. However,
this seems inconsistent with the Act as a whole, to focus on a
couple of principles’ potential to undermine the other principles
contained within. Especially given that best interests is considered paramount
and the child’s views are deemed as relevant
to the best
interests.[153]
Section
36(2) provides that a child, who is married, in a civil union or in a de facto
relationship, can consent to and refuse treatment
for themselves or another
person. There is, therefore, a statutory right on young people, on the basis of
attaining parenthood, to
consent to their child’s healthcare, self
grounded on the increased need for independence.
[154] Further, through marriage,
civil union or de facto relationships minors can be accorded competency. This
does not create tensions
with parental rights, which have been completely
terminated in the emancipated minor’s favour. Further, given the
qualification
that treatment must be to the child’s benefit is not in s
36(2), such children are closer to adult status than “ordinary”
16
to 17 year olds.
Section 36(5) seems to reduce the chance of importing
Gillick competency.[155]
This section purports to prevent s36 as being an overriding statutory provision
unless expressly stated. Subsection (5)(c) seemingly
revitalises the Re W
scenario, whereby parental consent overrides child refusal, as parental
consent is sufficient, except in the circumstances in (2)
where they have
forfeited parental rights. Section 37 grants medical professionals immunity from
legal suits if complied with when
administering a blood transfusion despite
nonconformity with s 36. Common law defences of necessity are authorised by s
36(5)(a).
Lord Diplock has suggested that caution be taken when
developing common law based on an elderly statute that is incompatible with
modern thinking, or politically
controversial.[156] Unfortunately
CoCA is recent legislation, albeit largely unmodified from its predecessor. More
importantly, the statute states nothing
regarding under-sixteen-year-olds, so
common law must develop. It is at least arguable that in some senses it is
incompatible with
modern thought. It must be remembered that the additions to s
36 have enhanced rather than restricted a minor’s capacity to
consent to
medical treatment, consistent with the overall purpose. An important feature of
purposive interpretation is that when
multiple possible meanings exist, the one
in best accordance with the purpose should be
effected.[157] Furthermore,
courts are often reluctant to accept a statute’s entire subsumption of
common law. [158]
Section
13 provides that CoCA is to act as a code. The section does not help further
arguments that Gillick can apply. As Gillick is not expressly
mentioned within the Act, there is no argument that this part of the common law
is preserved.[159] Further, the
High Court retains powers it had prior to 1970 for matters not provided for
within the Act, however Gillick was decided in
1986.[160]
Section 38 overrides s 36 and any ambiguities created in
subpart (2). Since 1977 all women have been able to consent to or refuse
an
abortion. The provision was unaltered by its replication within
CoCA.[161] However, this was
debated, especially the confidentiality implications. A Supplementary Order
Paper to the Bill, requiring parental
notification of girls under 16 seeking an
abortion was rejected 75:45.[162]
Bill English proclaimed the law “repugnant” in allowing girls to
return to school having had an abortion without parental
knowledge, as the
parents and girl, not the professional, have to live with the
“consequences”.[163]
While Tapu Misa acknowledged that there was no right answer to the problem, she
knew her position if her own daughter were
implicated.[164] However parents
cannot blame the law for their child’s
secrecy.[165] Surely, it is the
correct position as it would infringe rights of bodily integrity if one were
forced to terminate a wanted
pregnancy,[166] or denied a
desired termination that could be obtained, but for lack of consent capacity.
Section 38 provides that age is not determinative of capacity to
consent, but certainly capacity is still relevant. It does not unequivocally
state that all females can give effective consent to pregnancy termination,
rather that their age is an irrelevant consideration.
As competency is still
required,[167] the Gillick
mature minor test would be appropriate. Medical practitioners must consult
other practitioners to assess the woman’s mental
condition and likely
effects of continuation or abortion of
pregnancy.[168] Age is an
insufficient criterion to form incompetence but is still relevant for meeting
exclusion criteria from criminal
liability.[169]
However, s
38 as an exception to the rule is insufficient. For example, it allows consent
to an abortion, but if a complication arises,
applying strict interpretation of
s 36 without Gillick-competency, parents would have to consent to further
treatment. To consent, they would require sufficient information.
C New Zealand Bill of Rights Act 1990
Prima facie, all
children are entitled to the rights accorded within the New Zealand Bill of
Rights Act 1990 (NZBORA), as only s 12
has age restrictions. Section 11
expressly provides that “everyone” has the right to refuse medical
treatment. “Everyone”
has been defined by the High Court as solely
people competent to consent. [170]
Therefore, a minor must be Gillick-competent to be accorded the right to
refuse treatment under the NZBORA.
While the NZBORA cannot be used to
override other Acts, a consistent interpretation is preferable; Re J
depicts definitional balancing to prevent inconsistency between
rights.[171] While observing that
no court can decline provision application due to inconsistencies in NZBORA,
Gault J held that J’s parents’
right to religion was not allowed to
extend to imperilling J’s life or health, entitling the Court to intervene
and consent
to treatment.[172]
While not dealing with a mature minor, Gault J applied the reasoning behind the
Gillick mature minor doctrine, that parental rights are determined by the
extent of required parental duties and the paramount interests
of the child.
Even incompetent minors’ best interests are to be held paramount and
protected against parental rights to manifest
their
religion.[173] An orthodox
Catholic parent’s opposition to contraception, therefore, should not
override their child’s best interests.
