![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Otago Law Theses and Dissertations |
Last Updated: 5 May 2025
Private Nuisance, the Emanation Requirement and Physical Proximity
Ronan VM Comeskey
A
dissertation submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree
of Bachelor of Laws (Honours) at the University of
Otago –
Ōtākou Whakaihu Waka
11 October 2024
Acknowledgements
To Ruby,
thank you for your love and support.
To my family, likewise.
To Associate Professor Maria Hook, thank you for your
sustained encouragement, feedback and time.
To those who attended my
seminar, thank you. In particular, thank you, Dr Lucas Clover-Alcolea, for your
comments.
Last, but not least, to my fellow eighth floor inhabitants,
thank you.
Abstract
A majority of the
Supreme Court of the United Kingdom rejected the idea that emanation is required
for an action to be sustained in
private nuisance. This rejection contrasts with
dicta of the House of Lords and the New Zealand Supreme Court. In the presence
of
much uncertainty, I clarify the precise meaning of emanation and enquire
whether emanation is a requirement in New Zealand’s
law of private
nuisance. I also explain the deficiencies in the “physical invasion
view” of the tort of private nuisance,
and I propose that a more
convincing account of private nuisance focuses on the extraterritorial aspect of
the control that a claimant
exerts by successfully bringing an action against a
defendant in private nuisance. Those cases involving emanations, and those
founding
support for an emanation requirement, appease the more fundamental
concern about ensuring that a claimant cannot exert extraterritorial
control
too far.
Table of Contents
I Introduction
A The Problem: Conflicting Dicta about Emanation
This
contribution addresses dicta concerning a purported emanation requirement of the
private nuisance action. At this stage, note
that conflicting dicta exist as to
whether emanation is a requirement. The United Kingdom Supreme Court’s
recent decision in
Fearn v Tate Gallery disavowed any emanation
requirement. Lord Leggat JSC, writing for the majority, stated that “there
is no requirement that the
interference must be caused by a physical
invasion”.[1]
This is equivalent to rejecting a so-called “emanation
requirement”.[2] The last time
the New Zealand Supreme Court addressed the matter, the majority in Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 described a “requirement for
emanation”,[3]
and it doubted the viability of a claim in private nuisance in that case
“because of lack of
emanation”.[4] In an entirely
unrelated public nuisance context, the Supreme Court in Smith v Fonterra
again appeared to accept that the tort of private nuisance (and by extension
public nuisance) may require
emanation.[5]
This
cursory survey identifies two positions: that emanation is a requirement or
emanation is not a requirement. Following the decision
in Fearn, New
Zealand courts may soon be presented once again with the question of whether
emanation is an element of private
nuisance.[6]
B Roadmap
In Subpart C of this
Part, I explain the features of the tort of private nuisance of greatest
relevance to us here. I will discuss
the meaning of “emanation”,
whether it is a requirement and the requirement’s academic
equivalent—the “physical
invasion view”—in Parts
II–IV. By way of summary, I argue that “emanation” involves
physical invasion
of the claimant’s land, its status as a requirement in
New Zealand law is unclear, but it is inconsistent with some of the
case law and
is otherwise undesirable. Finally, in Part V, I argue that the bipolar
debate—that emanation is or is not a requirement—overlooks
the fact
that, where emanation is present, it effects a more fundamental feature of
private nuisance: physical proximity between
the defendant’s activity and
the claimant’s land.
C Private Nuisance
Private nuisance is
a “tort against
land”.[7]
It is often said that private nuisance protects one’s “right to use
and enjoy their land”.[8] Beyond
this, the tort is contentious and
unclear.[9] It is worth underscoring
and ascertaining some of the elements of private nuisance that I adopt.
A
claimant must prove that the interference is substantial and unreasonable.
