Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Yearbook of New Zealand Jurisprudence |
Last Updated: 24 April 2015
Forbidding Dwarf Tossing: Defending Dignity or
Discrimination Based on Size?
Dr Julia Davis*
i. intrOdUctiOn
In the last half of the twentieth century legislators began to use the idea
of human dignity to supplement the traditional concepts
of harm and autonomy as
the source of principled controls over the state’s entitlement to forbid
conduct on the pain of criminal
punishment. More recently, the concept of
dignity has been expressly relied upon by legislators to justify imposing
criminal sanctions
on those who organise dwarf tossing contests. This paper
examines the relative merits of the three suggested candidates for keeping
the
criminal law within principled boundaries, namely, the harm principle, the
principle of autonomy, and the idea of human dignity.
It presents a model of
criminal wrongdoing that is based on protecting not only our welfare and our
autonomy but also our desire
to be respected by others as persons of equal
dignity, worth and value. It concludes by suggesting that our primary allegiance
to
the principle that all human beings are equal in dignity will sometimes
require us to refrain from criminalising certain controversial
kinds of conduct
like dwarf tossing that may at first glance appear to be supremely
undignified.
ii. the chaLLenge OF dwarF tOSSing
An important task facing any community is to find a source of principled
moral limits that can be used to control the extent of the
criminal law. This
search is frustrated by the fact that the concept of wrongdoing, just like the
contested concept of a crime itself,
is open and empty of factual content. The
ordinary definitions of wrongdoing, as conduct that deviates from a rule,
standard or norm
of conduct that is thought to be right, and of a crime as
‘a legal wrong that can be followed by criminal proceedings which
may
result in punishment’1 both leave undone the hard work of
identifying in precise factual terms the conduct that ought to be forbidden by
the criminal law
and providing acceptable reasons why it is thought to be right
to punish offenders who are responsible for that conduct.
* Faculty of Law, University of Tasmania.
1 Williams G, Textbook of Criminal Law (1983) 27-28.
Legislators who have found that the meaning of these terms does not yield a universally accepted test for recognising criminal wrongdoing have sought assistance from other sources including religious teachings, moral and legal philosophy and criminology. However, despite our continuing community conversations about crime, wrongdoing and punishment, we have not agreed upon a clear test that can neatly divide the conduct that we feel compelled to act against from the conduct that we feel we must tolerate or deal with in other ways. Whenever a likely candidate is put forward by one camp, opposition from another camp points out its weaknesses. Consequently, legislators, whose allegiance to John Stuart Mill’s famous ‘harm principle’ is challenged by the
‘autonomy principle’ derived from Kantian ethics, adopt
compromises that open the law up to criticism that it is illogical,
inconsistent, and unprincipled. Lawyers and legal theorists, aware of the pull
of opposing values, respond in different ways: some
hail the collapse of the
harm principle and call for a new critical principle;2 some smuggle
aspects of one theory into another to bolster its perceived shortcomings;3
others craft hybrid theories that use different guiding principles at
different stages of the criminal justice process;4 while sceptics
argue that the law is hopelessly ambiguous, fatally contradictory and
fundamentally incapable of delivering justice.5
Fortunately, we are often able to agree upon the content of the criminal law;
the core crimes sometimes classified as mala in se or evil in themselves,
like murder, rape, theft and wounding, are commonly viewed by most members of
the community both as morally
wrong and as suitable objects of criminal
sanctions. By contrast, those kinds of conduct that are viewed as mala
prohibita or regulatory crimes, which occur at the penumbra of the criminal
law, do cause problems both for legislators and for citizens. In
these cases
where we disagree, our need for a critical principle that can assist us in
deciding upon the moral limits of the criminal
law is thrown into high relief.
One such challenging case is the ‘sport’ of dwarf tossing, a form of
entertainment that
was invented in Australia in the nineteen eighties, and which
spread rapidly to other parts of the world. Dwarf tossing is a contest
of
strength usually held in discotheques and bars, which rewards the person who is
able to throw a willing and suitably protected
dwarf the furthest onto a padded
landing stage.
2 Harcourt, BE, ‘The Collapse of the Harm Principle’ (1999) 90 JCrimL&Criminology
109.
3 For example, Joel Feinberg adopts an extended normative definition of harm as an indefensible and wrongful setback to interest, done with fault, and in violation of a person’s rights in The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Volume 1, Harm to Others (1984) 105-06,
36, 214-215, 186 and Harmless Wrongdoing (1988) 26.
4 See, for example, Hart HLA, Punishment and Responsibility (1984).
5 Norrie, A, Crime, Reason and History (1993) ‘Simulacra of
Morality? Beyond the Ideal/ Actual Antinomies of Criminal Justice’ in Duff
RA (ed.) Philosophy and the Criminal Law (1998) 101; and Punishment,
Responsibility and Justice: A Relational Critique (2000).
Another variant, dwarf bowling, involves launching a helmeted dwarf who is
strapped to a skateboard down a bowling alley; the winner
is the contestant who
knocks down the most pins.
At about the same time that dwarf tossing started to grow in popularity,
legislators and legal philosophers began to use the idea
of human dignity to
supplement, and at times to displace, a reliance on the traditional concepts of
harm and autonomy as the source
of principled controls over the state’s
entitlement to forbid conduct on the pain of criminal punishment. Responding to
the
protests of citizens who were outraged by the undignified spectacle of dwarf
tossing contests and who claimed that such events are
disgusting, demeaning and
objectify and ridicule little people, legislators in France and the USA
expressly relied upon the notion
of human dignity to justify imposing criminal
sanctions on those who organise dwarf tossing contests. The mayor of New York,
Mario
Cuomo, signed into law a bill prohibiting both forms of dwarf sports in
1990, saying that he did:
... not lightly impose limits on the activities of consenting participants.