D The Code
Gillick is reflected in The Code; delegated legislation authorised
by the Health and Disability Act
1994.[174] The Code goes beyond
common law with all rights applicable to all consumers, regardless of age. Right
7 is dedicated to competency
and consent and does not provide a set age for
deemed competency.
Right 7(2) provides a presumption of competence for
all health consumers, to make an informed choice, except where common law or any
enactment provides otherwise. Significantly, s 36 CoCA is ambiguous regarding
the position of those under 16, so The Code is not
necessarily subverted. Lord
Scarman held no support for presuming the competence of minors, he emphasised
the need for individualised
assessment.[175] McDowell argues,
even with a presumption, determination is still on a case-by-case basis so is
consistent with Gillick.
[176] However, a
presumption may reflect
reality.[177] Nonetheless, a
doctor interpreting the right might apply a status-based approach, using age as
reasonable grounds for concluding
incompetency. Therefore, greater clarity of
the legal position is required for a consistent approach. Skegg argues that
seeking to
determine competence is more desirable than presuming it. By seeking
to ascertain capacity, one is provided the chance of making
a more autonomous
decision. [178] This would allow a
consistent starting point, although naturally the degree of inquisition into
competence would differ depending
on age.
Right 7(3) allows for the
involvement of those with diminished competence commensurate to their level of
competence, thus allowing
for incompetent minors’ involvement. Right 7(4)
applies in the case of
incompetence.[179] Treatment
provided must be in the best interests, and the person administering treatment
must take reasonable steps to ascertain
the patient’s views, also taking
into account those of other persons involved in the child’s welfare.
Therefore, when
confronted with an incompetent minor, the doctor must strive to
assess the child’s views and their alignment with proposed
treatment, or
must consider parental views in the child’s best interests. The Code
proposes these as alternatives. However,
as The Code is not designed to displace
other laws, parental consent on the incompetent minor’s behalf would still
likely be
required.
Importantly, The Code, in some situations, places
an obligation on the health professional to assess competency and best
interests,
the same obligation required by Gillick. Further, at no point
is there a status-based test. Right 7(7) recognising every consumer’s
right to refuse services in conjunction
with the inclusion of refusal in ss 36
and 38 bolsters rejection of the English Court of Appeal’s arbitrary
decisions.
It is significant that the Health and Disability Commissioner
feels there is scope for Gillick under The Code. A mother’s
complaint against a local medical centre giving her 14 year old son a tetanus
injection after a minor
injury at school was found to be no
breach.[180] Right 7(2) in
presuming competency, in the previous Commissioner’s view, allows for a
competency-based assessment. In applying
Gillick, competency should not
be determined solely on an age basis, and rather determined by ability to
understand information regarding
risks and consequences of any decision and the
situation’s relative seriousness. Allowing a mature minor test would
satisfy
the objective of Right 3, to ensure services optimise the
consumer’s
independence.[181]
However,
power was not conferred by Parliament, to alter the general law relating to
consent.[182] Thus, The Code
cannot be inconsistent with other enactments If it is, the practitioner should
follow the other enactment.[183]
Despite The Code’s capability of consistent interpretation with
Gillick, reconciliation is required with s 36(1), which prevails in cases
of inconsistency. This means orthodox interpretations of s 36 could
prevail. However, a more satisfactory interpretation of reconciling
Gillick exists; 7(2) reasonable grounds can accommodate the mature minor
test highlighting autonomy which is consistent with the rights-based
origin of
the code.[184]
E
International Obligations
Almost universally ratified, UNCRC limits
parental powers and duties based on adolescents’ “evolving
capacities”
for
self-determination.[185] New
Zealand’s international obligations increasingly emphasise the child,
rather than rights exercised on its behalf by guardians,
and bolster the
adoption of the common law
approach.[186]
Article 12
stipulates that children are entitled to assume control of their affairs upon
developing the capacities enabling them to
do so. This is consistent with a
competency, rather than status-based, consent model. Article 24 is a right to
health and in paragraphs
(b) and (f) specifically include developing primary
healthcare and family planning; education and services.
Article
12’s ideology is reflected in Children’s Commissioner Act
2003’s purpose, where the Commissioner is to be
conferred powers to better
effect New Zealand’s obligations under UNCRC and to regard the convention
when exercising duties
and
powers.[187] Fraser J regarded the
UNCRC as a legitimate source from which to derive doctrines and rules regarding
children’s welfare.[188]
Furthermore, international instruments are considered to be relevant in
exercising discretion and interpretation of statues is to
be in a manner that
gives effect to international
obligations.[189] Therefore
international obligations add weight to the argument that Gillick
competency can apply in New Zealand.
VI Confidentiality
Confidentiality is vital and stems from the general obligation of
respect implicit in doctor-patient relationships.
[190] It increases youth confidence,
cooperation, ensures honesty regarding risky behaviours and thereby permits
proper appraisal of infection
risks and appropriate advice. However, this
conflicts with parents’ natural anxiousness concerning their child’s
life.[191] Parental notification
of girls seeking abortions or contraception forgets that boys too, are
implicated in the lifestyle choice the
parents are challenging. The New South
Wales Law Commission reported that requiring parental consent or notification in
sexual health
services deters many youths from seeking
treatment.[192] Despite this,
during the review of the Care of Children Bill, attention focused on the clause
replicating the status quo, allowing
a girl of any age the right to consent to
or refuse a pregnancy termination without mandatory notification. Kennedy
asserts that
adults, claiming a right to be informed, often present their
argument unattractively, harking back to traditional chattel ideology.