Different formulations exist,[10]
but the point is that a court undertakes a threshold enquiry. (For the remaining
Parts, I default to the “substantial and unreasonable”
formulation
for convenience only.) Those interferences causing “material injury to
property” always meet this threshold,
whereas those interferences causing
“sensible personal discomfort” might
not.[11]
The most important factor that bears on whether an interference is substantial
and unreasonable is the character of the locality,
because claimants within
localities of different characters may be expected to tolerate different levels
of
interference.[12]
Other factors relevant to whether an interference meets this threshold include
the presence of
malice[13]
and whether the claimant is overly
sensitive.[14]
A
second feature, implicit in the “maxim” “private nuisance is a
tort against land”, is the requirement that
a plaintiff has a sufficient
interest in the land which is the subject of the
interference.[15] The enquiry is
whether an interference constitutes harm to the land, not its
inhabitants.[16] Thus, in Hunter
v Canary Wharf, some plaintiffs were denied standing to sue for want of not
being mere licensees.[17]
(Hereinafter, I use “proprietor” to refer to someone with a
sufficient interest in land.)
A final, important feature of the tort is the
various standards that, if met, attribute the activity causative of an
interference
(and thus the harm) to the defendant. Defendants have been held
responsible for activities that they
create,[18]
those on their land which they
continue,[19] those on their land
which they
adopt,[20]
those caused directly by their
licensees[21]
and even those committed by their tenant with
authority.[22] Regarding creation,
one of the narrowest answers to the question “Who can be held
responsible?”[23]
is the creator that possesses the land from which the interference
originates.[24] However, the creator
of a nuisance is always liable for it, whether they are a trespasser or licensee
of the private land from which
the nuisance
originates.[25] Further, the origin
of the interference need not be privately owned
land.[26]
Some doubted authority even asserts the possibility of private nuisance
governing interferences originating from the affected
land.[27]
The correct position is that whilst private nuisance is certainly a tort
against land, it is not necessarily a “tort by
land”.[28]
Nolan attributes the error to, amongst other things, a conflation of land which
is not the plaintiff’s with land which is the
defendant’s for the
purpose of distinguishing private nuisance trespass to
land.[29]
II Emanation
To
determine whether emanation is a requirement, it is first necessary to ascertain
the meaning of emanation. In this Part, I demonstrate
that an “emanation
case” is, properly so-called, a case that involves physical
invasion of the claimant’s land. Moreover, the physical invasion must be a
necessary and sufficient condition for
the interference. A case which does not
fit this description is apt to be described as a “non-emanation case. Only
emanation
cases may satisfy an emanation requirement.
A “Emanation” Involves Physical Invasion of the Claimant’s Land
The starting point
is Lord Goff’s dictum in Hunter because our Supreme Court endorsed
it in espousing an emanation requirement in
Wu.[30] In Hunter, the
plaintiffs alleged private nuisance in relation to the defendant’s newly
constructed building that precluded the passage
of television signals to their
land. Deciding that this did not give rise to an actionable interference in
private nuisance, Lord
Goff (with whom Lord Lloyd agreed on this point)
delivered this passage:[31]
... in the absence of an easement, more is required than the mere presence of
a neighbouring building to give rise to an actionable
private nuisance. Indeed,
for an action in private nuisance to lie in respect of interference with the
plaintiff’s enjoyment
of his land, it will generally arise from something
emanating from the defendant’s land. Such emanation may take many
forms—noise,
dirt, fumes, a noxious smell, vibrations, and
suchlike.