But balancing all the interests affected, I am persuaded
that approval of this
bill respects basic human dignity and protects the safety and self respect of
the special people who are the
subject of this strange diversion.
6
In France, the Conseil d’État, affirming that respect for human dignity is one
of the constituents of public order, upheld a law forbidding dwarf tossing in
1995 and refused to allow dwarfs to compromise their dignity by allowing
themselves to be used as mere projectiles or be treated in
the same way as
inanimate pieces of sporting equipment.7 In 2002 this action
inspired a French citizen, Manuel Wackenheim, who earned his living by
participating in dwarf tossing contests,
to attempt to overturn the legislation
by taking his case against France to the UN Human Rights Committee.8
He argued that the French law was an unlawful, paternalistic act of
discrimination based on his size and maintained that the ban infringed
his
autonomy and his right to pursue
6 Abramovsky, A, ‘Bias Crime: A Call for Alternative Responses’ (1992) 19 FordhamUrbanLJ
875, 902, n 229.
7 Conseil d’État (October 27, 1995) req nos (Commune de Morsang-sur-Orge) and 143-578 (Ville d’Aix-en-Provence).
8 The French dwarf, who lost before the Conseil d’État, supra n 7, took his case to the UN Human Rights Committee on the grounds that the French regulations banning the organisation of dwarf throwing contests violated his rights under the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. The case was not successful: Mr Manuel Wackenheim v France Communication No 854/1999, UN Doc CCPR/C/75/D/8541999 (13 November 1996), UN Doc A/57/40 at 179 (2002) Decision of the Human Rights Committee, 75th Session, delivered
26 September 2002.
employment in a difficult job market.9 According to Mr Wackenheim,
the bans denied his human dignity, which he equated with having employment and
professional status. The
UN Human Rights Committee upheld the validity of the
ban on dwarf-tossing, claiming that it was necessary to protect public order
and
that notion of upholding human dignity was a valid basis for the laws.
I will argue in this paper that while the state is entitled to regulate the
conditions under which dwarfs can be employed in these
contests, it is not
entitled to use the criminal law to punish those who organise safe, regulated
dwarf throwing events. This conclusion
is based on a model of criminal
wrongdoing that aims to give a place to each of the three important principles
that have been suggested
as candidates for keeping the criminal law within
principled boundaries, namely, the harm principle, the principle of autonomy,
and
the idea of respecting human dignity. The recent emergence of the notion of
human dignity and its use in justifying the imposition
of criminal sanctions on
certain kinds of conduct generally thought to be harmless expressions of
personal autonomy, forces us once
again to think about the nature of the good
life for human beings, to clarify the role that the criminal law should play in
securing
that vision and to reconsider the relative value that the state should
place on our welfare and autonomy interests and our shared
desire to be
respected by others as persons of equal dignity and worth. The challenge posed
by dwarf tossing contests offers us a
useful test case to analyse the effects of
each of these different approaches to setting the moral boundaries of the
criminal law.
I begin in the next section by examining the relative merits of the harm
principle, the principle of autonomy, and the idea of human
dignity in order to
see how they might be used as the basis for our decisions to criminalise
conduct. The third section presents
an account of a crime as conduct that
threatens the foundations of the good life for human beings living together as a
community.
I suggest that, just like the good life which it mirrors and
protects, a crime contains two distinct dimensions; a factual dimension
that
focuses on preventing setbacks to our welfare and our autonomy, and a normative
dimension that is informed by the value that
we place on being respected
9 See supra n 8. This case has attracted the following comments: Baber HE, ‘The Ethics of Dwarf Tossing’ (1989) FallInt’lJAppliedPhil 1; Becker L, ‘Crimes Against Autonomy’ (1999) 40 William&MaryLR 959, 971; Beyleveld D & Brownsword R, Human Dignity in Bioethics and Biolaw (2001) 25-27; Brownsword R ‘Bioethics Today, Bioethics Tomorrow: Stem Cell Research and the Dignitarian Alliance’ (2003) 17 NotreDameJLEthics&PubPol icy 15; Friedman GS & Whitman JQ, ‘The European Transformation of Harassment Law: Discrimination Versus Dignity’ (2003) 9 ColumbiaJEurL 241; McGee RW, ‘If Dwarf Tossing is Outlawed, Only Outlaws will Toss Dwarfs: Is Dwarf Tossing a Victimless Crime?’ (1993)
38 AmerJJuris 335; and Owen DG, ‘Products Liability: Category
Liability: Product Outlaws’ (2000) 10 KansasJL&PubPolicy
126.
by others as an equal. I argue that our criminal law contains a distinctive
conception of justice that is based on our vision of ourselves
as equals in
dignity, worth and value, and which imposes a duty on each of us to respect
others by treating their interests in welfare
and autonomy as carrying a value
that is equal to our own. Under this ‘Good Life Model’ of the
criminal law, we cannot
justify criminalising any conduct unless it breaches
both the harm principle, which sets the factual boundaries of the criminal law,
and the equal dignity principle, which provides the criminal law with its moral
heart. The paper concludes by explaining why our
allegiance to the principle
that all human beings should be respected as persons of equal dignity will
sometimes lead to an apparent
paradox that requires us to refrain from
criminalising certain controversial kinds of conduct – like the practice
of dwarf
tossing – that may appear to many in the community to be
supremely undignified.
iii. the Search FOr the mOraL LimitS OF the criminaL Law
The Harm Principle
John Stuart Mill argued that the state should be entitled to restrict our
liberty only when our conduct risks doing harm to others.10 This
‘very simple’ principle has strong initial appeal because the
essentially factual notion of harm-doing, as conduct
that makes someone or
something worse off, appears to provide a straightforward test that can give
content to the moral, but factually
empty, concepts of wrongdoing and crime.
Furthermore, the utilitarian concern with harm and human welfare sits well with
the state’s
duty to govern for the health, safety and wellbeing of its
citizens. However, three problems arise when we put the notion of harm
into
place as the critical principle that determines the contours of the criminal
law.
