![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Otago Law Review |
![]() |
Last Updated: 27 May 2017
Charity begins at the politically correct home?
The Family First case
Rex Tauati Ahdar*
I Introduction
Is advancing the traditional or nuclear family uncharitable? Is it “controversial” and impermissibly political “propaganda” in the 21st century to advocate the two-parent, opposite-sex, married couple as the optimal domestic configuration in which to have and raise children? The Charities Registration Board (NZ) thought so and deregistered the organisation that had the temerity to advance it: Family First New Zealand.
It is not as though deregistration is an infrequent occurrence. There are a huge number of charities in New Zealand: 27,072, that have a combined income of $16.41 billion.1 But just as some charities bloom, others are scythed down if they fail to bear fruit. In 2013 the Inland Revenue reported that 3,902 charities had been deregistered since the Charities Register had been opened in February 2007.2 This means around 15 per cent, or some one in six, of the then around 26,000 charities were axed.3
Back to the case at hand: it needed an expensive appeal to the High Court for
Family First,4 an outspoken conservative entity, to ensure that its
deregistration as a charity was revisited. This article examines the Family
First
deregistration decision and, although it is hardly a landmark case, its
significance, I suggest, lies as a particularly clear example
of official
institutional antipathy towards the conservative political and religious
understanding of domestic personal relations.
II Background to the Family First New Zealand Appeal
The Family First New Zealand Trust (FF) was created in 2006 and FF was also
incorporated under the Charitable Trusts Act 1957 in that
same year. FF’s
purposes include “to promote and advance research and policy supporting
marriage and family as foundational
to a strong and enduring
society.”5 The next year it was registered under the Charities
Act 2005.6
* Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Otago; Adjunct Professor, School of Law, University of Notre Dame Australia at Sydney. This is a revised version of a paper presented at the Australian Charity Law Association annual conference, Brisbane, 29 August 2015. I am grateful for the helpful comments of an anonymous referee.
1 Charities Services (located within the Department of Internal Affairs)
website: <https://charities.govt.nz/> (as at 14 October 2015).
2 Susan Barker, “Deregistered charities” [2014] NZLJ 87 at 87.
3 At 87.
4 Re Family First New Zealand Ltd [2015] NZHC 1493, (2015) 27 NZTC 22-017
(HC) (“Family First”).
5 At [3].
6 Number CC 10094, registered on 21 March 2007.
The Charities Commission in 2009 reviewed FF’s operations to determine if it still warranted its charitable status and a year later concluded it did.7 A restructuring of charity regulation in 2012 saw the Charities Registration Board (Charities Board) and the Department of Internal Affairs replace the Commission. The Charities Board comprises three persons who “must act independently in exercising [their] professional judgement”.8
In September 2012, the Department recommended to the Charities Board that FF be removed from the Charities Register. In the Department’s view, FF had succumbed to advocating a political viewpoint. On 15 April
2013, the Board resolved to deregister FF.9 Family First duly
appealed and the High Court, on 17 June 2013, granted an interim order under s
60 of the Charities Act allowing
FF to stay registered pending the outcome of a
Supreme Court judgment in the Greenpeace case. This important decision
was delivered on 6 August 2014.10 The Supreme Court decision
– on, in my opinion, any reasonable and non-tortured reading –
called for a prompt reconsideration
of the FF deregistration and, equally I
suggest, FF’s eventual reinstatement. But this did not
happen:11
The Charities Board recognised the Supreme Court’s judgment in
Greenpeace introduced changes to the law concerning the charitable status
of entities that have a political purpose. However, the Charities Board
believed
it could not reconsider its decision concerning Family First unless Family
First’s appeal was allowed and the Charities
Board directed to reconsider
its decision.
So, and this bears emphasis, despite having the benefit of the Supreme
Court’s unusually clear ruling, the Charities Board put
FF to the
expense12 and stress of seeing through the appeal to the High Court
lodged a year earlier, winning its case and only then – once the Board
had
been ordered to do so by the Court – would it reconsider its original
deregistration decision. The Board, ex abuntanti
cautela, might have thought
that it had no power to reconsider FF’s eligibility for registration
without first
7 Family First, above n 4, at [6]–[7].
8 Charities Act 2005, s 8(4)(a). The Chairman, Mr Roger Holmes Miller, is a
Wellington lawyer and Registered Trustee, whose specialisations include
trust law and governance. Ms Caren Rangi is a chartered accountant
and audit specialist from Napier. Mr Simon Karipa is currently General
Counsel for Te Ohu Kaimoana (the Māori Fisheries Trust): <https://
www.charities.govt.nz/about-charities-services/charities-registration-
board/>.
9 Deregistration decision: Family First New Zealand, Charities Board (CC
42358), Decision No D2013-1, 15 April 2013 (“Board”): <https://charities.
govt.nz/charities-in-new-zealand/legal-decisions/view-the-decisions/
view/family-first-new-zealand>.
10 Re Greenpeace of New Zealand Inc [2014] NZSC 105, [2015] 1 NZLR 169.
11 Family First, above n 4, at [74].
12 The legal cost for the Board to take the Family First case to court was
$32,894 (not including GST): letter from Charities Services, Internal Affairs
(on file with author).
receiving a green light in the form of a court ruling. The appeal against deregistration having already been lodged, the Board might have believed it was best to see the matter run its course.