Strictly speaking, the elaboration about emanation is
obiter,[32]
because the determination that the interference was non-actionable followed from
the first proposition that one cannot complain about
the mere presence of a
neighbouring building. Lord Lloyd perhaps articulates it best; having already
decided that the interference
was non-actionable because the obstruction of
television signals is never actionable, he offered lack of emanation as
“further precision... in answering the
question”[33] of the
non-actionability of the interference. Moreover, observe that Lord Goff refers
to emanation from the defendant’s land. This is “much the
same” as invasions of the claimant’s
land,[34]
especially since private nuisance is not a “tort by
land”.[35]
In Wu,
after the electronic locks to the common property and the appellant’s unit
were reprogrammed, the respondent made the provision
of new electronic key
access conditional on entering into a management agreement to the effect that
the appellant, unwilling to enter
the agreement, could not access their unit. In
espousing the emanation requirement, the Court also made explicit what Lord Goff
left
vague: the emanated thing must invade the plaintiff’s
land.[36]
It also repeated Lord
Goff’s examples of emanations coming with the ambit of private nuisance:
“noise, dirt, noxious substances
or
vibrations”.[37] The spread of
fire and the “emission” of electromagnetic fields have also properly
been described as
emanations,[38]
because they involved a physical invasion of the claimant’s land. Although
the Supreme Court’s examples may be mostly
characterised as intangible,
tangible things—falling
trees,[39]
human bodies, golf balls, cigarette
butts[40]
and Japanese knotweed,[41] for
example—may constitute emanations. The Wu case did not involve the
physical invasion of the plaintiff’s
land,[42]
and the Court doubted the claim because of lack of
emanation.[43]
Note that
Hunter and Wu are cases bearing on an emanation
requirement, and we will return to these cases, amongst others, to
ascertain the extent to which an emanation requirement
exists.[44]
B What Emanation is not: “Metaphorical” Emanation
In this Subpart, I
address an interpretation of emanation inconsistent with Lord Goff’s
dictum. Emanation, in one sense, describes
the familiar, physical phenomena that
were the subject of the preceding Subpart: “[s]omething emitted or
radiated by a material
object; esp[ecially] applied to impalpable things, as
light, a magnetic or electric effluvium, [or] an
odour”.[45] Alternatively,
“emanation” (literally) means “[t]he process of flowing
forth, issuing, or proceeding from anything as a
source.”[46] To emanate, in
this second context, means “[t]o flow forth, issue [or] originate from a
person or thing as a
source.”[47]
It is this
second meaning of emanation which is its “metaphorical” meaning. If
pressed to accept the proposition that
“emanation” is an element of
the private nuisance action, Mann J of the High Court of England and Wales would
have accepted
that the interference in issue in Fearn—a
“gaze” or an “intense visual intrusion” from a
neighbour’s viewing platform—constituted
an emanation: “it may
be metaphorical to say that a gaze emanates in the same way as a noise or a
smell, but in my view the
metaphor is compelling in these
circumstances”.[48]
If we analyse Hunter through this lens, we might say that the
obstruction of television signals constituted that which
“metaphorically” emanated
by flowing forth from the
defendant’s land to the claimants’ land. Indeed, Lords Goff and
Cooke considered that Hunter involved what the German Bundesgerichtshof,
in another case involving the obstruction of television signals, called
“negative
Immissionen” (negative
effects).[49] These negative effects
are what metaphorically emanated from the defendant’s building. However,
as above, Hunter is a non-emanation case. Lord Goff’s dictum is
about the physical quality of the thing transported, and it does not include
“metaphorical emanation” or the transmission of “negative
effects”. As much as “metaphorical emanation”
may sidestep the
potential injustices flowing from Lord Goff’s dictum in
Hunter,[50] his dictum cannot
be understood in these terms.
C What Emanation is not: the Wu Confusion
The Supreme Court in
Wu adopted Lord Goff’s dictum, and to the extent that Wu
stands for the proposition that Lord Goff’s dictum is good law (and
relies on a proper interpretation of Lord Goff’s dictum),
it is relevant
to this
contribution.[51]
However, there exists another part of the Supreme Court’s reasoning.
It conflated emanation—the physical quality of the
interference—with the origin of the interference. The Supreme Court
stated:[52]
The requirement for emanation stems from the maxim sic utere tuo ut
alienum non laedas (enjoy your own property in such a manner as not
to injure that of another person). Thus, in order to sustain an action for
private nuisance, “it must
be proved not only that the plaintiff’s
use of his land has been interfered with but also that the defendant
maintained on his land a harmful state of affairs which caused that
interference.”
The maxim is
vague,[53] and it is the subject of
criticism.[54]
Moreover, David Neild rightly suggested that it is unclear how any emanation
requirement follows from the
maxim.[55]
Recall that the defendant in Hunter built a building on its land.
The phrase “from the defendant’s land” in Lord Goff’s
dictum—“[an action] will generally arise
from something emanating
from the defendant’s
land”[56]—is therefore
superfluous. Lord Goff’s emphasis was on the form which the
emanation takes which must, in general, be some physical
phenomenon.[57]
The Supreme Court, although purporting to adopt Hunter, misconstrued
emanation—something speaking to the physical quality of an
interference—with the origin of the interference
being the
defendant’s land. The emanation concept can only tell us that an origin
exists, but it cannot tell us anything more
particular about the origin.