The first problem is that a harm based test pushes the criminal law too far.
It does not tell us how to distinguish criminal conduct
from the conduct that we
think would be better dealt with by the civil law. More importantly, the harm
principle would extend the
reach of the criminal law far beyond its current
boundaries because, although it is relatively easy to identify, harm is
ubiquitous.
If we track the consequences far enough, almost any conduct can lead
to harm and so theoretically attract the criminal sanction.
Certainly, the harm
principle’s perceived strength (in liberal eyes at least) in ruling out
the criminalisation of conduct
that is essentially objected to on the grounds of
offence or moralism has been weakened by politicians who use ‘broken
windows’
arguments to
10 Mill JS, On Liberty and Other Essays (1998) 13-14.
extend the criminal law by finding remote harms in conduct traditionally
considered to be harmless to others like prostitution, begging,
selling alcohol,
using drugs, and engaging in homosexual activity.11
In the case of dwarf throwing, it has been argued by dwarfs who wish to
participate in the contests, that provided proper safety matters
are observed,
the activity is not dangerous and is certainly less dangerous that many kinds of
dwarf wrestling exhibitions, which
are not forbidden.12 If we compare
the sport with boxing, rugby or Australian Rules football where the risk of harm
cannot be eliminated because of the
nature of the games, regulated dwarf tossing
does not appear to be harmful enough to forbid. If we compare it with ordinary
recreational
pursuits like sky-diving and gliding, where we allow individuals to
risk their health and their welfare and (very often) death itself,
it seems that
we should allow the dwarfs a similar choice. However, some commentators like HE
Baber, who accept that the events can
be safely carried out without harming the
participants, claim that dwarf tossing contests are wrong and should be banned
under the
harm principle on the grounds that they cause remote harms to
‘unwilling non-participants, particularly other little
people.’13 These attempts to use the harm principle to justify
forbidding dwarf tossing contests reveal the limits of the harm principle and
our need either for a remoteness test for causing harm or for some other morally
acceptable source of limits.
The next problem arises because equating harm-doing with wrongdoing (and
reducing the moral problem to a purely factual question)
leaves out something
important; specifically, it does not take account of the characteristic attitude
of contempt for the value of
others that we read into conduct commonly seen as
criminal. To solve this problem Jerome Hall posited the existence of a special
kind of ‘penal’, ‘social’, or ‘criminal’
harm ‘the essential determination of which is
the moral culpability of the
actor,’14 and Joel Feinberg adopted an extended normative
definition of ‘harm’ that includes notions of fault, moral
wrongdoing
and the idea of violations of rights.15 In the case of
dwarf tossing this extension does not lead us to criminalise those who organise
dwarf tossing
11 See Harcourt BE, ‘The Collapse of the Harm Principle’ (1999) 90 JCrimL&Criminology
109; and Feinberg J, ‘Harm to Others - A Rejoinder’ (1986) 5 CrimJusticeEthics 27.
12 Such precautions may include: the wearing of helmets, the use of padding, a requirement for insurance coverage, a requirement for up to date medical certificates from recognised orthopaedic specialists, and a stipulation that no person who is drunk may be allowed to participate in the throwing. See also McGee RW, ‘If Dwarf Tossing is Outlawed, Only Outlaws will Toss Dwarfs: Is Dwarf Tossing a Victimless Crime?’ (1993) 38 AmerJJuris
335.
13 Baber HE, ‘The Ethics of Dwarf Tossing’ [1989] FallInt’lJAppliedPhil 1.
14 Hall J, General Principles of Criminal Law 2nd Ed (1960) 215 & 242.
15 See Feinberg, supra n 3.
contests because, if the dwarfs are consenting, there does not appear to be
any violation of their rights or any special fault or
culpability associated
with the action that would lead us to think that the conduct is intrinsically
criminal or morally wrong.
Unfortunately, however, these definitional manoeuvres lead to a third problem
– the struggle over the meaning of harm. Once the stronger moral notions
of culpability and wrongdoing are added into these extended definitions of
‘harm’, they overpower it and harm’s usefulness as a
factual test is lost. In a frustrating twist, these tactics,
which were designed
to enhance harm’s limiting function, destroy its original meaning and we
are forced back to the debates
about the nature of moral wrongdoing that divided
us in the first place. Adopting a definition of a crime as the culpable choice
to harm another may improve upon our understanding of a crime as mere
harm-doing, but it means that the harm principle ceases to
be the critical
principle that we had hoped for. So, although the concept of harm does appear to
offer a usefully factual source
of limits on the criminal law, its own
limitations and our struggles over its meaning and role have led philosophers
and lawyers
to put forward the concept of autonomy as a necessary supplement to
the harm principle.
The Autonomy Principle
Immanuel Kant’s theory of autonomy and treating persons as ends in
themselves has been very influential in Anglo-American justifications
of
punishment. However, arguments over the relative importance of human welfare and
autonomy have persisted, not only between consequentialists
and deontologists,
but also between unaligned theorists who attempt to find a place for both the
harm principle and the autonomy
principle in the criminal law. Furthermore,
recent debates over autonomy’s role have moved away from Kant’s
account,
which grants us equal moral worth insofar as we are rational and
autonomous, in favour of a more factual account of autonomy’s
significance. Autonomy, defined as the exercise of control over the conduct of
one’s own life by defining, choosing and pursuing
a good life on
one’s own terms (regardless of whether those decisions are based in
morality or in rationality)16 is seen simply as another object of
desire that may deserve legal protection. So conceived, it is no longer the key
moral attribute
justifying our duties to others. Theorists following this
approach disagree not only over the meaning of autonomy and its relation
to the
harm principle and the matter of human welfare, but also over the priority that
these aspects should have in structuring the
criminal law.