[193] Mandatory notification
ignores the reality that reactions will likely be severer than if the daughter
discloses
voluntarily.[194]
There are
strict exceptions for disclosure under the Health Information Privacy Code 1994
(HIPC) as parents have no automatic right
to their child’s health
information. [195] HIPC draws no
distinction between adults and children, and an understanding-based test is
adopted for the ability to exercise HIPC
rights.[196] Rule 11 prohibits
disclosure of health information save for where an exception applies, and is
discretionary in application. A
representative is someone with a degree of
access to, and control over, a person’s health information, including a
child under
16’s parent or guardian.
[197] Under section 22F of the
Health Act 1956, a representative has limited rights to information about their
child. The Privacy Commissioner notes that, while the laws surrounding
health
information may allow disclosure, health practitioners must consider both legal
obligations under HIPC and ethical obligations
of confidentiality. The
law’s allowance of disclosure does not necessarily render it
ethical.[198] This is significant,
given the particularly sensitive nature of sexual health
services.[199]A
representative’s request is treated as equivalent to a patient’s
request for health information; however, it can be
refused if perceived as
against the child’s interests.
[200] Once the patient is 16,
parents no longer have rights to their health information per se. However, rule
11(2)(b) will permit a health
practitioner to disclose information to a
principal caregiver if compatible with professional practice, or if getting the
patient’s
permission is undesirable. For example, if they are unconscious,
not if they are attempting to obtain something potentially objectionable,
like
an abortion.[201] Rule 11(2)(d)
permits disclosure without consent if necessary to prevent serious threats to
the life or health of the individual
concerned. This is unlikely to extend to
the unborn “child” in a proposed termination. Sometimes the
practitioner’s
role is to encourage parental acceptance of the value of
their child’s
autonomy.[202]
FPA states
they will encourage the girl to tell her parents, as Gillick holds, but
her refusal is not sufficient for a doctor to ignore her confidentiality. If
disclosure was standard, future patients
may be
deterred.[203] Naturally, there
will be compromises. Where the adolescent is monetarily dependent on a guardian,
the provider may be unable to conceal
the fact that gynaecological services were
rendered, but non-specific details may be
given.[204] However, given that
most sexual health services in New Zealand have government subsidies, this
compromise is minimal.
Kennedy requires that one must have the legal
capacity to entrust so as to bind the doctor to such an obligation.
[205] Therefore, prima facie when
the child is incompetent, the doctor is obliged to disclose information gained,
to the parents. This
is consistent with the paramount concern of child’s
interests. If competent, however, the balance does not favour
disclosure.[206] This must be
true, as status-based confidence rights would ignore the fact that children
often acquire autonomy before their sixteenth
birthday, and would undermine the
therapeutic
relationship.[207]
VII
Australia
Despite adoption of Gillick in common law
jurisprudence, [208] some states
have opted to legislate.
New South Wales allows minors consent to medical
or dentistry treatment in certain
circumstances.[209] The provision
requires the minor to be 14 or older, so that treatment undertaken with prior
consent of the minor is lawful, with
relation to claims of battery or assault,
as if the minor were the age of majority. This is similar to s 36 but deems
competency
at a younger age. New South Wales Law Commission believes that a
young person, even if incompetent to give consent should, nonetheless,
have
access to contraceptive advice and treatment, if she will otherwise have, or
continue to have, unprotected intercourse, risking
pregnancy and
STIs.[210] The health practitioner
in such circumstances could exercise discretion to act in the patient’s
best interests, and so would
dispense with required parental involvement in both
mature and immature minors. In doing so, the pivotal requirement of consent is
removed, thereby providing a workable framework for the situation. This possibly
goes too far in bending legal principles in applying
also to incompetent minors,
albeit achieving a desirable result.
Section 12 Medical Treatment and
Palliative Care Act 1995 (SA) contains a statutory framework for when medical
treatment can be administered
to a child 15 years or less; if the child
consents; the doctor believes it capable of understanding the treatment;
treatment is in
the child’s best interests; and another doctor who has
examined the child has written supporting the proposed treatments. The
final
requirement provides consistency in practice, however, will inherently create
delays and increased costs in treatment as time
is required for a second
opinion.
VIII New Zealand
It is unhelpful having a legal
framework that ideal practice and reality significantly depart from.