The
Supreme Court’s understanding of emanation—that is, that emanation
says something about the origin of the interference—is related to
the metaphorical notion of emanation in the preceding Subpart. Justice Asher (of
the High
Court) in Wu decided that
provided:[58]
... the plaintiff does not have exclusive control over the area from which
the nuisance emanates, there appears to be no restriction
on the place from
which a nuisance must emanate.
Whether or not Asher J was correct about
there being no such
restrictions,[59] his Honour
correctly identified that all interferences emanate in the
metaphorical sense from their
origin.[60] It is best to not
use the words “emanation” or “emanate” to describe this
concept; it culminated in Court
of Appeal in Wu stating that Hunter
“was concerned with [an] interference that had emanated from a
source outside of the [claimants’]
property.”[61] This is, of
course, a misrepresentation of Hunter.
Consider Guppys v
Brookling for a straightforward illustration of the difference between
emanations (involving physical invasions) and “metaphorical”
emanations (bearing on the origin of an interference). In that case, the
defendant landlord, to remove their tenant, took steps to
render the land
uninhabitable including disconnecting utilities and making access
difficult.[62]
A “thing”, being an obstruction, metaphorically emanated from
outside the plaintiff’s land into the plaintiff’s
land, but the case
did not involve the physical invasion of the plaintiff’s land, and so it
is a non-emanation
case.[63]
D Not All Cases Involving Physical Invasion are Emanation Cases
We return to the
understanding that emanation involves physical invasion. The purpose of this
Subpart is to establish that not every
case that involves a physical
invasion is an emanation case—that is, a case that might meet an emanation
requirement. There is no consensus in
the literature or the case law as to what
cases involving physical invasions are properly characterised as
emanation cases, and so I seek to provide clarity in this Subpart. In
particular,
we will see that two cases, Thompson-Schwab v Costaki and
BNZ v
Greenwood,[64]
plague this disagreement. Moreover, the framework introduced here will help us
carefully distinguish emanation and non-emanation
cases for the remainder of
this contribution.
An emanation case involves a physical invasion that
is a necessary and sufficient condition for the interference. A
physical invasion is necessary for the interference if, without it, there is
nothing of which the
claimant may complain. A physical invasion is sufficient
if, by itself, it may constitute a “substantial and
unreasonable” interference. A case involving physical invasions might fail
to be
an emanation case for want of necessity or sufficiency.
1 Necessity
Recall that Fearn
involved an intense visual intrusion from neighbouring land. The defendant
in that case operated a viewing platform, and it invited
guests onto the
platform who looked at, peered into, waved at and photographed the
claimants’ luxury, glass-walled
apartments.[65] Contrary to the
understanding of emanation introduced in this Subpart, Mann J (in addition to
that discussed in Subpart B, above)
characterised the interference in Fearn
in this way:[66]
If the sight of something on the defendant’s land can give rise to a
nuisance claim as in Thompson-Schwab v Costaki..., then it should be
noted that part of the privacy claim could be founded on the fact that the
claimants find it oppressive to see the watchers watch them.
In
Costaki, the complaint was about the defendant using their land for
prostitution.[67] It has therefore
been described as an “affront”
case,[68]
because the interference constitutes one of offence. Some suggest it is a
non-emanation case.[69] However,
Douglas and McFarlane observe that the visibility of the defendant’s
premises, “which necessarily requires the passing of light rays
over the claimant’s land”, means that Costaki is an emanation
case by invasion of
light.[70]
The
Court’s decision in Costaki indicates that the cause of the
interference was considered to be the knowledge of the use of nearby
land—the affront—more
so than the mere existence of the
plaintiff’s line of sight to the
activities.[71] The Court of Appeal
ordered injunctive relief prohibiting the use of the premises for prostitution
“in the manner complained
of by the plaintiffs [the residents of 8
and 13 Chesterfield Street] in this action or otherwise so as to cause a
nuisance to the plaintiffs or either of
them”,[72] even though the
evidence only showed that the defendants’ activities “force[d]
themselves upon the sense of sight at least of the residents in No.