The Act, on my reading, is simply silent on when, how, and under what circumstances, a reconsideration takes place. There is brief mention of the Board’s duties in respect of assessing a new application for registration from a deregistered charity.13 But there is no express provision permitting the Board to reconsider a yet-to-be-implemented decision to deregister a charitable entity. By the same token, neither is there any provision preventing it from doing so. There is a hint that unnecessary formalities are not to be generated: s 19(3) states that “the Board is not required to follow a formal process” when it evaluates an originating application for registration as a charity. Logic would suggest the same approach be followed for reconsideration of determinations to expunge existing charities and, for that matter, fresh applications by a deregistered entity.
To return to the legislative scheme more generally, under the Charities Act 2005 a trust qualifies for registration if it derives income for charitable purposes (s 13) and the Act adopts the venerable statement of Lord Macnaghten in Pemsel:14
5. Meaning of charitable purpose and effect of ancillary non-charitable
purpose
(1) In this Act, unless the context otherwise requires, charitable
purpose includes every charitable purpose, whether it relates
to the relief of
poverty, the advancement of education or religion, or any other matter
beneficial to the community.
The section goes on to provide that any non-charitable purpose that is merely
ancillary to the charitable one is not fatal.
(3) To avoid doubt, if the purposes of a trust, society, or an
institution include a non-charitable purpose (for example, advocacy)
that is
merely ancillary to a charitable purpose of the trust, society, or institution,
the presence of that non-charitable purpose
does not prevent the trustees of the
trust, the society, or the institution from qualifying for registration as a
charitable entity.
(4) For the purposes of subsection (3), a non-charitable purpose is
ancillary to a charitable purpose of the trust, society,
or institution if the
non-charitable purpose is –
(a) ancillary, secondary, subordinate, or incidental to a charitable purpose
of the trust, society, or institution; and
(b) not an independent purpose of the trust, society, or
institution.
13 Charities Act 2005, s 31(4).
14 Commissioners for Special Purposes of the Income Tax v Pemsel [1891] AC 531
at 583.
In determining an entity’s purposes, its activities must also be taken into account, to the extent that the latter assists in evaluating:15
(1) the meaning of a stated purpose where the stated purpose is capable of bearing more than one meaning;
(2) whether the entity is undertaking an unstated non-charitable purpose;
(3) whether the entity’s purposes provide a benefit to the public; and
(4) whether a non-charitable purpose falls within the saving provisions of s 5(3) of the Charities Act.16
The deregistration of a body cannot occur unless the Board is satisfied
that it is “in the public interest” to do so.17
The Board, in concluding that FF was a candidate for deregistration
(primarily on the basis that it was engaged in political advocacy)
was
“heavily influenced”18 by the Court of Appeal
judgment19 in Greenpeace.
III The Charities Board Decision
Deregistration was, according to the Board’s analysis, justified on three
bases.
First, it held that FF’s main purpose was to “promote points of view about family life” and this was a non-charitable political purpose lacking a self-evident public benefit.20 Second, FF had an independent purpose to procure government action consistent with FF’s stance, and this purpose was a non-charitable, political one that was not ancillary to any valid charitable purpose. Third, FF’s purpose to advance its views about family life was not a charitable purpose of an educational or religious nature, nor was it beneficial to the public within the fourth category of charity.
A Political purposes that are not self-evidently beneficial to the
public21
The Board suggested that there are three types of political purposes excluded
from the notion of a charity:22 furthering the interests of a
particular political party; purposes to procure governmental actions (including
through legislation);
and, thirdly, purposes “to promote a point of view,
the public benefit of which is not self evident as a matter of
law.”23
15 Charities Act 2005, s 18(3)(a)(i)(ii).
16 Family First, above n 4, at [24].
17 Charities Act 2005, s 35(1).
18 Family First, above n 4, at [39].
19 Re Greenpeace of New Zealand Inc [2012] NZCA 533, [2013] 1 NZLR 339.
20 Board, above n 9, at [32].
21 See generally Juliet Chevalier-Watts Law of Charity (Thompson Reuters,
Wellington, 2014) at § 7.5.
22 Board, above n 9, at [38], citing Re Collier (Deceased) [1988] 1 NZLR 81 at
89–90.
23 Above.
The Board focused upon the third kind of excluded political purpose. Careful
parsing of the FAQ section of FF’s website on what
it meant by
“family” revealed that this organisation strongly supported the
“natural family”, that is: 24
... the union of a man and a woman through marriage for the purposes of
sharing love and joy, raising children, providing their moral
education,
building a vital home economy, offering security in times of trouble, and
binding the generations.
FF affirmed “the marital union to be the authentic sexual bond”, “the sanctity of human life from conception to death”, “the complementarity of the sexes is a source of strength” amongst other propositions in an
11 item list. FF’s stance on families was, said the Board, “an
opinion or value judgment.”25 In a key passage we learn
that:26
The Board also considers that the Trust’s perspective on family is one that is controversial in the relevant sense, ie that its benefit to the public is not self-evident as a matter of law. The Board considers it can be taken as a given that there is no relevant self-evident benefit to specific positions on conscience issues such as procreation outside of marriage (point 6), the definition of marriage as a union between a man and woman (point
2), the sanctity of life from conception to death (point 7). Moreover, the
Board considers that the Trust’s [ie, FF’s]
opinion that the
government must shelter and encourage the “natural family” (point
8); its opinions regarding the consequences
of the demise of the “natural
family” [viz “moral and political failure” resulting in
“poverty, starvation
and environmental decay”] (points 5 and 9); its
prescription for the role of men and women in family life (point 10) and its
advocacy against an individual rights perspective [viz “the natural
family, not the individual, is the fundamental social unit”]
(point 1) are
fairly described as controversial in contemporary New Zealand
society.