[211] Given that legislation does
not differentiate between contraceptive treatment for children and adults, and
there is no express denial
of capacity for under 16 year olds, it is possible to
apply Gillick in New Zealand, especially given the favourable mention it
has enjoyed[212] McDowell argues
that absolutely requiring parental consent is overly
conservative.[213] Skegg
recommends that the better view is, common law capacity not being extinguished
by legislation, the consent of those under 16
being sometimes effective in
law.[214]
An adolescent
engaging in sexual relations may require treatment for STIs, or contraception to
prevent pregnancy, and those who seek
these services may have more maturity than
those who fail to.[215] FPA
provides free sexual health consultations and treatment in the community and
applies the “Fraser Guidelines”. The
“Fraser
Guidelines”, as interpreted by FPA, require competency “to make
informed decisions on a daily
basis.”[216] Thus it seems,
while the courts have yet to formally adopt Gillick-competency,
the Gillick test is already applied by doctors. Importantly, and
consistent with the “Fraser Guidelines”, FPA expect their health
professionals to encourage the child’s communication with parents but
acknowledge that it is not always possible. The Medical
Council’s
statement is less structured. They interpret s 36 as not automatically
prohibiting effective consent from persons
under 16, and recommend that doctors
assess the child’s competency and form an opinion on their capability to
give informed
consent. [217] A
competent child is “able to understand the nature, purpose and possible
consequences of the proposed investigation or treatment,
as well as consequences
of non-treatment.”[218]
Seemingly this is a lower and narrower standard limited to medical matters, than
advanced in Gillick. Self-assessment of best interests postulated in
common law, requires consideration and balancing of physical, psychological and
social effects of proposed treatment.
[219] In practice, it is important
to establish rapport and support the young person by encouraging discussion of
implications beyond medicine,
and reinforce despite confidentiality of
consultation that the young person should discuss this choice with a trusted
adult. [220] Overall, the medical
profession has already adopted Gillick.
While Gillick is
not necessarily excluded by legislation, and is unlikely to be endorsed by any
higher authority, statutory provision would be ideal.
The HDC, which governs
most healthcare disputes, speaks favourably of Gillick. The Family Court
has applied the wider principles in guardianship disputes, and FPA in providing
contraceptives, has adopted the “Fraser
Guidelines” to govern their
practice so there is scope for application. I personally propose that to best
align practice with
the law would be to legislate for Gillick competency
for those under 16 in a statutory amendment. Amendment would reduce scope of
interpretation of s 36. [221] Such
provision would be consistent with New Zealand’s legislative matrix, but
most importantly in line with practice. Recognising
increasing autonomy with
maturity in a clinical setting is appropriate and feasible, reducing need to
rely on status-based competency.
Furthermore, it is arguable that matters with
such far reaching social implications are best left to Parliament, which has the
benefit
of written submissions and is capable of rapid law change of outdated
law.[222] While the controversial
nature of such provision may hinder rapid legislation, it would provide the
requisite clarity.
IX Recent Updates
Since the completion of this paper in 2012, Judge Somerville’s judgment
in the Family Court has further affirmed the position
of this paper whilst
looking at s 16 CoCA, which concerns the exercise of guardianship.
[223] It was acknowledged that
guardians’ rights dwindle with the age of the child and yield to the
child’s right to make
their own decision when reaching a sufficient
understanding and intelligence to be capable of making independent decisions.
This
is a further restatement of Lord Scarman’s speech, showing acceptance
for Gillick to be part of New Zealand law.
[224] Judge Somerville considered
that the guardian’s role in general decision making for a child is staged,
beginning with determining
important matters for the child, moving to
determining them with the child and ending with helping the child to determine
questions
for themselves to prepare the child to have the freedom to make their
own decisions. [225] This changing
tiered role of guardians aligns with the view that age alone cannot determine
competency to consent and one interpretation
of s 36 CoCA discussed above.
X Conclusion
Blanket age restrictions based on a
status model of capacity are archaic and restrictive of children’s rights
in insisting that
all below this arbitrary age are incompetent and not the best
judge of their own interests.[226]
Given capacity is changing alongside the child’s individual development; a
competence-based consent is
required.[227] The Gillick
mature minor test is also potentially applicable in other necessary treatment,
mental health services and drug addiction services,
or even general
non-emergency health care. The “Fraser Guidelines”, which enshrine
the Gillick-competency principle specifically for contraceptives, are
already adopted by major health providers in New Zealand. Gillick should
be adopted and embraced to achieve a greater balance between the interests of
parents, children and the state,
[228] while also according with
the demands of reality. Amendment to explicitly fill this gap would create
clarity and consistency of
practice and is more likely than judicial declaration
on the point. Although it may be met with resistance, it would be merely
aligning
the law to society’s practice.
The law relating to parent and child is concerned with the problems of growth and maturity of the human personality. If the law should impose on the process of ‘growing up’ fixed age limits where nature only knows a continuous process, the price would be artificiality and a lack of realism in an area where the law must be sensitive to human development and social change.[229]
[*] Chantelle Murley is currently
in her final year of studying a BHSc/LLB(Hons) at the University of Auckland.
She wrote this paper
in 2012 as part of the honours component of her law degree.
The author would like to acknowledge Jo Manning for her much appreciated
support
and guidance as a supervisor for this research project and also Helen Simpson
for her editing and valuable feedback.
[1] Scholendorff v Society of
New York Hospital (1914) 105 NE 92 (CA) at 93 per Cardozo
J.
[2] Jodi Ribot “Underage
Abortion and Beyond: Developments of Spanish Law in Competent Minor’s
Autonomy” (2012) 20 Med L Rev 48 at
51.
[3] Carol Peters
“Consenting to Medical Treatment: Legal Requirements vs Medical Practice.
Are Healthcare Providers Exposing Themselves
to Potential Legal Action?”
(2009) 122 N Z Med J 50.
[4]
“Editorial: Abortion Law Best Left as it Stands” The New Zealand
Herald (online ed, Auckland, no date supplied); Bill English “Pregnant
Girls More at Risk if Parents Kept in the Dark” The New Zealand Herald
(online ed, Auckland, 12 October 2004); and Tapu Misa “When it Comes
to Abortion, Mothers Surely Know Best” The New Zealand Herald
(online ed, Auckland, no date supplied).