13.”[73] Whilst Douglas and
McFarlane are correct that a line of sight necessitates an invasion by light, a
line of sight itself, and thus
a physical invasion, was not considered necessary
in that case. Without any physical invasion, the claimant still had something to
complain about. Costaki is therefore a non-emanation
case.
Greenwood involved a dazzling glare created by the interaction
of sunlight and the defendant’s
building.[74]
Some suggest it is a non-emanation
case,[75] but like Costaki,
the case involved light “invading” the plaintiff’s
land.[76]
Unlike in Costaki, the invasion of light formed a necessary (and
sufficient) component of the invasion, for in its absence, there could be no
interference.
Greenwood is an emanation
case.[77]
Fearn is a non-emanation case because the cause of the complaint was
the interference with the plaintiff’s privacy, notwithstanding
that the
claimants could see those overlooking their
apartments.[78] If there existed a
one-way window between the claimants’ and defendant’s land
permitting light to enter the defendant’s
viewing platform and forbidding
light to enter the claimants’ land (thereby precluding light from the
defendant’s platform
invading the claimants’ apartments), Mann
J’s affirmative finding as to the potential actionability of the
interference
ought to have been the
same.[79] Notice that if the
defendant in Greenwood implemented a one-way window, the outcome of the
case would have differed.
2 Sufficiency
A non-physical
interference (an affront or obstruction, for example) that involves a physical
invasion will not ordinarily be an emanation
case because the invasion will not
ordinarily meet the sufficiency condition. Take, for example, a claimant who
suffers an obstructed
view and pleads their case on the basis that light,
reflected from the obstruction, is physically invading their
land.[80] If the physical component
of the interference sufficed, by itself, to be a private nuisance, then
all activities situated within the line of sight of my land are substantially
and unreasonably interfering
with my land and are thereby causing a private
nuisance against
me.[81]
This ought not to be the case.
The sufficiency condition is, I admit,
elusive. Let us work through a final example, the Indianian case Wernke v
Halas. In that case, a toilet “seat and lid [were] affixed to a piece
of blue plywood with a painted brown spot” facing the
claimant’s
land.[82]
Unlike in Costaki, there is no doubt that the case involved an
invasion by light. Moreover, unlike in Fearn, the physical invasion was a
necessary condition for the interference; if the claimants could not have
seen the “tasteless decoration”, they would have had
nothing to
complain about. But the physical invasion falls short of being sufficient
because the complaint was that the toilet seat
constituted an “aesthetic
annoyance”,[83] and the
allegation relied on the claimants’ aesthetic displeasure to be
“substantial and
unreasonable”.[84] Wernke
is a non-emanation
case.[85]
E Conclusion: The Meaning of Emanation
Toward determining
whether emanation is and should be a requirement of private nuisance in
the following Parts, we now know with certainty what an emanation case is: (a)
it involves something crossing into the boundary of the
claimant’s land; (b) the thing has certain physical
characteristics; and (c) the physical thing is both a necessary and
sufficient condition for the interference. Any emanation requirement says
nothing of the origin of the interference.
III The Status and Nature of an Emanation “Requirement”
The question of
whether emanation is a requirement, and also the nature of any emanation
requirement, is more nuanced than its cursory
treatment in Part I. In this Part,
I build on our examination of Hunter and Wu to the extent they
espouse an emanation requirement. I also consider some subsequent
treatment of these cases.
A Hunter, Some Illustrations and Wu
Lord Goff in
Hunter provided that a private nuisance “generally arise[s]
from something emanating”.[86]
Moreover, he squared the successfully pleaded non-emanation cases on the basis
that they are “so
offensive”,[87] and his
Lordship specified that such non-emanation cases must be “relatively
rare”.[88] It appears that
Lord Goff envisaged that emanation cases are generally actionable, whereas
non-emanation cases are actionable only
if they meet some threshold of
offensiveness. We know what sort of cases meet that first test; they are the
cases properly described
as “emanation cases” according to Part II.
It therefore is apt to turn to the meaning of those “relatively
rare”
cases.