16 On Joseph Raz’s account ‘a man is autonomous even if he chooses the bad.’ Raz J, The
Morality of Freedom (1986) 411.
Andrew Ashworth and Nicola Lacey argue that autonomy and welfare represent
competing values.17 They suggest that the criminal law does not (and
cannot) rank one consistently over the other and argue that we must negotiate
compromises
between the two on a case by case basis.18 By contrast,
John Gardner and Joseph Raz maintain that autonomy as the ‘key ideal of
human well-being for our age’ is
the true source of the value that we
place on our welfare interests.19 However, when defining autonomy,
they also give primacy to the notion of capacity or functioning, and they
resolve the dilemma over
autonomy’s relationship to the concept of harm by
classing as harmful only the adverse effects upon welfare that will reduce
the
prospective exercise of a person’s autonomy.20 Like Feinberg,
who also links interferences with autonomy to the harm principle, Gardner and
Raz agree that conduct causing only transitory
pain, disfigurement, grief and
distress, which are disliked states that ‘come to us, are suffered for a
time, and then go,
leaving us whole and undamaged as we were
before’21 cannot count either as harmful or as an interference
with autonomy.
The insistence that adverse effects upon welfare are harmful only when they
impair future capacity for chosen action seems not only
to put an artificial
limit upon the meaning of harm but also to underrate the importance that
we
17 Lacey N, State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values (1988) 103-105;
and Ashworth A, Principles of Criminal Law 2nd Ed (1996) 24.
18 Ashworth A, Principles of Criminal Law 4th Ed (2003) 323-329. Lacey suggests in State Punishment, supra n 17 at 117, that ‘it would be foolish to imagine that one always acts as an absolute constraint on the pursuit of the other’. She argues that the two are incommensurable political values and points out that trade-offs between the two must be made when a community considers both the aim and the distribution of punishment. Ibid, 180, 187. More recently, however, Lacey has argued that the values of autonomy and welfare are not necessarily in opposition: Unspeakable Subjects (1998) 52.
19 Gardner J, ‘On the General Part of the Criminal Law’ in Duff RA (ed) Philosophy and the Criminal Law (1998) 205, 242-243. See also Raz J, ‘Autonomy, Toleration and the Harm Principle’ in Gavison R (ed.) Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy (1987) 313, 327-
320, and The Morality of Freedom (1986) 413-414.
20 Joseph Raz argues that harm has a ‘forward looking aspect’ that is linked directly to autonomy and that we can classify as harmful therefore only those effects that ‘affect options or projects’ either by depriving ‘a person of opportunities or of the ability to use them’ or by reducing
‘his ability to act in ways that he might desire.’ Raz, The Morality of Freedom, supra n 19 at 413-414. John Gardner also emphasises that harm is ‘not the pain or lost limb or shock in itself’ but is instead the consequent ‘attenuation of capacity or opportunity for action, reducing the range of alternative actions and activities that are available to the person who is harmed.’ Gardner J, ‘On the General Part of the Criminal Law’ in Duff RA (ed.) Philosophy and the Criminal Law (1998) 205, 243.
21 Feinberg, Harm to Others, supra n 3 at 45. AP Simester and
Andrew von Hirsch also limit the scope of harm to those effects that impair a
person’s ‘opportunities
to engage in worthwhile activities and
relationships and to pursue valuable, self-chosen goals’ in Simester AP
& von Hirsch
A, ‘Rethinking the Offense Principle’ (2002) 8
LegalTheory 269, 281.
place on our welfare. We do appear to value an intact, unblemished body and
the absence of pain, grief and distress as important aspects
of the existence
that we aim to secure for ourselves, and, whether these effects disable us from
action or not, we do regard ourselves
as being worse off or harmed if we are
blighted in such ways even if it is only for a short time.
Another troubling example is the case of a ‘harmless rape’,
described by John Gardner and Stephen Shute, where an unconscious
victim is
secretly violated by another without any physical damage resulting and where the
event is never discovered.22 Gardner and Shute classify it as
harmless because they insist that harm must have a prospective dimension that
will affect the victim’s
future exercise of her autonomy. Again, it is
difficult to agree with their assertion that the rape does no harm simply
because the
victim’s future capacity for autonomy is unaffected. The
victim’s control over access to her body was diminished, and
I suggest
that, viewed objectively, this factual setback to her opportunity to exercise
her autonomy must be seen as making her worse
off and therefore be classified as
harmful.23
Giving autonomy a controlling role within the harm principle also leads to a
second set of problems that arise partly because our
welfare interests and our
autonomy interests often conflict and partly because giving primacy to one over
the other unbalances the
law by leaving out something we value. Our welfare
interests, defined as comprising all the things both internal and external to
the person that are important for human existence, cover what we might call the
passive aspects of wellbeing. Our interests in autonomy comprise the
active aspects of our wellbeing or, as Mill called it, well-doing.24
Even though our desires to improve our welfare and to pursue our autonomy
may sometimes conflict, reinforcing links do exist between
the two; an adequate
welfare base lays the foundation for the exercise of our autonomy and exercising
our autonomy can often improve
our welfare. However, if one of these aspects is
missing, no improvement or increase in the other can make up the loss. The
pampered
slave, whose welfare interests are completely satisfied, but whose
entitlement to the free exercise of his will is denied, cannot
be said
to
22 Gardner J & Shute S, ‘The Wrongness of Rape’ in Horder J (ed.) Oxford Essays in
Jurisprudence 4th Series (2000) 193.
23 The criminal law exists not simply to respond to subjectively experienced wrongs or the subjectively experienced harms that flow from those wrongs, but to make an objective, public, assessment of conduct. Criminal law is the external view, and consequently we are entitled to make external assessments of harm just as Gardner and Shute go on to make an external assessment of wrongdoing in this case.