[5] Ministry of Health Our
Children’s Health: Key Findings on the Health of New Zealand Children
(June 1998) at 132.
[6]
Contraception, Sterilisation and Abortion Act 1977, s
2.
[7] Joshua Douglas “When
is a ‘Minor’ also an ‘Adult’?: An Adolescent’s
Liberty Interest in Accessing
Contraceptives from Public School Distribution
Programs” (2007) 43 Willamette L Rev 545 at 551; and Family Planning
“Sexuality – Young People and Their Rights” (2007) Positive
Sexual Health: Family
Planning
<www.familyplanning.org.nz/health_info_issues/information_for_parents_caregivers/young_people_their_rights>.
[8]
Peters, above n 3.
[9] Family
Planning, above n
7.
[10]Contraception,
Sterilisation and Abortion Act, s 46; Health Practitioners Competence Assurance
Act 2003, 174(2).
[11]Ellie Lee
“Young Women, Pregnancy and Abortion in Britain: A Discussion of Law
‘In Practice’” (2004) 18 Intl
JL & Poly & Fam 283 at
286.
[12] Ribot, above n 2 at 49;
and Lucy Thomson “Whose Right to Choose? A Competent Child’s Right
to Consent to and Refuse Medical
Treatment in New Zealand” (2001) 8 Canta
LR 143 at 149.
[13] New Zealand
Bill of Rights 1990, s11.
[14]
Ralph Pinnock and Jan Crosthwaite “When Parents Refuse Consent to
Treatment for Children and Young Persons” (2005) 41
J Paediatr Child
Health 369 at 371; and Re L (A Minor)(Medical Treatment: Gillick
Competency) [1998] 2 FLR 810 (Fam) at 812.
[15] New South Wales Law
Commission Young People and Consent to Health Care (Report 119, 2008) at
[6.3].
[16] Care of Children Act
2004, s 36 (3) [CoCA].
[17]
Re T [1992] EWCA Civ 18; [1992] 4 All ER 649
(CA).
[18] Ministry of Health
Consent in Child and Youth Health: Information for Practitioners (December
1998).
[19] Health and Disability
Commissioner Act 1994, s
2.
[20] Re T, above n
17.
[21] Ribot, above n 2, at
55.
[22] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at
[1.11].
[23] Accident
Compensation Act 2001, s
317.
[24] C Paul “The New
Zealand Cervical Cancer Study: Could It Happen Again?” (1988) 297 BMJ 533;
and Thomson, above n 12, at
147.
[25] Re W (A Minor)
(Medical Treatment: Court’s Jurisdiction) [1992] 1 Fam 64 (CA) at
78.
[26] Accident Compensation
Act, s 319.
[27] Taylor v
Beere [1982] NZCA 15; [1982] 1 NZLR 81
(CA).
[28] Green v Matheson
[1989] NZCA 195; [1989] 3 NZLR 564 (CA); and Health and Disability Commissioner Act, s
57(1)(d).
[29] Crimes Act 1961,
ss 196 and 190.
[30] Gillick v
West Norfork and Wisbech Area Health Authority [1985] UKHL 7; [1986] AC 112 (HL) at 190.
[31] Health and Disability
Commissioner Act, s 57(1).
[32]
Peters, above n 3, at 53.
[33]At
57.
[34] Opinion 01HDC02915
Health and Disability Commissioner, 6 March 2002.
[35] Fiona Miller “Wake up
COCA! Give Children the Right to Consent to Medical Treatment (2011) 7 NZFLJ
85.
[36] Care of Children Act, s
36. See also; High Court and Family Court jurisdiction to render consent
(whether given by Gillick-competent minor or guardian) subject to the
Court’s Guardianship authority.
[37] Lainie Friedman Ross
Children, Families and Health Care Decision- Making (Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 2002) at ch
8.
[38] Ministry of
Health, above n 18.
[39]
Jo Bridgeman “Young People and Sexual Health: Whose Rights? Whose
Responsibilities?” (2006) 14 Med L Rev
418.
[40] Gillick, above n
30, at 173.
[41] Bridgeman, above
n 39.
[42] BM Dickens and RJ Cook
“Adolescents and Consent to Treatment” (2005) 89 IJGO 179, at
179.
[43] Pinnock and
Crosthwaite, above n 14, at
370.
[44]At
370.
[45] Care of Children Act,
ss 3(2)(c) and 6.
[46] United
Nations Convention of the Rights of the Child 1577 UNTS 3 (opened for signature
20 November 1989, entered into force 2 September 1990), art
12.
[47] Ministry of Social
Development New Zealand’s Agenda for Children: Summary Report
(June 2002).
[48] Dickens and
Cook, above n 42, at 183.
[49]
Ribot, above n 2, at 50; and Pinnock and Crosthwaite, above n 15, at
370.
[50] Ribot, above n 2, at
51.
[51] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at
[6.89].
[52] Pinnock and
Crosthwaite, above n 14, at
370.
[53] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at [1.7]; and Miller, above n
35.
[54] Health and Disability
Commissioner (Code of Health and Disability Services Consumers' Rights)
Regulations 1996 [The Code], right
7; and PDG Skegg “Presuming Competence
to Consent: Could Anything Be Sillier?” (2011) 30 QUTLJ
165.