Further careful website investigation revealed “the controversial nature of the Trust’s advocacy for ‘the natural family’”27 – this position being starkly apparent from another long list of policies it promoted to politicians. These policies included those to: “protect marriage in law as one man-one woman”, “end discrimination against stay-home parents”, “amend section 59 [of the Crimes Act 1961] to decriminalise parents who use light smacking for correction of children”, “promote married couple adoption”, “oppose euthanasia”, “criminalise the act of pimping and brothel keeping”, “reduce the availability of pornography” and so on.28
The Board rejected the submission that FF’s agenda accorded with the
international and domestic law concerning family life and
children’s
rights. “Neither New Zealand’s international law obligations nor
New
25 Board, above n 9, at [45].
26 At [46] (emphasis added).
27 At [47].
28 At [47].
Zealand’s domestic law”, it maintained, “favour ‘the natural family’
over other forms of family.”29
The Charities Board was incorrect, at least with respect to the international position. Beginning with the Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948, the UN has consistently assumed the traditional or natural family in its conventions that mention the “family”.30 Article 1(3) of the Declaration states that “the family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to protection by society and the State.” And as for what is a family, art 16(1) strongly implies that it is the traditional nuclear one. That article reads: “Men and women of full age ... have the right to marry and to found a family.” It could hardly be clearer. The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights 1966 reiterates these propositions.31 Later Resolutions (not, be it noted, Conventions) have admittedly proffered more inclusive and broader concepts of the “family in its various forms”.32
This year, on 3 July 2015, the UN Human Rights Council in Geneva passed a
resolution on the Protection of the Family.33 The
Resolution:34
Reaffirms that the family is the natural and fundamental group unit of
society and is entitled to protection by society and the State,
Notes with concern that the contribution of the family in society and
in the achievement of development goals continues to be largely overlooked and
underemphasized, and recognizing the potential of the family to contribute to
national development and to the achievement of major
goals of every society...
including the eradication of poverty and the creation of just, stable and secure
societies.
The resolution was passed by 29 votes to 14, with 4 abstentions. Those
nations in the minority include Western countries, such as
the US,
France,
29 At [48].
30 This phrase was used by the UN in the International Conference on
Population and Development, Cairo (1994), UN Doc A/CONF 171/13
(1994) at 5.1. See Maria S Aguirre and Ann Wolfgram “United Nations
Policy and the Family: Redefining the Ties that Bind” (2002) 16 BYU J
Public Law 113.
31 ICCPR 1966, art 23: “(1) The family is the natural and fundamental group
unit of society and is entitled to protection by society and the State.
(2) The right of men and women of marriageable age to marry and to
found a family shall be recognized.”
32 See Aguirre and Wolfgram, above n 30, at 116 ff.
33 A/HRC/29/L 25.
34 Above (original emphasis).
Germany and the UK, with “liberal” or “progressive”35 (for want of more accurate epithets) agendas to advance, inter alia, wider notions of the family and the promotion of reproductive and LGBT rights.36
On the domestic front, however, the Charities Board was on firmer ground. The
recognition of other forms of family beyond the traditional
nuclear one is a
well documented phenomenon. As Professor Mark Henaghan
summarises:37
current legal policy on the concept of the family is moving from a primarily
moral [traditional married nuclear family] view to a
much greater recognition of
a wide variety of family relationships. This means a significantly wider variety
of relationships have
been given legal status and recognition by family law
legislation in recent times. The primary driving force behind this change is
the
idea of equality as expressed in anti-discrimination law. This concept of
equality assumes that personal relationship are essential
the same, and for that
reason should be treated the same...
B Independent purpose to procure government action
FF had the purpose to procure governmental action reflecting its views.38
Propaganda directed to private individuals and corporations to advance
charitable objects is permissible, whereas that directed to political actors,
such as Members of Parliament, is not.39 The Board considered that FF’s
stated purposes and activities pointed towards an independent or stand-
alone purpose to procure political actions. The calls for governmental
action were “pervasive through the Trust’s overall endeavour.”40
C Purposes that were not religious, educational or beneficial to the
public
1 Advancement of religion
FF failed under this category of charitable purpose. The fact that only
religious persons could be trustees and that the Trust stated
on its
website
35 On the definition of “liberal” see eg Roger Scruton The Palgrave Macmillan
Dictionary of Political Thought (3rd ed, Palgrave MacMillan, New York,
2007) at 394: “In US popular usage, ‘liberal’ means left-liberal, and is
expressly contrasted with ‘conservative’. In this usage a liberal is one who
leans consciously towards the under-privileged, supports the causes of
minorities and socially excluded groups, believes in the use of state power
to achieve social justice, usually in the form of welfare programmes, and
in all probability shares the egalitarian and secular values of the modern,
and maybe those of the postmodern world-view.” On the meaning of
“progressive”, see Scruton ibid at 561.
36 “A new global force is fighting liberal social mores”, The Economist,
11 July 2015.
37 “Legally defining the family” in Mark Hengahan and Bill Atkin (eds)
Family Law Policy in New Zealand (4 th ed, LexisNexis NZ, Wellington,
2013) 1 at 5.
38 Board, above n 9, at [95]–[96] and [100].
39 At [93].
40 At [100].
that it spoke “from a family friendly perspective with an emphasis on the Judeo-Christian values which have benefited New Zealand for generations” were not sufficient.41 These factors demonstrated the Trust may have “a connection with, be motivated by or be conducive to [religion]”42, but that is not enough. On that reasoning, the Society for the Protection of the Unborn Child (now renamed Voice for Life) has failed to meet the criteria for this head of charity.43 (FF did not challenge this conclusion on appeal.)