24 John Stuart Mill saw the good life as composed of
‘well-being’ and ‘well-doing’: see On Liberty,
supra n 10 at 84. The useful notions of ‘passive well-being’ and
‘active well-being’ used by John Gardner
neatly match Mill’s
two elements: see Gardner J, ‘On the General Part of the Criminal
Law’ supra n 19.
live well. Equally, the woman, whose entitlement to exercise her autonomy is
guaranteed, but whose living conditions of deprivation
and poverty mean that her
choices are limited to deciding which of her children gets enough to eat, does
not have a good life.25
If we view welfare and autonomy as incommensurable elements of the good life
and as equally worthy of the law’s protection,
then neither can take
priority in shaping the criminal law. Because we do commonly see ourselves as
worse off in a factual sense
when these interests are set back, it follows that
conduct that sets backs either our welfare or our autonomy could be covered by
the harm principle. However, while this move improves our theory of harm, and
settles the relationship between harm, welfare and
autonomy (in its modern
factual sense), it does not bring us any closer to resolving the other problems
that arise if the harm principle
sets the limits of the criminal law. Even in
its modified form, it still fails to capture the message about the value of
others that
we object to in conduct that is commonly called criminal, and if any
conduct that risks a setback either to another’s autonomy
interests or to
their welfare interests qualifies as harmful, the boundaries of the criminal law
would extend even further than they
do now.
Despite these problems associated with the concept of autonomy, it clear that
the test case of dwarf tossing would not be a fit subject
for the criminal
sanction if the autonomy principle alone were to be used to set the boundaries
of the criminal law. In no case are
dwarfs forced to participate, and in fact
many dwarf participants claim that they enjoy the sensation of flying through
the air and
that they relish the fact that they are the centre of attention, not
only while the event takes place, but afterwards when patrons
socialise with
each other and with the participants.26 Furthermore, there appears
to be no likelihood that participating in such events would impair the
dwarfs’ capacity for the future
exercise of their autonomy. One solution
to the theoretical dilemmas might be to return to Kant’s account of our
moral worth
as being grounded in our rationality and our capacity to will that
our maxims become universal law. Unfortunately, this vision of
autonomy’s
special moral significance is open to the objection that it may lead us to
ignore non-human animals and any non-rational
or incapacitated humans,27
and so, to salvage what is valuable in Kant’s account of our moral
worth, we must turn to the idea that has dominated modern
legal thinking and
examine the role that human dignity can play in the criminal law.
25 Partha Dasgupta explains how destitution creates both physical pain as well as the moral pain of having to make tragic choices over the allocation of food and health care in Human Well-being and the Natural Environment (2001) 37.
26 See references in n 9 supra.
27 Hursthouse R, Ethics, Humans and Other Animals (2000).
Human Dignity
The starting point for any discussion of human dignity is Immanuel
Kant’s famous statement in The Metaphysics of Morals:
Every human being has a legitimate claim to respect from his fellow human beings and is in turn bound to respect every other. Humanity itself is a dignity; for a human being cannot be used merely as a means by any human being
... but must always be used at the same time as an end. It is just in this
that his dignity (personality) consists, by which he raises
himself above all
other beings in the world that are not human beings and yet can be used, and so
over all things. But just as he
cannot give himself away for any price (this
would conflict with his duty of self-esteem), so neither can he act contrary to
the
equally necessary self-esteem of others, as human beings, that is, he is
under obligation to acknowledge, in a practical way, the
dignity of humanity in
every other human being. Hence there rests on him a duty regarding the respect
that must be shown to every
other human being.28
After World War II the Kantian idea that state authorities have a fundamental
duty to respect the equal dignity of all human beings
began to feature in both
international human rights law and the domestic constitutions of states like
Germany and Israel.29 Even in France and the USA where there is no
express legislative recognition of human dignity (but where the concept of
equality has
strong constitutional support), the idea has been used to limit the
law right through the criminal justice process. In addition to
upholding laws
banning dwarf tossing events,30 courts have struck down laws
criminalising homosexual
28 Kant I, The Metaphysics of Morals (originally published in 1797) Mary Gregor (trans) (1996)
209, see also 434-435.
29 See, Englard I, ‘Human Dignity: From Antiquity to Modern Israel’s Constitutional Framework’ (2000) 21 CardozoLR 1903; Hörnle T, ‘Offensive Behaviour and German Penal Law’ (2001) 5 BuffaloCrimLR 255; Resnick J & Suk JC, ‘Adding Insult to Injury: Questioning the Role of Dignity in Conceptions of Sovereignty’ (2003) 55 StanfordLR
1921. Courts in both Israel and Germany are empowered to strike down legislation that
conflicts with this duty.
30 See supra ns 7 and 8.
sodomy,31 outlawed punishments like castration,32
prohibited routine strip searches33 and forbidden race or
gender based discrimination in jury selection,34 all on the grounds
that the law must recognise our equal dignity.
In the case of dwarf tossing contests, the most commonly expressed objection
relates to the issue of human dignity. Because there
is no equal status or
reciprocity between participants as there is in harmful or risky sports like
boxing, rugby or Australian football
(where each participant undertakes the same
risk and engages in the same conduct) the throwing of the dwarfs appears to be
demeaning
of the human projectiles, who in these contests are equated to the
status of inanimate shot-puts or javelins. The dwarfs also shoulder
an unequal
risk of harm by comparison with those who launch them and they do not have an
equal entitlement to toss the other participants
as they themselves are tossed.
On the other hand, there are many human activities that may be thought of as
undignified that do not
attract the sanctions of the criminal law. If we compare
the case with those where we allow men and women to perform together in
peep
shows for the titillation of paying customers, we may well conclude that it is
unreasonably discriminatory to refuse the dwarf
an opportunity to engage in what
may be less demeaning employment.