[55] Peters, above n 3, at
57.
[56] Gillick, above n
30, at 186.
[57] Ian Kennedy
Treat Me Right: Essays in Medical Law and Ethics (Clarendon Press,
Oxford, 1988), at 56.
[58]
Children, Young Persons, and Their Families Act 1989, s 272(1); and Crimes Act,
ss 21 and 22(1).
[59] Crimes
Act, s 143.
[60] Sarah Elliston
“If You Know What’s Good For You: Refusal of Consent to Medical
Treatment by Children” in Shelia
McLean (ed) Contemporary Issues in
Law, Medicine and Ethics (Dartmouth, Aldershot (England), 1996), at 42.
[61] United Nations Convention
of the Rights of the Child, above n 46; and Thomson, above n 12, at 150.
[62] Pinnock and Crosthwaite,
above n 14, at 370.
[63] Kennedy,
above n 57, at 58.
[64] Pinnock
and Crosthwaite, above n 14, at
371.
[65] Elliston, above n 60,
at 29.
[66] Gillick,
above n 30, at
188.
[67] Gillick v West
Norfork and Wisbech Area Health Authority [1984] QB 581 (QB) at
596.
[68] Gillick v West
Norfork and Wisbech Area Health Authority [1985] 2 WLR 413
(CA).
[69] Kennedy, above n 56,
at 623; and Morag McDowell “Medical Treatment and Children: Assessing the
Scope of a Child’s Capacity
to Consent or Refuse to Consent in New
Zealand” (1997) 5 J L & Med 81 at
81.
[70] Re Agar-Ellis,
Agar-Ellis v Lascelles [1883] UKLawRpCh 194; (1883) 24 Ch D 317
(CA).
[71] Gillick, above
n 30, at 182.
[72]
Ministry of Health, above n
18.
[73] Ian Kennedy and Andrew
Grubb Medical Law (3rd ed, Butterworths, London, 2000) at
1140.
[74] Hewer v Bryant
[1970] 1 QB 357 (CA).
[75]
Gillick, above n 30, at 171.
[76] At 184.
[77] At 186 and
189.
[78] Gillick, above n
30, at 171.
[79] At
169.
[80] Kennedy, above 57, at
94 and 100.
[81] Gillick
,above n 30, at 173.
[82] At
173.
[83] At
174.
[84] McDowell, above n 69,
at 81.
[85] Gillick, above
n 30, at 197.
[86] At
194.
[87] Elliston, above n 60,
at 30.
[88] Gillick,
above n 30, at 201.
[89] At
201.
[90] Kennedy, above n 57, at
94.
[91] Gillick, above n
30, at 204.
[92] Shiranikha
Herbert “Sexual Offences Act 1956 s6 Doctor Prescribing Contraception for
Girl Under 16 Without Parents’ Consent:
Whether Necessarily
Unlawful” [1986] Crim LR 113 at
114.
[93] Jessie Hill
“Medical Decision Making by and on Behalf of Adolescents: Reconsidering
First Principles” (2012) 15 J Health
Care L & Poly 37 at
62.
[94] Gillick, above n
30, at 174.
[95] AC v Manitoba
(Director of Child and Family Services) [2009] SCC 30, [2009] 2 SCR 181; and
Secretary of the Department of Health and Community Services v JWB and SMB
[1992] HCA 15; (1992) 175 CLR 218 (HCA)[Marion’s
Case].
[96] JSC v Wren
(1986) 49 Alta LR 289 (ABCA) at
[13].
[97] Re A (Capacity:
Refusal of Contraception) [2010] EWHC 1549 (Fam), [2011] 1 Fam
61.
[98] Gillick, above n
30, at 171, 189 and 201.
[99]
Re A, above n 97, at
64.
[100] At
64.
[101] R (Axon) v
Secretary of State for Health [2006] QB 239
(QB).
[102] At
[2].
[103] At[59] and
[69].
[104] At
[86]-[87].
[105] At
[90].
[106] Re L, above
n 14.
[107] At
812.
[108] Re P [1986] 1
FLR 272 (Fam). Compare; Re R (A Minor)(Wardship: Medical Treatment) [1992]
1 Fam 11 (CA) at 26.
[109]
Re R, above n 108; and Re W, above n
25.
[110] Nigel Lowe and
Satvinder Juss “Medical Treatment – Pragmatism and the Search for
Principle” (1993) 56 MLR
865.
[111] Re R, above n
108, at 24.
[112] At
22.
[113] Re W, above n
25.
[114] At
81.
[115] Grubb and Kenedy,
above n 73, at
984.
[116]McDowell, above n 69,
at 89.
[117] Re W, above
n 25, at 79.
[118] PN v BN
(2006) 25 FRNZ 536 (FC) at
[28].
[119] Re I FC
Wellington Fam-2004-085-1046 3 November
2005.
[120] ARB v KLB
[Guardianship Dispute] [2011] NZFLR 290
(FC).
[121] Re SPO FC
Wellington Fam-2004-085-1046, 3 November 2005 at
[25].
[122] Re J (An
Infant): B and B v Director General of Social Welfare [1996] NZCA 469; [1996] 2 NZLR 134
(CA).
[123] At 143 and
145.