2 Advancement of education
FF is very active in publishing and disseminating its opinion through its website and media releases. It hosts an annual “New Zealand Forum on the Family” and commissions polls on issues and solicits research on subject dear to its heart.44 The Board considered that FF’s website publications were “predominantly opinion pieces”45. FF’s commissioned research papers constituted “propaganda for the points of view promoted by the Trust.”46 The reports did not, for instance, present original research nor provide a balanced and rigorous literature review.47
3 Other purposes beneficial to the community
Within this broad category FF argued its work aimed to improve the moral and spiritual welfare of the community. But having found that FF’s purpose was a political one (“to promote a specific model of family life”48) this, according to the Board, ruled out it being charitable under the moral and spiritual improvement category.49
Could FF bring itself under the promotion of good citizenship umbrella?
Again, the Board said no. FF’s purpose and activities
were “to
promote a controversial point of view rather than to facilitate balanced and
informed debate of public issues.”50 In another passage it
chided that where an entity’s contributions to public debate “simply
reflect a specific position
and do not advance education or reflect rigorous
standards of objective analysis and factual research”51 it
would not pass muster.
IV The High Court Appeal
We have seen that the gravamen of the Board’s deregistration decision
was that FF’s purposes and activities were political.
The Board had
duly
41 At [57].
42 Liberty Trust v Charities Commission [2011] NZHC 577, [2011] 3 NZLR 68
at [94].
43 Molloy v CIR [1981] 1 NZLR 668 (CA).
44 Board, above n 9, at [71].
45 At [74].
46 At [75].
47 At [75].
48 At [83].
49 At [82]–[83].
50 At [84].
51 At [89].
followed the Court of Appeal in Greenpeace which, it will be recalled, had held that, inter alia, political activities and controversial objects were fatal to charitable status. To be fair then, the Board was adhering to the law as it was.
A Political purpose and controversial views
The majority of the Supreme Court in Greenpeace reversed the Court of
Appeal’s stance on matters political. It stated: “charitable and
political purposes are not mutually
exclusive in all cases: a blanket exclusion
is unnecessary and distracts from the underlying inquiry whether a purpose is of
public
benefit within the sense the law recognises as charitable.”52
Accordingly, Collins J in Family First held: 53
The Charities Board’s decision was based upon a fundamental legal
proposition that has subsequently been found to be incorrect.
The Charities
Board’s view that political purposes could not be charitable underpinned
its decision. In view of the Supreme
Court’s explanation that political
purposes are not irreconcilable with charitable purposes, it is appropriate for
the Charities
Board to reconsider the position of Family First in light of the
Supreme Court’s judgment.
The Supreme Court majority in Greenpeace was also adamant that the
so-called controversial nature of the views or purposes espoused by the entity
was not, as the Court of
Appeal had held, a bar to the law’s recognition
of it as a charity: 54
We are unable to agree with the Court of Appeal suggestion that views
generally acceptable may be charitable, while those which are
highly
controversial are not. In Molloy the existence of public controversy over
abortion helped explain why maintaining the legal status quo on abortion could
not be assumed
to serve the public benefit in the way the law regards as
charitable. But the more general emphasis on controversy taken from it
may be
misplaced. It is reminiscent of the suggestion by Lord Wright in National
Anti-Vivisection Society that “intangible benefit” which is
charitable is that “approv[ed] by the common understanding of enlightened
opinion
for the time being”. Such thinking would effectively exclude much
promotion of change while favouring charitable status on
the basis of
majoritarian assessment and the status quo. Just as unpopularity of causes
otherwise charitable should not affect their charitable status, we do not
think that lack of controversy could be determinative. We consider that the
Court of Appeal was wrong to place such emphasis
in the present case on the
acceptance in New Zealand legislation and society
52 Greenpeace, above n 10, at [3] and [74] per Elias CJ, McGrath and Glazebrook JJ. William Young and Arnold JJ dissented. At [127] they state: “the position that political advocacy is not charitable is reasonably defensible not only on the basis of the authorities but also as a matter of policy and practicality.”
53 Family First, above n 4, at [84].
54 Greenpeace, above n 10, at [75] (emphasis added). The Lord Wright
quotation is from National Anti-Vivisection Society v Inland Revenue
Commissioners [1947] UKHL 4; [1948] AC 31 at 39.
of the ultimate goal of nuclear disarmament and popular support in New
Zealand for the elimination of weapons of mass
destruction.
In Greenpeace the appellant organisation had signalled it would change its objects from “the promotion of peace and disarmament” – which had fallen foul of the political purpose exclusion before both the Charities Commission (the predecessor to the Charities Board) and the High Court – to “the promotion of nuclear disarmament and the elimination of all weapons of mass destruction”.55 This amendment satisfied the Court of Appeal since, in its view, the object was now sufficiently non- controversial. But the Supreme Court, as we have seen, said this was
the wrong litmus test:
Instead, assessment of whether advocacy or promotion of a cause or law reform is a charitable purpose depends on consideration of the end that is advocated, the means promoted to achieve that end and the manner in which the cause is promoted in order to assess whether the purpose can be said to be of public benefit within the spirit and intendment of the
1601 Statute.56
The trouble with a controversy criterion is, one would have thought, fairly
obvious. Jonathan Garton, with perhaps a hint of hyperbole,
contends:
“Controversy alone simply cannot be an appropriate barometer for
determining whether a particular purpose is political:
if it were, there would
be little, if anything, that could ever be charitable.”57
Returning to the actual objects in dispute in Greenpeace, the
Supreme Court explained: 58
[T]he court would have no adequate means of judging the public benefit
of such promotion of nuclear disarmament and elimination of all weapons of mass
destruction, taking into account
all the consequences, local and international.