The emphasis on the special moral dignity of persons traces back to Aristotle
and Cicero35 and features in the theories of utilitarians like Mill
and Bentham as well as deontologists like Kant and Hegel.36 This
solid core of agreement
31 In Lawrence v Texas [2003] USSC 4776; 123 S Ct 2472 (2003) the US Supreme Court declared unconstitutional a Texas law forbidding homosexual sodomy on the grounds that by criminalising only homosexual sodomy and unjustifiably creating a class of ‘second-class citizens’, the Texas legislature had failed in its duty to respect equally the dignity of those persons subject to the law.
32 See Meir Dan-Cohen’s discussion of State v Braxton 326 SE 2d 410 (SC 1985), where the appellate court withdrew the option that the lower court had given defendants between choosing 30 years imprisonment or being surgically castrated: Dan-Cohen M, ‘Basic Values and the Criminal’s State of Mind’ (2000) 88 CalLR 759, text accompanying n 13, reprinted as the chapter on ‘Defending Dignity’ in Dan-Cohen M, Harmful Thoughts (2002).
33 See the ruling by the US District Court for the Eastern District of New York in Augustin v Jablonsky 99-CV-3126 (DRH) (ARL) 2001 US Dist LEXIS 10276 forbidding routine strip searches upon arrest for minor offences.
34 The US Supreme Court prohibited discrimination on the basis of race or gender in jury selection in: Batson v Kentucky [1986] USSC 89; 476 US 79, 90 L Ed 2d 69 (1986) on grounds of gender; and J.E.B. v Alabama ex rel T.B. [1994] USSC 6; 511 US 127, 114 L Ed 2d 89 (1994) on grounds of race.
35 Wright RW, ‘The Principles of Justice’ (2000) 75 NotreDameLR 1859. Nicola Lacey, in State Punishment, supra n 17 at 144-148, traces the liberal themes of equality and ‘taking persons seriously as moral agents worthy of equal respect and concern’ from Kant, Bentham and Mill, to the work of HLA Hart, Ronald Dworkin, John Rawls and Peter Singer.
36 See Mill’s discussion of Bentham’s famous aphorism
‘Each is to count for one and no-one more than one’
in On
Liberty, supra n 10 at 198-199; and Kant I, The Metaphysics of Morals
supra n 28 at 434-435.
between philosophers whose views are often opposed suggests that the equal
dignity principle may be well suited to the task of justifying
principled limits
on the criminal law. However, before we can give dignity this crucial role, we
must resolve three difficulties
emerging from the dignity jurisprudence that
cloud its meaning, use and significance.
The first problem is the blurring of the boundaries between dignity and harm.
Just as legal philosophers have smuggled moral elements
into their accounts of
harm, so have lawyers fused harm with dignity as American courts use the idea of
‘dignitary harms’
to justify overturning legislation.
‘Dignitary’ or ‘expressive’ harms are said to be imposed
on individuals
by the improper messages about individual value that state laws
express; they result from the attitudes expressed through government
actions
rather than the material consequences they cause.37 These harms are a
fiction designed to give legal standing to people who are not themselves
threatened by the impugned laws, but who,
because they wish to overturn them,
must prove injury to comply with rules governing procedure. This usage should be
resisted because
the source of these complaints is located in the normative
realm of value and not in the factual world of welfare or autonomy interests.
They tell us nothing new about harm. Rather, they remind us that we see
ourselves as being equal in dignity and that we feel morally
outraged when the
law does not do justice to that value.
The second problem arises because dignity has two senses. Dignity in the
first sense refers to the inherent worth that attaches to
all human beings
simply because they are human beings – and in our times this worth is seen
as equal worth. In its second sense
dignity refers to a state of existence or
conduct that is characterised by the absence of perceived indignity, humiliation
or degradation.
It is linked to our feelings, experiential wellbeing and
self-esteem. However, because dignity is not simply the opposite of perceived
indignity, there is an asymmetry between the two senses that creates problems in
legal debates. Dignity as equal worth is a normative
quality. It exists in the
moral sphere and remains untouched by events or experience; we cannot differ in
equality or have more or
less of it. Conversely, dignity in the second sense is
a quantitative and factual matter; we can progressively lose our dignity as
more
and more indignities are heaped upon us. Dignity in this factual sense cannot
advance our search for moral limits. If we want
protection from perceived
indignities we can simply appeal to the harm principle that defends our welfare
and autonomy, but this
kind of dignity is too weak to do the moral
37 Pildes RH & Niemi RG, ‘Expressive Harms, “Bizarre Districts”, and Voting Rights’ (1993)
92 MichLR 483, 506-507. See also Anderson ES & Pildes RH, ‘Expressive Theories of
Law: A General Restatement’ (2000) 148 UPennLR 1503.
work of justifying the duties to others that the criminal law imposes upon us.38
However, dignity in its normative sense offers more hope, precisely because
it focuses upon the moral worth of human beings and because
it is now welded to
the powerful idea of equality.
The third problem casting doubt on dignity’s usefulness as a limiting
principle arises because dignity based arguments work
both ways. This is
illustrated by the French dwarf tossing case, France v Wackenheim,39
where both parties invoked the notion of human dignity to justify opposing
arguments. France (using dignity in the second sense),
argued that using human
beings as projectiles creates an undignified public spectacle. Mr Wackenheim,
whose welfare and autonomy
interests were not harmed by his participation,
claimed that dignity consists in having a job and being treated without
discrimination
based on size (thereby using both senses). This case suggests
that, on its own, the concept of human dignity does not give us enough
guidance.
Dignity is not an open concept like the notion of wrongdoing, but we struggle
over its significance in the law because
it has different senses and often
points us in opposite directions. It is morally important, but factually
imprecise, and so while
our insistence that each person’s intrinsic and
equal human dignity must be respected may offer us a moral justification for
our
criminal laws, it cannot determine their factual content.