Justice Burnton in Anglian Water v Crawshaw Robbins
considered that those “relatively rare” cases were apt to be
described as
“exceptional”,[89] and
his Honour utilised Lord Goff’s dictum in an entirely proper
way:[90]
... the negligent interruption of a supply of gas by a third party is not
actionable as a private nuisance. It does not involve an
invasion of any
substance or form of energy on to [sic] the claimant’s land. It is not one
of the exceptional cases of liability
in nuisance without such an invasion. A
home owner [sic] or tenant does not have a property right in the supply of gas.
His or her
protection lies in his or her rights against the gas
supplier.
Justice Burnton (a) enquired into whether the case was an
emanation case then, (b) having concluded it was not an emanation case,
considered whether it was an exceptional case. Given Burnton J’s brief
analysis in answering the second question, I surmise
that his Honour considered
whether the case belonged within one of the established categories of
non-emanation cases.
Indeed, this was the approach of Kenneth Martin J of
the Supreme Court of Western Australia in Shogunn v Public Transport
Authority. His Honour decided (a) that the modification of road markings
reducing the accessibility of the claimant’s premises was a
non-emanatory
interference and (b) that the case was not actionable because the
claimant’s case did not fit the relevant category of non-emanation
cases,[91] being the
“picketing”
cases.[92]
In
Onus v Telstra, Price J of the Supreme Court of New South Wales also
adopted Lord Goff’s approach and applied it sensibly by (a) deciding
that
the mere construction of the defendant’s mobile network tower did not
constitute an emanation and (b) justifying why, nonetheless, the case was
a “special” actionable one, because of the serious risk to the life
of users of the nearby
airfield.[93]
Justice Price’s approach is more flexible than the one that seeks to
categorise non-emanation cases.
Before the Wu case came before the
courts, Frater J of the New Zealand High Court in Harbourcity v Owen
described emanation as a “necessary link” and did not
consider whether the non-emanatory interference in that case—the loss of
development potential of the
claimant’s land—came within Lord
Goff’s exception.[94]
The
Supreme Court in Wu adopted Lord Goff’s dictum in Hunter
(notwithstanding the Wu confusion), and it articulated it in terms of
emanation being a
requirement:[95]
For an action for private nuisance to be sustained on the basis of
interference with the use or enjoyment of land, some emanation
of the effect of
the nuisance from the defendant’s land to the plaintiff’s land is
usually required. There may be circumstances where the “activities
on the defendant’s land are in themselves so offensive to neighbours
as to
constitute an actionable nuisance”. However, those circumstances will be
“rare”.
Moreover, those rare cases were, to the Court, a
“category of
cases”,[96] and so it would
appear to endorse the less flexible approach to Lord Goff’s
dictum.
B Subsequent Consideration in New Zealand and the United Kingdom
The Court of Appeal
in BEMA v Body Corporate 366611 stated of the dicta in Wu
that “[t]o say that emanation is usual is to recognise that it may not
always be
necessary.”[97]
The dispute in BEMA arose from, for our purposes, the same circumstances
as in Wu.[98] Even though the
Supreme Court doubted that the refusal to afford the appellant access
constituted an actionable interference in private
nuisance “because
of lack of emanation” “in the sense used in the
caselaw”,[99] the BEMA
Court came to the opposite conclusion simply because emanation is not
always necessary.[100]
These
positions are irreconcilable. The Supreme Court purported to use lack of
emanation as a reason for doubting the private nuisance claim. The
BEMA Court did not consider either step of the Hunter
analysis.[101] Both
Courts’ dicta are, strictly speaking, unbinding because they preferred to
resolve the respective cases in
trespass.[102] Since both Courts
derived their position from an uncritical acceptance and surface-reading of
Hunter,[103] neither should
be considered particularly persuasive.
The Court of Appeal has further
considered an emanation requirement since its decision in BEMA. In
Nottingham Forest v Unison
Networks,[104] the Court made
sure to justify that falling trees were emanations despite being tangible,
unlike the intangible interferences paradigmatic
of private
nuisance.[105] The Court of Appeal
could have avoided the question by citing BEMA. It instead cited
Wu; it described emanation as “a traditional requirement”;
and it labelled the BEMA Court’s contributions as
“reservations on the emanation
requirement”.[106]
Given the Court decided the case was an emanation case, it did not need to
determine the definitive existence or nature of an emanation
requirement.