Whether promotion of these ideas is beneficial is a matter of opinion in
which public benefit is not self-evident and which seems unlikely to be
capable of demonstration by evidence.
In their dissenting judgment, William Young and Arnold JJ held that political
advocacy did debar an entity from being registered as a charity. Their
reasoning, nonetheless, echoes that of the majority on the competency and
desirability of judges evaluating the merits of a cause, whether controversial
or otherwise: 59
[J]udges are usually not well-placed to determine whether the success of a
particular cause would be in the public interest. This
may be for reasons of
institutional competence. By way of example, a dispute between Greenpeace
and the chief executive of the Department of Internal Affairs under the
Charities
Act does not provide an ideal forum for determining the appropriate
policies for New Zealand to adopt towards other states in relation
to nuclear
weapons and weapons of mass destruction.
55 See Greenpeace, above n 10, at [4]–[7].
56 Greenpeace, above n 10, at [76] (emphasis added).
57 Public Benefit in Charity Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013) at
206.
58 Above n 10 at [101] (emphasis added).
59 At [125] (emphasis added).
Similar considerations may apply in relation to Greenpeace’s purpose of
protecting the environment, a purpose which is closely
intertwined with the
advocacy of causes (for instance against genetic engineering) the worth of which
are not easily determined by
the courts. As well, and leaving aside the
practical difficulties of forming a judgment on such issues, a judge may
feel that entering into such an inquiry lies outside the proper scope of the
judicial role.
On Greenpeace’s refashioning of its objects to make them less controversial in order to regain its charitable status, the Supreme Court in polite but terse fashion scolded: “It is not clear why the change in Greenpeace’s objects was treated by the Court of Appeal as being so decisive in the result”60 and “the substitution of one abstract end for another does not provide sufficient answer.”61
B Benefit to the public head of charity
Collins J saw the force of FF’s argument that advocacy “for its
conception of the traditional family was analogous to
organisations that have
advocated for the ‘mental and moral improvement’ of
society.”62 When it reconsidered FF’s eligibility, he
emphasised that the Board must be scrupulously objective when undertaking the
analogical
exercise of comparing FF’s activities with entities that had
been accepted as charitable under this head. With more than a hint of
disapproval he added: 63
This exercise should not be conflated with a subjective assessment of
the merits of Family First’s views. Members of the Charities Board may
personally disagree with the views of Family First, but at the same time
recognise there is a legitimate analogy between its role and those organisations
that have been recognised as charities. Such an approach would be consistent
with the obligation on members of the Charities Board
to act with honesty,
integrity and in good faith.
C Advancement of education
Counsel for the Board insisted that FF’s publications were of “a
tenacious and polemical character” marked by “indoctrination
or
dissemination of propaganda.”64 Yet the Board was forced to
concede that at least one commissioned report – that by the New Zealand
Institute of Economic Research
(“The Value of Family: Fiscal Benefits of
Marriage and Reducing Family Breakdown in New Zealand”) – contained
significant
original
60 At [99].
61 At [100].
62 Family First, above n 4, at [87].
63 At [89] (emphasis added).
64 At [92]. The Board had used these pejorative expressions in its
deregistration decision: Board at [66], [67] (by implication), [75].
research.65 The Board, said the High Court, must reconsider its
decision in light of this report.66
V Reflections on the Family First case
A The “traditional” or “nuclear” family
In my introduction I suggested that the Charities Board decision in Family First represented an expression of contemporary state antipathy to the “nuclear” family. The nuclear family is a relatively modern construct, for broader or extended forms of family structure have been common throughout recorded human history.
In twenty-first century liberal democracies, the principal flag bearers for
the traditional family are conservative religious communities.
Among theists and
the three global religions of the Book – Judaism, Christianity and Islam
– the family has an elevated
and foundational status.67 This
is shared by the political philosophy of conservatism. Roger Scruton
cautions:68
It hardly needs saying . . . that the support and protection of this
institution [viz, the family] must be central to the conservative
outlook, and
that changes in the law which are calculated to loosen or abolish the
obligations of family life, or which in other
ways facilitate the channeling of
libidinal impulse away from that particular form of union, will be accepted by
conservatives only
under the pressure of necessity. . . The family is the origin
of self-respect, being the first institution through which the social
world is
perceived. It is also autonomous: a form of life which has no aim besides
itself.
The common elements of the major Semitic faith traditions’ conception
of the family are heterosexual parents and the procreation
and
nurture
65 Family First, above n 4, at [93].
66 The author has written a report for FF, subsequent to the Board decision.
Rex Ahdar, Killing Me Softy: Should Euthanasia Be Legalised? (Family First
NZ, 2014) was published in early 2014, https://www.familyfirst.org.nz/
research/killing-me-softly/.
67 See generally Peggy Morgan and Clive Lawton (eds) Ethical Issues in Six
Religious Traditions (Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, 1996) at
143–144 (Judaism); at 185–186 (Christianity) and 232–236 (Islam); Don S
Browning, M Christian Green and John Witte Jr Sex, Marriage and Family
in World Religions (Columbia University Press, New York, 2006). The
Catechism of the Catholic Church [Liberia Editrice Vaticana] (Vatican, 1994)
at para 2202 states: “A man and woman united in marriage together with
children, form a family... It should be considered the normal reference
point by which the different forms of family relationship are to be
evaluated.”
68 The Meaning of Conservatism (revised 3rd ed, St Augustine’s Press, South
Bend, Indiana, 2002) at 129–130.
of the offspring of such lifelong opposite-sex unions. In Catholicism,
for example: 69
It is in the family that the mutual giving of self on the part of man and
woman united in marriage creates an environment of life
in which children
‘develop their potentialities, become aware of their dignity and prepare
to face their unique and individual
destiny.’ ... it proceeds [sic] in
importance and value the functions that society and the State are called to
perform. The
family possesses inviolable rights and finds its legitimization in
human nature and not in being recognized by the State. The family,
then, does
not exist for society or the State, but society and the State exist for the
family.