[124] Re J (An
Infant): Director General of Social Welfare v B and B [1995] 3 NZLR 73 (HC)
at 86.
[125] At
87.
[126] Contraception,
Sterilisation and Abortion Amendment Act 1990, s 2(1).
[127] Contraception,
Sterilisation and Abortion Act, ss 3(2) and
3(6).
[128] Care of Children
Act 2004, s 38.
[129] J Beatson
“The Role of Statute in the Development of Common Law Doctrine”
(2001) 117 LQR 247 at 256; and Andrew Burrows “The Relationship between
Common Law and Statute and the Law of Obligations” (2012) 128 LQR 232 at
233-235.
[130] Friedman
Ross, above n 37.
[131]
Opinion 01HDC02915, above n 35.
[132] Health and Disability
Commissioner “ The Informed Consent Process and the Application of the
Code to Children” (6 August
1998)
HDC
<http://www.hdc.org.nz/education/presentations/the-informed- consent-process-and-the-application-of-the-code-to-children>
.
[133]
Except for s 38 which concerns
abortions.
[134] Care of
Children Act 2004, s13.
[135]
PDG Skegg “Capacity to Consent to Treatment” in PDG Skegg and Ron
Paterson (eds) Medical Law in New Zealand (Thomson Brookers, Wellington,
2006) at [6.3.1].
[136] A
consent, or refusal to consent, to any of the following, if given by a child of
or over the age of 16 years, has effect as if
the child were of full
age.
[137] Graham Rossiter
“Medical Treatment of Minors” [2006] NZLJ 10; Thomson, above n 12,
at 171; and Miller, above n 35, at 86.
[138] Re R, above n
108; and Re W, above n
25.
[139] Ministry of Health,
above n 18.
[140] JF Burrows
and RI Carter Statute Law in New Zealand (4th ed, LexisNexis, Wellington,
2009) at ch 8.
[141]
Auckland Healthcare Services Ltd v Liu HC Auckland M812/96, 11 July
1996.
[142]Auckland
Healthcare Services Ltd v T [1996] NZHC 2237; [1996] NZFLR 670 (HC).
[143] Robert Ludbrook and
Lex De Jong Care of Children in New Zealand: Analysis and Expert
Commentary (Brookers, Wellington, 2005) at
36.06.
[144] Burrows and
Carter, above n 140, at ch
7.
[145] Commerce Commission
v Fonterra Cooperative Group Ltd [2007] NZSC 36, [2007] 3 NZLR 767 at
[22].
[146] Section 3 (1)The
purpose of this Act is to—
(a)promote children’s welfare and best interests, and facilitate their development, by helping to ensure that appropriate arrangements are in place for their guardianship and care;
...
(2) (c)respects children’s views and, in certain cases, recognises
their consents (or refusals to consent) to medical
procedures
[147] Burrows and
Carter, above n 140, at ch
7.
[148] Hawthorn v Cox
[2007] NZHC 840; [2008] 1 NZLR 409(HC) at
[61].
[149] AC v
Manitoba, above n 95.
[150]
Ludbrook and De Jong , above n 143, at
[36.04].
[151] Re J,
above n 122, at 145.
[152] Care
of Children Act 2004, s 3(1)(a) and (b); and PN v BN, above n 118, at
[22].
[153] Care of Children
Act 2004, s 4 (6).
[154]New
South Wales Law Commission , above n 15, at
[6.26].
[155] Nothing in this
section affects an enactment or rule of law by or under which, in any
circumstances,—
(a)no consent or no express consent is necessary; or
(b)the consent of the child in addition to that of any other person is necessary; or
(c)subject to subsection (2), the consent of any other person instead of the
consent of the child is
sufficient.
[156] Erven
Warnink BV v J Townend & Sons (Hull) Ltd [1979] AC 731 (HL) at
743.
[157] Burrows and Carter,
above n 140, at ch
8.
[158]Ludbrook and De Jong,
above n 143, at [36.14]; Beatson, above n 129; and Burrows, above n
129.
[159] Section 13
(1).
[160] Section 13
(2).
[161] (1)If given by a
female child (of whatever age), the following have the same effect as if she
were of full age:
(a)a consent to the carrying out on her of any medical or surgical procedure for the purpose of terminating her pregnancy by a person professionally qualified to carry it out; and
(b)a refusal to consent to the carrying out on her of any procedure of that
kind.
[162]
Supplementary Order Paper 2004 (292) Care of Children Bill 2003
(54-3).
[163] English, above n
4.
[164] Misa, above n
4.
[165] Editorial, above n
4.
[166] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at
[6.85].
[167] Nicola Peart
“ Prevention and Termination of Life Before Birth” in PDG Skegg and
Ron Paterson (eds) Medical Law in New Zealand (Thomson Brookers,
Wellington, 2006) at
17.3.6.
[168] Contraception,
Sterilisation and Abortion Act, s
34.
[169] Crimes Act, s
187A(2).
[170] Re S
[1991] NZHC 2959; [1992] 1 NZLR 363 (HC).
[171]
New Zealand Bill of Rights Act, ss 4 and
6.
[172]Guardianship Act 1968,
s 25(3)(a).
[173] Sections 13
and 15.
[174] Health and
Disability Commissioner Act,
s20(1).
[175] Gillick,
above n 30, at 189.
[176]
McDowell, above n 69.