In
the United Kingdom, lack of emanation is no longer a reason to deny a claim
because, according to the majority of the Supreme Court
in Fearn,
“[a]nything short of direct trespass on the claimant’s land
which materially interferes with the claimant’s enjoyment of rights in
land is capable of being a
nuisance.”[107] Even though
the non-emanatory interference in Fearn was considered capable of being a
nuisance, those who suppose that emanation is a requirement may still well argue
that a claimant’s
“rights in land” are, or ought to be,
limited as much as possible to excluding
emanations,[108] notwithstanding
Lord Leggat’s insistence that “there is no requirement that the
interference must be caused by a physical
invasion”.[109]
The
minority also considered that “intense visual intrusion”, although
being non-emanatory, is capable of being an actionable
nuisance without
displacing Lord Goff’s dictum. Instead, for the minority, such an
intrusion comes within Lord Goff’s
“relatively rare”
exception.[110] Given there
existed no established authority about the actionability of interferences
against privacy interests via
overlooking,[111]
we see here a more flexible interpretation of Lord Goff’s exception,
notwithstanding that Lord Sales JSC described Fearn as belonging within
the exceptional “category” of cases.
C Emanation may or may not be a Requirement
The position in New
Zealand is uncertain because our leading authorities are obiter and conflicting.
On the approach taken in Hunter and adopted in Wu, actionable
non-emanation cases brought “on the basis of interference with use or
enjoyment of land” require some additional
justification. This
justification likely comes in the form of fitting the case at hand with the
established, actionable non-emanatory
interferences. On the BEMA
approach, that a case is an emanation case is wholly irrelevant to the
analysis.
IV The “Physical Invasion View” Should be Rejected
We now explore the
academic claim that private nuisance only governs, or ought to only govern,
physical invasions. This is so that
we can appreciate what a court does
when it claims that emanation is a (general) requirement for liability in
private nuisance. Nolan calls this claim the “physical
invasion
view” of the tort.[112] I
adopt this terminology for the remaining Parts. For our purposes, the physical
invasion view is concerned with physical invasions
to the extent that they are
emanations within the meaning ascertained in Part II (and so captured by any
emanation requirement as
ascertained in Part
III).[113]
The gist of the
physical invasion view is that a proprietor’s rights are limited to being
able to exclude physical things from
entering the physical boundaries of their
land.[114] So, it goes, an
interference with the use or enjoyment of land is only an actionable nuisance if
the defendant is responsible for
something crossing into the plaintiff’s
land.[115]
In the following Subparts, I analyse different aspects of the physical invasion
view and critique it.
A Rights in Land
When, on a physical
invasion view, can we say that a proprietor’s land is interfered with?
McBride supposed, in explaining the
physical invasion view, that “[i]n the
absence of a physical interference with your land, or a right attached to your
land,
nothing has happened to your
land”[116] This begs the
question “What is your land?” In this Subpart and the next,
we will see that the answer given by the physical invasion view is unduly
restrictive.
1 Claims to exclude and freedoms to use
A landholder has a
right to exclude things from their
land.[117] Thus, claimants have
succeeded in bringing trespass claims against others for entering and crossing
over their land[118] and
projecting objects into the airspace above their
land.[119] The Court of Appeal
recently catalogued many examples of things which a claimant can exclude from
their land in trespass: cars; spoil,
debris and litter from gutters;
firecrackers, stones, earth and rubbish; bathing machines; hunting dogs; and
creepers growing over
a
gutter.[120] To the proponent of
the physical invasion view, private nuisance protects the same
right,[121] and so landholders may
bring an action against another responsible for foul-smelling
particles,[122]
smoke,[123]
dust[124] or
noise[125] entering their land.
