Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Yearbook of New Zealand Jurisprudence |
Last Updated: 25 April 2015
A FEW SIMPLE POINTS ABOUT CUSTOMARY LAW AND OUR LEGAL SYSTEM
DR ALEX FRAME
The Tūhonohono gathering, held at Hopuhopu on the great awa Waikato of
such importance to the Kīngitanga and the Tainui
tribes, brought together
many knowledgeable participants to consider its central theme of customary law.
It may be of some small
use, therefore, if at the outset I try to discuss a few
simple points about the place of customary law in our legal system, such
as it
is at the present time. Some of the points are dealt with more fully in the
Introduction to Te Mātāpunenga: A Compendium of References to the
Concepts and Institutions of Māori Customary Law, a draft of which was
made available to participants and which, it is anticipated, will be published
formally soon after this record
of the Symposium proceedings.
i. THREE “ULTIMATE LEGAL PRINCIPLES”
It was our world-famous jurist Sir John Salmond who observed in his classic
work on Jurisprudence that:1
... there must be found in every legal system certain ultimate principles,
from which all others are derived, but which are themselves
self-existent.
Before there can be any talk of legal sources, there must be already in
existence some law which establishes them
and gives them their
authority.
Although there is nothing pre-ordained about this, our New Zealand legal
system, as currently understood, would seem to require the
tabulation of three
such “ultimate legal principles”:2
(1) Acts of Parliament in proper form are a source of law;
1 Sir John Salmond Jurisprudence (7th ed, Sweet and Maxwell, London, 1924) at 169–170.
Although the work was first published in 1902, the 7th edition was the last published under Salmond’s personal control before his death in the same year and is for that reason perhaps the best expression of that author’s mature and considered thought. For further discussion, and particularly on Salmond’s anticipation of Hans Kelsen’s later concept of the “grundnorm”, see Alex Frame Salmond: Southern Jurist (Victoria University Press, Wellington, 1995) at
65-67 and footnote 58.
2 I have elsewhere raised a question whether a time may come when it
will be impossible to describe the functioning of the New
Zealand legal order
without adding a further “ultimate legal principle” concerning the
Treaty of Waitangi. See Grey and Iwikau: A Journey into Custom (Victoria
University Press, Wellington, 2002) at 69.
(2) the common/customary law as declared by the Courts is a source of
law;
(3) in the event of conflict between an Act of Parliament and common/
customary law, the Act is recognised as prevailing.
It is the second principle which provides an indisputable point of entry for
Māori customary law to our legal system. Observers
might be forgiven for
wondering why the guarantees in the Second Article of the Treaty of Waitangi are
not a prior and preferable
alternative point of entry, and may be puzzled to
learn that, so long as the 1941 decision of the Privy Council in Te
Heuheu’s
case is considered as correctly stating the law, our courts will
not directly enforce the terms of the Treaty in the absence of statutory
direction. In those circumstances, the domestic legal effect of the Treaty is
subsumed under the first ultimate legal principle.3
ii. THE COMMON/CUSTOMARY LAW IS FOUND AND
DECLARED BY THE COURTS
It is sometimes forgotten that there are only two kinds of law known to legal
systems described significantly as “common law
systems”. We may rely
on Sir John Salmond again for a clear statement of the position:
It was long the received theory of English law that whatever was not the
product of legislation had its source in custom. Law was
either the written
statute law, or the unwritten, common, or customary law. ... Lex et
consuetudo Angliae was the familiar title of our legal system. The common
law and the common custom of the realm were synonymous
expressions.4
The duty of our Judges to discover and declare our common/customary law is
explicitly recognised in the oath of office taken by them
in which they
undertake to: “well and truly serve Her Majesty according to law ... [and
to] do right to all manner of people
after the laws and usages of New
Zealand”.5
The importance and indigeneity of New Zealand common law has been further
emphasised recently by both Parliament and the Courts. In
2003 Parliament
specifically recognised and decreed that New Zealand’s final court of
appeal
3 Hoani Te Heuheu Tukino v The Aotea District Maori Land Board [1941] NZLR 590; [1941] AC 308 (PC). For an extended discussion of Te Heuheu’s case and an argument that it should not continue to be regarded as correctly stating New Zealand law, and that the Treaty should be accorded direct legal enforceability in our courts, see Alex Frame “Hoani Te Heuheu’s Case in London 1940-41: An Explosive Story” (2006) 22 New Zealand Universities Law Review 148.