[177]
Skegg, “Presuming Competence to Consent,” above n
54.
[178] At
178.
[179] Where a consumer is
not competent to make an informed choice and give informed consent, and no
person entitled to consent on behalf
of the consumer is available, the provider
may provide services where -
a) It is in the best interests of the consumer;
and
b) Reasonable steps have been taken to ascertain the views of the
consumer; and
c) Either, -
i. If the consumer's views have been ascertained, and having regard to those views, the provider believes, on reasonable grounds, that the provision of the services is consistent with the informed choice the consumer would make if he or she were competent; or
ii. If the consumer's views have not been ascertained, the provider takes
into account the views of other suitable persons who are
interested in the
welfare of the consumer and available to advise the
provider.
[180] Opinion
01HDC02915, above n
34.
[181] Health and Disability
Commissioner, above n
132.
[182] Skegg,
“Capacity to Consent to Treatment,” above n 135, at
[6.3.1].
[183] Clause 5:
Nothing in this Code shall require a provider to act in breach of any duty or
obligation imposed by any enactment or prevents
a provider doing an act
authorised by any
enactment.
[184] Thomson, above
n 12, at 177; and McDowell, above n
69.
[185] Dickens and Cook,
above n 42, at 181.
[186]At
181.
[187] Children’s
Commissioner Act 2003, s 3(c) and
(d).
[188] H v F (1993)
10 FRNZ 486 (HC) at
499.
[189] Tavita v Minister
of Immigration [1993] NZCA 354; [1994] 2 NZLR 257
(CA).
[190] Kennedy, above n
57, at 63.
[191] Grubb and
Kennedy, above n 73, at
1076.
[192] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at
[6.62].
[193] Kennedy, above n
57, at 61.
[194] Melissa Prober
“Please Don’t Tell My Parents: The Validity of School Policies
Mandating Parental Notification of a Student’s
Pregnancy” (2005) 71
Brook L Rev 557 at 580.
[195]
Sarah Kerkin “Disclosing Children’s Health Information – A
Legal and Ethical Framework” ( 6 August 1998)
Privacy Commissioner
<www.privacy.org.nz/disclosing-children-s-health-information-a-legal-and-ethical-framework/>.
[196]
Ministry of Health, above n 18, at
26.
[197] Health Information
Privacy Code 1994, cl 3.
[198]
Privacy Commissioner “ Health Information Privacy Fact Sheet 3: Disclosure
of Health Information” (2011)
<http://privacy.org.nz/health-information-privacy-fact-sheet-3-disclosure-of-health-information-the-basics/?highlight=minor%20health%20confidentiality>
.
[199]
Privacy Commissioner “Health Information Privacy Code 1994: Incorporating
amendments and including revised commentary”
(December 2008)
<http://privacy.org.nz/assets/Files/Codes-of-Practice-materials/HIPC-1994-incl.-amendments-revised-commentary.pdf>
.
[200]
Rule 11(4)(b).
[201] Privacy
Commissioner “ Health Information Privacy Fact Sheet 4: Dealing with
Requests for Health Information” (2011)
<
http://privacy.org.nz/health-information-privacy-fact-sheet-4-dealing-with-requests-for-health
information/?highlight=minor%20health%
20confidentiality>.
[202]Ministry of Health, above
n 18.
[203] Kennedy,
above n 57, at 65.
[204]
Dickens and Cook , above n 42, at
183.
[205] Kennedy, above n 57,
at 115.
[206] R(Axon) v
Secretary of State for Health, above n
101.
[207] Kerkin, above n
195.
[208] Marion’s
Case, above n 95.
[209]
Minors (Property and Contracts) Act 1970 (NSW),
s49.
[210] New South Wales Law
Commission, above n 15, at
[6.92].
[211] Lee, above n 11,
at 301.
[212] Contraception,
Sterilisation and Abortion Amendment Act, s2(1); and Care of Children Act s
36(1).
[213] McDowell, above n
69, at 81.
[214] Skegg,
“Capacity to Consent to Treatment,” above n 135.
[215] Dickens and Cook, above
n 42, at 182.
[216] Family
Planning, above n 7.
[217]
Medical Council of New Zealand “Information, Choice of Treatment and
Informed Consent” (March 2011) Medical Council of
New Zealand
www.mcnz.org.nz/assets/New-and-Publications/Statements/Informed-choice-of-treatment-and-informed-consent.pdf
at [28].
[218] At
[28].
[219] Re F (Mental
Patient: Sterilisation) [1991] UKHL 1; [1990] 2 AC 1
(HL).
[220] Bpac
“Identifying Young Adolescents Who are Sexually Active” (April 2011)
Contraception in Early Adolescence
<www.bpac.org.nz/magazine/2011/april/contraception.asp>.
[221]
Miller, above n 35.
[222]
Burrows and Carter, above n 140, at ch
16.
[223] Webb v Swanson
[2013] NZFC 6792 at [12].
[224] Gillick, above n
30.
[225] Webb v Swanson
[2013] NZFC 6792 at
[12].
[226] Thomson, above n
13, at 148.
[227] Ministry of
Health, above n 18.
[228] WR
Atkin “Parents and Children: Mrs Gillick in the House of Lords”
[1986] NZLJ 90 at 100.
[229] Gillick, above n 30, at 186, per Lord Scarman.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZPubIntLawJl/2014/19.html