It seems that the search for a single controlling principle must fail. A harm
based assessment offers us a usefully factual test that
protects our welfare and
autonomy, but it is too broad in scope and leaves out the moral dimensions of a
crime. On the other hand,
the normative claim that human beings are equal in
dignity or moral worth may offer us a usefully moral justification for our
criminal
law, but it cannot tell us what kinds of conduct those laws should
forbid. The challenge then, is to place these key elements into
some kind of
harmony by creating a model of the criminal law that not only reflects and
protects the lives that we want to live and
the kind of community that we want
to be, but can also ensure that our criminal laws do justice to all those living
within our community
of equals.
iv. the ‘gOOd LiFe mOdeL’ OF criminaL wrOngdOing
My model of the criminal law aims to reflect the value we place both on
protecting ourselves from conduct that may harm us and on
responding to conduct
that does not respect us as persons of equal dignity. It is based on
38 This may account for a recent editorial in the British Medical Journal doubting the usefulness of the concept of dignity by Macklin R, ‘Dignity is a Useless Concept’ (2003) 327 BritMedJ
1419.
39 See supra ns 8 and 7.
the assumption that there is a logical connection between our vision of the
fundamental elements of the good life for human beings
and our understanding of
the nature of a crime, seen as conduct which threatens those elements. I suggest
that we can identify three
incommensurate elements of the good life that the
criminal law should protect. They are our welfare interests, our autonomy
interests
and our shared desire to be respected by others as persons of equal
dignity and worth. The two factual elements of welfare and autonomy
represent
the things that we want for ourselves from life in general. By contrast,
the third element is normative and relational; being respected as a person of
equal worth is something
that we want from others because it confirms our
vision of ourselves as members of a community of equals who have recognised in
each other a reciprocal entitlement
to be treated as equals. These elements were
discussed in Section III and appear in Table 1, which follows.
TABLE 1. THE TWO DIMENSIONS OF A CRIME
The Factual Dimension
|
The Normative Dimension
|
|
WELFARE
Having and Being
|
AUTONOMY Choosing, Doing & Achieving
|
RESPECT
Counting as an Equal
|
1. DEFINITION
The welfare factors
include all those things,
both internal and external
to the person, that are
important to human
existence.
2. FOCUS
Passive states of well-
being.
3. BASIS
Our common needs for:
• physical, emotional and
mental health;
• possessions and wealth;
• reputation;
• community services and
institutions,
• social support; and
• a safe and secure
physical environment.
|
1. DEFINITION
Autonomy is the exercise
of control over the
conduct of one’s own life
by defining, choosing and
pursuing the good life on
one’s own terms.
2. FOCUS
Active states of well-
being or ‘well-doing’.
3. BASIS
Our common desires to:
• define the good life for
ourselves; to choose
when, where and how to
pursue it; and to succeed
in that pursuit.
• This depends on both
- our capacity, and
- our factual
opportunities for
decisions and action.
|
1. DEFINITION Respect is an attitude which recognises that each human being
is entitled to be treated asa person of equal dignity,
worth and value.
2. FOCUS
A relational state of being
treated right by others.
3. BASIS
Our shared beliefs in:
• the equality of all
human beings;
• the ideas of justice,
reciprocity, rationality
and the principle that we
should treat:
- like cases alike,
- equal cases equally,
and
- different cases
differently.
|
In Table 2, the positive elements in the model of the good life are
transposed into the negative elements contained in the model of
a crime.
Therefore, just like the good life that it reflects and protects, a crime has
two dimensions: a normative or moral dimension
governed by a principle that
requires each person to respect others as persons of equal dignity worth and
value; and a
factual dimension that protects our interests in welfare and autonomy, which
is governed by the harm to others principle. Because
our demand that others
respect us as equals contains two sub-aspects that include both the attitude
that others take towards us as well as their actual conduct towards
us, the notion of equal respect can be linked both to the definition of fault
and the definition of wrongdoing.
TABLE 2. THE TWO DIMENSIONS OF THE GOOD LIFE
THE FACTUAL DIMENSION
The ‘Harm to Others’ Principle
|
THE NORMATIVE DIMENSION
The ‘Respect Others as Equals’ Principle
|
||
HARM TO WELFARE
Setbacks to welfare (ie, our passive states of wellbeing)
that make us worse off.
|
HARM TO AUTONOMY
Setbacks to autonomy (ie, our active states of wellbeing)
that reduce either our capacity or our opportunities for chosen action.
|
WRONGDOING Conduct towards others
Conduct that deviates from the norm requiring each person to
respect others
by treating them as persons of equal dignity, worth and
value.
|
FAULT Responses to others
An attitude which fails, in the circumstances, to recognise
or to respond properly to the equal dignity, worth and value of others.
|
The key to understanding how this model justifies transforming our reciprocal
desires for respect into rules requiring respectful
conduct lies in the crucial
connection between our vision of ourselves as equals in dignity, worth and value
and the primary principle
of justice that directs that like cases should be
treated alike, and equal cases, equally.40 Once we recognise that all
human beings are equals, the direction to treat equal cases equally requires
more from us than a mere attitude
of respect. In fact, the principle of justice
is directed not to our attitudes at all, but to our conduct itself; given that
we are
equals, it requires us – whatever we might think of others –
to treat them as equals. This connection between justice
and our equal worth
enables us to make laws mandating respectful conduct that apply to all within
the community of equals and it
suggests that the critical message is not that we
see ourselves simply as possessing dignity, but that we see ourselves as
possessing equal dignity.
At its moral heart, the criminal law contains a distinctive conception of
justice that requires equal treatment of equals by equals.
However, before we
can give factual content to our moral norm of equal respect, we must return to
the good life model and recognise
that we are equal not only in a moral sense,
but also in two essential factual ways as well. As equal human beings and as
equal members
of a community we also share a wide range of factual
40 Aristotle first laid down this principle of justice in Book V of The Nicomachean Ethics
(1998 edition) 106-136.
interests in welfare and autonomy in equal measure. It follows that if our
common interests in welfare and autonomy are of equal value,
then no one
person’s interests can take priority over those of any others, because
equality mandates a stand-off.