4 Sir John Salmond, Jurisprudence, above n 1, 208.
5 Oaths and Declarations Act 1957, section 18. Emphasis added.
would, in its work of discovering and declaring the common/customary law of
New Zealand, consult “New Zealand conditions, history
and
traditions”. Section 3 of the Supreme Court Act 2003 declares the purpose
of the Act to be:
(a) to establish within New Zealand a new court of final appeal comprising
New Zealand judges –
(i) to recognise that New Zealand is an independent nation with its own
history and traditions; and
(ii) to enable important legal matters, including legal matters relating to
the Treaty of Waitangi, to be resolved with an understanding of New Zealand
conditions, history, and traditions... [Emphasis added.]
That point was further emphasised by the Chief Justice, Dame Sian Elias in
Attorney-General v Ngati Apa, more popularly known as the
“Foreshore and Seabed case”:6
But from the beginning the common law of New Zealand as applied in the Courts
differed from the common law of England because it reflected
local circumstances
(p.652, para.17)
Any prerogative of the Crown as to property in foreshore or seabed as a
matter of English common law in 1840 cannot apply in New Zealand
if displaced by
local circumstances. Maori custom and usage recognising property in foreshore
and seabed lands displaces any English
Crown Prerogative and is effective as a
matter of New Zealand law unless such property interests have been lawfully
extinguished.
The existence and extent of any such customary property interest
is determined by application of tikanga. (p.660, para 49)
iii. THERE ARE FOUR REQUIREMENTS FOR CUSTOMARY LAW TO BE ACCEPTED AND DECLARED BY THE COURTS
Sir John Salmond once more provides the assistance needed to identify the
four tests which must be satisfied for custom to operate
as a source of law for
our courts.
(1) “[A] custom must be reasonable”;
(2) “[A] custom must not be contrary to an Act of
Parliament”;
6 Attorney-General v Ngati Apa [2003] 3 NZLR 577. This was not a
new approach. A well- known example, nearly a century earlier, is provided by
Chief Justice Stout
in Baldick and Others v Jackson (1910) 30 NZLR,
343.
(3) The custom “must have been observed as of right. A merely voluntary
practice, not conceived as based on any rule of right
or obligation, does not
amount to a legal custom and has no legal operation”;
(4) “[C]ustom, to have the force of law, must be immemorial ... custom
was immemorial when its origin was so ancient that the
beginning of it was
beyond human memory...”.7
If more ancient authority be required for the tests, resort may be made to
the pithy statement, still in Law French, from the Case of Tanistry in
1608:8
Et issint briefement, custome est un reasonable act, iterated, multiplied
& continued per le people, de temps dont memory ne court.
(Translation: In
brief, custom is a reasonable rule, followed consistently and continuously by
the people from time immemorial.)
It will be seen that these tests preserve both the supremacy of Parliament as
recognised in the third ultimate legal principle listed
above, and, through the
requirement of “reasonableness”, the moral integrity of the legal
system as a whole. I should
perhaps, however, say a little about the
requirements of reasonableness and “immemoriality”.
First as to “reasonableness”. As Fritz Kern pointed out in his masterly study
of conceptions of law in the Middle Ages:9
... long-usage does not prove a practice to be rightful. On the contrary.
“A hundred years of wrong make not one hour of right,”
and Eike of
Repgow in the Sachsenspiegel, for example, emphasised that slavery, which
originated in force and unjust power, and was a custom so ancient that “it
is
now held for law,” was only an “unlawful custom”. The
existence of an unlawful or “evil” custom for
so long a time shows
that usage or age cannot make or reveal law.
The “good old law” clung to so tenaciously by our forbears had to
be both old and good to be law, and it is this second test which
has been entrusted to the judges in the form of the modern requirement of
“reasonableness”.
7 The above paragraph is a digest of Sir John Salmond’s exposition at pages 217-220 of his Jurisprudence (7th ed, 1924). For a fuller account of the authority for, and application of, these tests, see Alex Frame Grey and Iwikau: A Journey into Custom, above n 2, Section VII ‘Revaluing Custom as a Source of our Law’, at 63-76.
8 Case of Tanistry 80 Eng. Rep. 516 (1608), quoted in EK Braybrooke, “Custom as a Source
of English Law” (1951), 50 Michigan Law Review 71 at 73.
9 Fritz Kern Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages, transl. SB
Chrimes (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1968) at 150. The work was first published in
German in 1914 and first published in
English translation in 1939. Pocock
recommends its quality.