The “nuclear” nature of the family (father, mother and dependent children) is not as central as the emphasis upon the family as timeless or, the preferred label, “traditional”. Many within Christianity, even conservative Protestantism,70 acknowledge that the nuclear family is neither as traditional nor biblical as conservative Christians maintain. 71
Certainly, the recognition of grandparents and other close kin (uncles, aunts, cousins) within the notion of “family” is widely accepted in other sectors of theism, most notably Islam.
Broader understandings of the family are common in non-Western communities.
In Māori society, “the primary meaning of
‘whanau’—the
one that springs first to mind for native
speakers of Māori—is a group of relatives defined by reference to a
recent ancestor,
comprising several generations, several nuclear families and
several households”.72 Indeed, the very breadth of the whanau
has proved potentially problematic for Māori in the charitable context.
Māori may
jeopardise their eligibility for charitable status by reason that
the beneficiaries of the charity are connected by blood ties (and
other familial
bonds) and thereby prima
69 Pontifical Council for Justice and Peace Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church (United States Catholic Conference of Bishops, Washington DC, 2004) at §§ 212 and 214 (original italics omitted). The quoted sentence is from the Encyclical letter from John Paul II, Centesimus Annus (1 May
1991).
70 See W Bradford Wilcox, Mark Chaves and David Franz “Focused on the
Family? Religious Traditions, Family Discourse, and Pastoral Practice”
(2004) 43 Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 491 at 493. The non-
Evangelical reader may not perceive the pun in the title. James Dobson’s
Focus on the Family organisation is one of the largest and longest running
Evangelical Christian organisations in the United States.
71 See eg Carolyn Osiek “The New Testament and the Family” in Lisa Cahill
and Dietmar Mieth (eds) The Family Concilium 1995/4] (Orbis, Mary Knoll,
NY, 1995) at 1–9. On conservative Christianity generally see Rex Ahdar
Conservative Christians and the Law (Ashgate, Aldershot, 2001).
72 Jacinta Ruru “Kua tut te puehu, kia mau: Māori aspirations and family
law policy” in Henaghan and Atkin, above n 37, 57 at
59.
facie fail the “public benefit” test (which contemplates benefits being
general and indiscriminate in nature).73
In one sense those who support and
promote the traditional family and who adhere to conservative understandings of
sex roles and parenting
will never be deterred by the rulings of a governmental
agency. But organisations that do wish to contribute to public debate and
the
shaping of public policy are vulnerable to legal determinations that curtail
their activities in this kind of endeavour. The
loss of charitable status and
the financial and other benefits it brings is significant. Susan Barker
comments: 74
Most charities that are denied registration struggle to survive: they
struggle to challenge decisions of the regulator . . . ; they
struggle to gain
funding as busy funders rightly or wrongly restrict funding to registered
charities only; they struggle with issues
of confidence and credibility, as the
reasons for having been rejected by their own regulator are difficult to
communicate to their
stakeholders.
One suspects Family First NZ is in this category: it is heavily dependent on giving, with “almost all of its income being derived from donations.“75
It is salutary to see the Supreme Court firmly declaring that the controversial criterion is irrelevant. A brief look at the plethora of registered charities reveal many that have objects that are “controversial” in so far as 21st century “liberal” or “progressive” political and social sensibilities are concerned. Take, for example:
• Family Life International NZ
• Destiny Church Auckland Trust
• Pregnancy Counselling Services
• Society for the Promotion of Community Standards76
• Maxim Institute77
73 Susan Barker, Michael Gousmett and Ken Lord The Law and Practice of Charities in New Zealand (Lexis Nexis NZ, Wellington, 2013) at 406–407; Kerry O’Halloran Charity Law and Social Inclusion: An International Study (Routledge, London, 2007) at 288. Fortunately, the Charities Act 2005, s
5(2)(a) meets this concern: “However,– (a) the purpose of a trust, society, or institution is a charitable purpose under this Act if the purpose would satisfy the public benefit requirement apart from the fact that the beneficiaries of the trust, or the members of the society or institution, are related by blood”.
74 Barker, above n 2, at 87.
75 Family First, above n 4, at [16]. In the 2013 financial year, donations to it
came to $371,138.
76 CC20268, registered 17 December 2007.
77 CC24446, registered 16 May 2008.
Family Life International is a Roman Catholic organisation whose aim is “to promote the full dignity and wonder of human life (from the moment of natural conception to the moment of natural death), of human sexuality, of marriage and family, and to inform and protect kiwi women and their babies from the harm of abortion.”78 Aside from the notorious extravagance of the Destiny Church’s79 leadership, this indigenous Pentecostal church has been an outspoken opponent of gay rights.80
Pregnancy Counselling Services81 is listed on the Pro-Life NZ website and is primarily tasked with counselling women to think seriously about options other than abortion should they want to discontinue their pregnancy.82 The Society for the Promotion of Community Standards, founded by Patricia Bartlett in 1970, and claiming a membership of 21,000 by 1975,83 has been relatively quiet in recent years, but a generation ago it was a regular and vocal critic of the “permissive society” (as it would term it) viz, public nudity and pornography, films and television programmes that portrayed too much violence and sex, the legalisation of prostitution and so on.84 Despite a massive sea change in cultural terms, it still fights the good fight today: “Our ‘fight’ is with those who are perpetually engaged in forcing back the moral boundaries”85. The Maxim Institute is a conservative think tank that champions neo-liberal economic measures (such as combatting welfare dependency), defending parental rights and so on.86
C “Political correctness” at work?