This means that the criminal law, as the law of equal justice, imposes a
reciprocal duty on each of us to respect others by treating
their fundamental
interests in welfare and autonomy as carrying a value that is equal to our own
and so, whenever the desires of
two or more persons conflict, any use of fraud,
force or coercion is ruled out and the only acceptable way to resolve the issue
is
to resort to persuasion or to let the status quo prevail. It also imposes a
limited, unilateral duty on each human animal to respect
the interests that we
share equally with other non-human animals. Our recognition that we share
interests in welfare and existence
as a species with other animals, but not
interests in autonomy, explains why it is lawful to kill an animal humanely and
eat it,
but not to torture it or neglect its welfare.41
The law of equal justice also explains why the criminal law imposes an extended duty on able-bodied adults of full capacity to make special efforts to equalise the position of any children, or non-rational, incapacitated humans who are disadvantaged by their circumstances of factual inequality. In the case of dwarfs, for example, we are obliged as a community to ensure that they are not discriminated against on the grounds of their stature. This comes about because equality is an abstract concept, which, when applied to human beings, makes sense only in circumstances of factual difference. If we must treat equal cases equally we must also treat different cases differently. Consequently we are not entitled to ignore the weak, whose identity and intrinsic worth as human beings remains unchanged by their factual incapacity, rather our duty is to make extra efforts to compensate for their reduced capacity for autonomy. So, in our encounters with other beings, there is first a moment of recognition when we realise that we are equal in our inherent worth and in our factual interests in autonomy and welfare. This is followed by a moment of acknowledgement of the consequent duty to respect that equal dignity and those equally shared interests, and finally, each time we are faced with choosing our path through life, with a moment of choice to accept or reject that duty. This takes us back to Aristotle, who said that ‘if a man harms another by choice, he acts unjustly
... provided that the act violates proportion or
equality.’42
41 It appears that some animals may share our passion for equal justice: Brosnan SF & de
Waal FBM, ‘Monkeys Reject Unequal Pay’ (2003) 425 Nature 279.
42 The Nicomachean Ethics, supra n 40 at 127-128.
v. cOncLUSiOn: the paradOx OF dignity
The good life model of the criminal law suggests that we are not justified in criminalising any conduct unless it breaches not only the ‘harm to others’ principle, which gives factual content to this concept of a crime, but also the
‘equal respect for others’ principle which, on my account
provides the criminal law with its moral justification. Under
the good life
model of the criminal law, the primary moral principle requiring us to respect
the equal dignity, worth and value of
others explains why we also need the harm
principle to give factual content to the criminal law – because we cannot
treat others
as moral equals until we can identify the ways in which we are
factually equal. Furthermore, the model’s combination of the
two
principles also helps us to limit the spread of the criminal law that would
occur if we used only the harm principle as our source
of limits. The good life
model, because it contains the equal respect principle that focuses on both the
attitude of disrespect and
the wrongful conduct that evidences that disrespect,
defines a crime as conduct that is animated by a failure to recognise or to
respond properly to the equal dignity, worth and value of others and their equal
entitlement to pursue and enjoy their welfare and
exercise their autonomy within
the boundaries provided for by the state. This means that we cannot classify any
and all conduct that
risks harm as criminal, but only the conduct that risks
harm to the equal interests of others, which we read as a conscious failure
of
respect.
The good life model places the duty of equal justice not only on each of us
within the community as individual persons, but also upon
the most dangerous of
legal persons: the state itself. It not only justifies the state’s
punitive responses to those who have
failed in their conduct to do equal justice
to others but also limits the state to criminalising only conduct that both
threatens
harm to the equally shared welfare or autonomy interests of others and
at the same time is read as a failure to respect the equal
value of others. This
account of the limits on the criminal law leads to an interesting paradox that
results from the asymmetry feature
of the meaning of dignity discussed in
section III. This paradox of dignity requires the state, in the name of our
equal dignity,
to refrain from criminalising certain controversial or upsetting
kinds of conduct like dwarf tossing events that may be perceived
as supremely
undignified. It arises because our vision of ourselves as equals in dignity and
worth, which gives the criminal law
its moral justification, grounds our duty to
respect others as sovereign equals, entitled to exercise their capacity for
autonomy
either in ways that may be antithetical to their own welfare interests
as objectively viewed by others or in ways that are perceived
by others to be
undignified or even offensive (always providing that their exercise of that
autonomy does not itself risk harm to
the welfare or autonomy of others). This
means that
we must respect not only the choices of a dwarf, who enjoys being paid to fly
through the air in a safe, regulated dwarf tossing event,
but also the choices
of those who wish to test their strength by hurling the dwarf through the air. I
would argue that legislation
forbidding safe, regulated and consensual dwarf
tossing is impermissible under the good life model: first, because the conduct
is
not relevantly harmful (it neither harms the dwarfs’ welfare interests,
nor infringes their autonomy interests), and secondly,
because it cannot be read
as displaying any attitude of disrespect to the equal value of the
dwarfs.
Any legislation imposing criminal sanctions on those who organise dwarf tossing contests would appear, therefore, to contain a false evaluation of the relative worth of citizens. The false evaluation contained in such a statute would be: “Because dwarfs are not equal to persons of full stature, they must be protected from autonomously choosing, as others of full stature do, to engage in these (possibly) demeaning kinds of activities and employment.” Such a paternalist statute improperly treats the dwarf as a person of lesser capacity by comparison with others of full stature and amounts to impermissible discrimination based on size. Consequently, I conclude that under the good life model, the state can insist that dwarf tossing is carried out in safety, but it cannot criminalise those events within a legal system that, on my account, is itself justified because it must stand up for our equal dignity.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZYbkNZJur/2006/16.html