Secondly, Sir John Salmond is clear that the original meaning of “time
immemorial” for the purpose of establishing custom
as law was that the
custom be “so ancient that the beginning of it was beyond human memory, so
that no testimony was available
as to a time when it did not
exist”.10 But English law substituted “legal
memory” for this human memory and fixed the year 1189 (the date of
accession to the
throne of Richard I (“Richard Coeur de Lion”) as
the date at which memory ceased. There is no reason, however, for applying
this
idiosyncratic rule of thumb to Māori customary law, which must accordingly
be considered under the original and more general
meaning of immemoriality
identified by Sir John Salmond.
A second point about the immemoriality requirement is that it does not
preclude development and modification of custom. This dynamic
aspect of
customary law has been well recognised by the common law courts, as is shown
with respect to Māori custom concerning
adoption by the Privy Council in
Hineiti Rirerire Arani v Public Trustee in 1919, where Lord Phillimore
said:11
It is ... abundantly clear that Native custom, and especially the Native
custom of adoption ... is not a fixed thing. It is based
upon the old custom as
it existed before the arrival of Europeans, but it has developed, and become
adapted to the changed circumstances
of the Maori race to-day.
The New Zealand-born political philosopher JGA Pocock first published his
work on “The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law”
in 1957, and
reissued it in 1987 with a “Retrospect”.12 Its central
method derived from the realisation that the thoughts and actions of ancient
times could only be understood if the world
in which they occurred were
“resurrected” and described in detail. Pocock saw the paradox
presented by these two sides
of customary law – its constant adaptation
and its timelessness. His resolution for the paradox was to quote Hale’s
old
argument of a ship totally replaced in materials over its life still being
the same ship: “If the law can remain the same when
the whole of its
content has been altered, it must be the continuity of the process of law-
making which counts.”13
10 Salmond, above n 1, at 220.
11 Hineiti Rirerire Arani v Public Trustee NZPCC 1840-1932. See also the interesting statement by Lord Phillimore that “the maories as a race may have some internal power of self- government enabling the tribe or tribes by common consent to modify their customs...”. For further discussion see Grey and Iwikau, above n 2, at 72.
12 JGA Pocock The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: Reissue with a Retrospect
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1987).
13 Ibid, at 176.
iV. A DEFINITION OF CUSTOMARY LAW FOR Te
MāTāpunenga
Te Mātāhauariki Institute researchers, under the guidance of Judge
Michael Brown, the late Dr Tui Adams, and a very distinguished
Advisory Panel.
have grappled from the beginning with the formulation of a definition of
“customary law” which did not
exclude norms which were
“spiritually sanctioned” rather than directly physically enforced by
the group or tribe. The
Editorial Board of Te Mātāpunenga
finally settled on the following:14
A social norm is legal if its neglect or infraction is regularly met, in
threat or in fact, by the application of force or the construction
of serious
social disadvantage by an individual, group, or agency possessing the socially
recognised privilege of so acting.
It may be useful if I sketch the process by which that definition took shape.
The Editorial Board began with Hoebel’s helpful
proposal
that:15
a social norm is legal if its neglect or infraction is regularly met, in
threat or in fact, by the application of physical force by
an individual or
group possessing the socially recognised privilege of so acting.
But even Hoebel’s definition, while displaying a commendable departure
from the tendency of mainstream 19th-century Western
jurisprudence to insist on
“commands” and “sovereignty” before conferring the
status of “law”,
still clung to “physical force” as the
hallmark and sine qua non. What then of a norm the breach of which was believed
by both the offender and the social group to lead on to
“supernatural” punishment? Hoebel’s definition would deny
it
legal status. The Board pondered Lon Fuller’s
question:16
Just what is meant by force when it is taken as the identifying mark of law?
If in a theocratic society the threat of hell-fire suffices
to secure obedience
to its law, is this “a threat of force”?
The Board considered that adding the consequence of “the construction
of serious social disadvantage” might broaden the
definition so as to
capture that circumstance, as it considered was necessary to fully represent the
Māori legal order.
14 Te Mātāpunenga: A Compendium of References to the Concepts and Institutions of Māori
Customary Law, Introduction.
15 E Adamson Hoebel The Law of Primitive Man: A Study of Comparative Legal Dynamics
(Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1954) at 28.
16 Lon Fuller The Morality of Law (Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticut, first
published in 1964, revised ed 1969) at 109.
V. THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF RANKING CUSTOMARY CONCEPTS AND
INSTITUTIONS ON A “PRIMITIVE/SOPHISTICATED” SCALE
My friend and colleague Paul Meredith and I have pointed out that use of a
supposed “primitive/sophisticated” scale for
customary legal
concepts and institutions is inappropriate because a particular set of criteria
is necessarily chosen by which to
measure
“sophistication”:17
Other criteria could be proposed which might produce different orderings. For
example, if social cohesion were taken as the measure,
or economic cost, then
legal systems might be placed at different positions on the scale. Systems in
which law consisted of technical
legal signals administered by expensive
specialist groups of judges, lawyers, and policemen might be seen as
“primitive”
when compared to “sophisticated” systems
capable of functioning effectively without either.
I have tried to provide an example to illustrate the futility of attributing
“primitivity” and “sophistication”
in an account of
Māori customary legal principles encountered by Governor Grey and his party
on their journey overland to Taupō
with Iwikau Te Heu Heu in the summer of
1849–1850. In discussing the Māori theory of obligation in relation
to taonga, founded on the active and personal role of hau, it was
concluded that: “This system need no policemen, courts, or bailiffs, since
the taonga themselves serve as enforcers.”18
A modern Minister of Justice – and his or her colleague in charge of the Treasury
– might be very interested in such a system! Far from appearing
“primitive”, such a system might on examination
prove to be very
“sophisticated”. As proposed earlier, all would depend on the
criteria adopted.
VI. the so-called Issue of “genuIne” Versus “spurIous” custom,
And the generAL chArge thAt custom is mAde up to suit
Customary law has its critics. Some legislators, inclined towards
codification of law, tend to regard customary law as a perplexing
and
complicating intrusion upon the clear geometry of their architectural plans, and
are happy to take
17 Alex Frame and Paul Meredith “Performance and Maori Customary Legal Process”, 114
Journal of the Polynesian Society 135, at 139.
18 Grey and Iwikau, above n 2, 59-61.
every opportunity to sweep it away.19 Some judges, perhaps
forgetting the origins of the common law in custom, have come to see that body
of law as judge-made, rather than as judge-found. Some jurists and
commentators have expressed suspicions that customary law is simply “made
up” by claimants with axes
to grind or interests to pursue. This last
matter is discussed in the Introduction to Te Mātāpunenga,
where the authors state that:
The business of argument based on customary law – and for that matter
on written codes – is to present an outcome which
is faithful to what are
urged to be the fundamental values of the society. Of course that will involve
appeals to a “Golden
Age”, and of course there will be attempts to
“edit”.20 On the other hand, the business of
adjudicators, scholars, and the collective memory of society (however that may
be stored, whether
in venerable tomes or in traditional genealogies and song) is
to identify and denounce fabrications or false pleadings, without stifling
the
necessary dynamism of customary law.
So the answer to the detractors and critics of customary law is twofold.
First, that our constitutional arrangements require courts
to seek and declare
it in accordance with well-understood and coherent tests allowing and requiring
the sifting out of false or doubtful
claims and permitting the abandonment of
“unreasonable” custom, such as norms or practices contrary to modern
human rights
norms. Secondly, that the value of customary law lies in its
balancing of the well-accepted “top-down” law-creating powers
of a
legitimate legislature with the “bottom-up” recording and
development of customary law. We do not reject the undoubted
utility of rational
law making, but seek to balance its value against the danger that legal
“architects” may lose touch
19 I have elsewhere contrasted this “architectural” approach to law making, which aims at clearing the legal deck ready for the grand new vision of the law-maker, with a more “archaeological” approach aimed at uncovering the historical concepts and values of the society concerned. See “Making Constitutions in the South Pacific: Architects and Excavators” in David Carter and Matthew Palmer (eds) Roles and Perspectives in the Law: Essays in Honour of Sir Ivor Richardson (Victoria University Press, Wellington, 2002) 277.
20 If an example be demanded from the early colonisation period in New Zealand, see FD Fenton’s “The Laws of England Compiled and Translated into the Māori Language by direction of His Excellency Colonel Thomas Gore Browne, C.B., Governor of New Zealand” (Auckland, 1858). In that work, which attempted to summarise the origins and content of English law, Māori were told that:
A wise and generous people, the English, have settled in his land; and this people are willing to teach him, and to guide him in the well-made road which themselves have travelled for so many generations; that is the path of the perfected law – in the path by which themselves have attained to all the good things which they now possess; wisdom, prosperity, quietness, peace, wealth, power, glory, and all other good things which the Pakeha possesses... (p. ii)
Few jurists, or citizens, would have described the state of English law in
the mid-19th century as “perfected”.
with that reservoir of support and determination in the hearts of the people without which law becomes an alien imposition, to be abandoned as soon as circumstances permit.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZYbkNZJur/2011/5.html