A great deal of the analysis of . . . family problems is couched in terms of
the ‘decline’ or ‘collapse’ of
‘The Family’.
It is only by grasping that “The Family” does not exist, that the
ideological nature of such
analyses can be recognized. . . . ‘The Nuclear
Family’ does not exist except as a powerful image in the minds of most
people. . . . traditional views of ‘The Family’ have been
conservative, racist, classist, and heterosexist. In developing
new forms of
theorizing and a new postmodern sociology of family living, a key strategy is
that of exploring a wide range of values.87
78 From its website: <http://www.fli.org.nz/about> .
79 CC22039, registered 30 June 2008. That Church’s other “branches” at
Wellington, Hamilton, Christchurch and so on were also registered on
that same date.
80 See eg “Protesters hold up Destiny Church march” New Zealand Herald,
7 March 2005. For a (rare) academic analysis see Peter Lineham Destiny:
The Life and Times of a Self-Made Apostle (Penguin, Auckland, 2013).
81 CC2976, registered 30 June 2008.
82 See the Pro-Life NZ website:
<http://prolife.org.nz/pregnancysupport />
83 Laurie Guy, Shaping Godzone: Public Issues and Church Voices in
New Zealand 1840–2000 (Victoria University Press, Wellington, 2001) at
368. 84 Its early years (1970–1995) are recounted in Carolyn Moynihan
A Stand for Decency (SPCS, 1995) and Guy, ibid, ch 18. 85 From its website:
<http://www.spcs.org.nz/about/>
. 86 See is website
<http://www.maxim.org.nz/about_us/overview3.aspx>
. 87 Jon Benards, ”We Must Not Define ‘The
Family’!” in Barbara Settles et al (ed) Concepts and Definitions of the Family for the 21st Century
(Howarth Press, Binghamton, NY, 1991) 21 at 22, 23 and 33. Political correctness is a much used and abused term and I invoke it here
with some trepidation, acknowledging that it “is a
complex, discontinuous,
and protean phenomenon which has changed radically, even over the past two
decades.”88 Nonetheless, I will take as a starting point
Geoffrey Hughes’ broad elucidation that: “Political correctness is
based
on various idealistic assumptions on how society should be run and how
people should behave towards each other.”89 Similarly, Erich
Kolig explains: 90 Political correctness is the self-cleansing mechanism of hegemony, a
palliative of conscience, the practical arm of self-righteousness.
Practically,
it means conforming with meaning-makers and opinion-manufacturers who enjoy
popular currency at the moment. . . . In
a pluralistic and democratic form of
society such as exists in New Zealand, there is at any time a plethora of
opinions and view,
ethical points of view and the like abound. This fact should
neither surprise nor overwhelm. The interesting question is why, in
this
multitudinous mix, do some meaning-makers and some opinions rise to prominence
and, what is more, to social dominance, while
others fail. A “primary idealistic assumption” of political correctness,
contends Hughes, “is that of equality.”91 This is
manifested in myriad ways, but, for present purposes, it leads ineluctably to
pluriform conceptions of the family. To preserve
the equal status and dignity of
persons of different genders, sexual orientations and so on – who come
together to form this
entity – one needs “families”, plural.
As Henaghan notes:92 Based on ideas of equality, non-discrimination and a political assumption of
social expectations, a wide variety of family structure
are being accepted into
the mainstream definition of the legal family, whether they want to be or not.
Such a policy change, as with
all policy changes, is likely to create winners
and losers. In contrast, a single definition that presupposes there is something called
the family is exclusive not inclusive, monolithic not diverse, oppressive
not facilitative. To promote a concept of the family as the
optimal model is dangerously narrow and judgmental, if not downright
anti-social. Modern liberalism’s stance toward the family concurs: the nuclear
family unit of married heterosexual husband and wife and dependent
children
cannot be an exhaustive definition. Invoking liberal philosopher Joseph
Raz’s notion of “value pluralism”,
Andrew Bainham, for
example, argues that this “implies that all those intimate and family
relationships 88 Geoffrey Hughes Political Correctness: A History of
Semantics and Culture (Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester, UK, 2010) at 3. 89 At 21. 90 “Of Condoms, Biculturalism and Political Correctness: The
Maori Renaissance and Cultural Politics in New Zealand” (2000) 46
Paiduma 231 at 246. 91 Hughes, above n 88, at 21. 92 Henaghan, above n 37, at 24. which can be considered valuable should be supported by the state in an
even-handed way. No particular form of relationship or family
arrangement should
be officially promoted.”93 So, for example, same- sex partners
(married or unmarried, with or without children) ought to be considered, in law,
a family.94 As Baroness Hale of Richmond, writing extra-judicially,
observed: “Non-traditional families of so many kinds are so common that
it
is difficult to argue that a proper way to protect the traditional family is to
deny all recognition to other kinds of relationship.”95
Increasingly, legal theorists question the continued right of the state
“to regulate families qua families, and to encourage or discourage
certain kinds of familial relationships.”96 In this vein,
Alice Ristroph and Melissa Murray, for example, mounted a tentative case for
familial “disestablishment”:
in the same way the American state is
constrained under the First Amendment from establishing a religion, it ought to
also be curtailed
from endorsing and supporting a specific vision or model of
the family, such as the “marital, nuclear family”.97 To refer to the family, as Family First do, with loaded epithets such as
“nuclear”, “traditional” and “natural”
is to
provoke irritation, if not anger. Is not “tradition” associated with
Victorian, patriarchal, hierarchical and thus
oppressive forms? The word
“nuclear” even carries an air of odium since – although
clearly not used here in a scientific,
industrial or military sense – it
jars in the ears of enlightened New Zealand citizens wedded to a nuclear-free
society. The
word ”natural” could, in other contemporary contexts,
be a “virtue” word.98 It resonates with a clean, green
and unpolluted environment and foods or products produced therefrom are usually
unhesitatingly prized.
But in the context of domestic and familial structures,
it is a “vice” or taboo word, for it implies that forms other
than
the natural model are perforce “unnatural”. To describe a family
form as unnatural is to pass judgment based on
outdated and bigoted views on
just what marriage, procreation and parenting are all about. VI Conclusion Promoting the traditional nuclear family is not an uncharitable exercise.
That is the way it should be. Furthermore, after the Supreme
Court’s
ruling in Greenpeace, the controversial nature of a charity’s aims
is not a bar ipso facto to its legal recognition. Again, this is a correct
conclusion.
This is an even more sound position given the
vulnerability 93 “Family Rights in the Next Millennium” (2000) 53
Current Legal Problems 471 at 475. 94 See eg Ruthann Robson “Resisting the Family: Repositioning
Lesbians in Legal Theory” (1994) 19 Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and
Society 975 at 975. 95 “Homosexual Rights” [2004] Child & Family LQ 125 at
130. 96 “Disestablishing the Family” (2010) 119 Yale LJ 1236 at
1240. 97 Ibid. 98 Peter Westen “‘Freedom’ and ‘Coercion’
– Virtue Words and Vice Words” of charities whose objectives appear, to liberal minds, to be antiquated and
antediluvian. Conservative organisations overseas have
been wont to cry that
they are the target of officialdom. For example, in the United States, the Tea
Party and other avowedly conservative
non-profit groups, were, it seems, singled
out for scrutiny from the Internal Revenue Service and subjected to an auditing
to ascertain
whether they still merited tax-exempt status.99 Family
First might feel similarly victimised here. However, this case alone is flimsy
evidence to pronounce any such sweeping charge.
Moreover, one only has to note
that that the leading case, Greenpeace, involved a quintessential
“progressive” entity, one situated at the other end of the political
spectrum. Interestingly, the Charities Board in deregistering Family First cited
Re Collier (Deceased) several times.100 It is a shame it did
not also quote this passage from Hammond J:101 All would surely agree that a bequest for bringing about revolution, or
outright disobedience of the law must be illegal; and hence
it could not be
charitable. But once Courts are beyond those concerns, the debate becomes much
more difficult . . . in making decisions
in an area like this, [ie,
‘charitable trusts [being] those for the advocacy of a particular point of
view or ‘propaganda’
trusts as they are sometimes pejoratively
termed’] Judges are, in reality, making decisions about the
‘worth’ of
a particular bequest. The argument is that judges’
views on (say) temperance, or birth control, or euthanasia, do reflect an
assumption as to ‘worth’ and that that affects outcomes. . .
. I have to say that I have considerable sympathy for that viewpoint which
holds that a Court does not have to enter into the debate
at all. . . . Rather,
the function of the Court ought to be to sieve out debates which are for
improper purposes: and to then leave the public debate to lie where it falls,
in the public arena. Family First NZ was put to considerable expense to preserve its charitable
status. “Charities are reluctant litigants”
as Barker, Gousmett and
Lord note, for litigation will typically draw from the precious donated funds
that have been earmarked for
the beneficial tasks these entities have set
themselves.102 At the time of writing, FF still had not received the
benefit of the reassessment by the Charities Board that the High Court
mandated,103 although for now its registration is intact. 99 Juliet Eilpern “IRS targeted groups
critical of government, documents from agency probe show”, Washington
Post, 12 May 2013; Jackie Calmes “Senate Report cites IRS
Mismanagement in Targeting of Tea Party Groups” New York Times, 5
August 2015. 100 Re Collier [1998] 1 NZLR 91 was cited in
the Board decision, above n 9, at footnotes 33, 39, 40, 43, 80 and 107. 101 Re Collier, ibid, at 90 (italics
supplied). The excerpt I have inserted in the square brackets is from the
preceding paragraph at the same page. 102 Barker et al, above n 73, at 701. 103 Email by Bob McCoskrie, National Director of Family First New
Zealand, to author (14 October 2015) (on file with author). A final point. In Aid/Watch the majority of the High Court of
Australia approved the notion that “the generation of lawful means of
public debate”
on a particular subject (in that instance, the
effectiveness of foreign aid in the relief of poverty) was “itself a
purpose
beneficial to the community within the fourth head [of charity] in
Pemsel.”104 In this vein Professor Matthew Harding
observes:105 If the pursuit of political purposes tends to produce a culture of free
political expression and therefore tends to sustain and augment
conditions under
which democratic government can flourish, there are reasons to think that the
pursuit of such purposes by ‘not
for profit’ organisations tends to
make a distinctive contribution to such a culture. The question whether the promotion of the traditional family is worthwhile
should be a matter, as Hammond J said, of public debate
to be left where it
falls, in the public arena. To effectively silence voices in public debate that
are controversial or unfashionable
by deregistering them as a charity is
regrettable, a loss for democratic discourse – and, in the end, a loss for
us
all. 104 Aid/Watch Inc v Commissioner of Taxation
[2010] HCA 42 at [47]. This passage was quoted without comment by the
majority of the Supreme Court in Greenpeace, above n 10, at [67]. 105 Charity Law and the Liberal State (Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 2014) at 191.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/OtaLawRw/2015/11.html