Douglas and McFarlane specify that although private nuisance purports to protect
claimants’ “right
to use and enjoy their
land”,[126] their
“right to use” is protected only indirectly to the extent that a
claimant’s legally recognised “right
to exclude” is
violated.[127]
The
difference, according to Douglas and McFarlane, is that whilst a landholder is
certainly free to use their land (this freedom describing their
“right to use”), they may claim to exclude things from
their land (this claim describing their “right to
exclude”).[128] Rights
(freedoms) to use do not oblige any other person to behave in any particular
way; they only protect the proprietor from complaint
or challenge in relation to
a particular use.[129] Conversely,
rights (claims) to exclude oblige others to refrain from including in
another’s land themselves or things for which they are responsible
(Douglas and McFarlane
say that we must not “physically interfere”
with another’s land).[130]
This is what, for the remainder of this contribution, I mean by
“freedom” and “claim” in relation to rights
to use and
rights to exclude.[131]
A
private nuisance claim in an emanation case often arises at the intersection of
a defendant landholder’s right to use and
a claimant landholder’s
right to exclude.[132] Whilst the
former is free to emit physical entities from their land, the claimant
may claim to stop them when the emanation constitutes a substantial and
unreasonable
interference with the use or enjoyment of their
land.[133]
The difference
between rights to use and rights to exclude in a non-emanation case is best
illustrated by Fearn. Consider first the claimants’ rights. In Part
II, we established that the Tate Gallery was not responsible for anything
emanating
into the claimants’ land. From the physical invasion view, such
an interference cannot constitute an actionable nuisance. The
same can be said
of the other non-emanation cases: Hunter, Wu, BEMA,
Costaki and
Guppys.[134] But the
claimants in Fearn succeeded; they therefore had a claim to
something; and so on the physical invasion view the case was wrongly
decided.[135]
Their claim did not arise from the right to
exclude.[136] Instead, the Court
directly protected their freedom to use with a claim to
use.[137] Indeed, Lord Leggat
JSC purported to do exactly that, not only for non-emanation cases but for the
tort of private nuisance as a
whole:[138]
Frequently, such interference is caused by something emanating from land
occupied by or under the control of the defendant which physically
invades the
claimant’s land. ... In all such [emanation] cases, however, the
basis of the claim is not the physical invasion itself but the resulting
interference with the utility or amenity value of the claimant’s
land.
As the dispute was one between proprietors, consider, too, the
defendant’s rights. The Tate Gallery’s freedom to use its
land for
its own purposes did not protect it from the claimant’s complaint
because the complaint was about an actionable nuisance. This may be
contrasted with the position in Hunter where their Lordships articulated
the defendant’s activity in terms of their “freedom to build”,
thereby (in the
absence of any emanation) insulating the defendant from
liability for obstructing the passage of television
signals.[139]
2 An anomaly in this framework
That this
exclusion-based model of private nuisance is flawed may be proved by
counterexample. We have seen counterexamples. Recall,
for example, Costaki
BEMA, Guppys and the picketing
cases.[140] Indeed, commentators
have pointed out that there are many such counterexamples; the private nuisance
action protects, amongst other
non-emanatory interferences, withdrawal of
lateral support, diversion of a stream, interference with acquired
rights[141] and, in the United
States, unsightly activities (despite Wernke) and spite
fences.[142]
My focus here is
on a particularly problematic type of case—conditions affecting the
temperature of the claimant’s land—that
undermines the model of the
physical invasion view. It is first necessary to discuss some background.
Bagshaw proposes a more capacious
requirement than emanation, being
“behaviour having an effect that alters the physical condition of the
claimant’s premises”.
This includes “negative
emanations” and “energy
transfers”.[143] By
“negative emanations”, Bagshaw does not refer to the transmission of
“negative
Immissionen”.[144] Rather,
Bagshaw refers to those physical things which “emanate” from
the claimant’s land to somewhere else.
With that background,
conditions which cause the plaintiff’s land to become unbearably cold
cause an interference that is a
combination of the two of Bagshaw’s
categories; it is a “negative energy transfer” because these
conditions cause
heat energy to “emanate” from the
claimant’s
land.[145]
Are we to suppose that an interference which causes the plaintiff’s land
to be unbearably hot may be
actionable,[146] whereas the
withdrawal of heat from the plaintiff’s land cannot be actionable?
No.[147] Towards impugning Douglas
and McFarlane’ model, are we to suppose that the claimant in the latter
case exercises an ordinary
“right to exclude” heat, whereas, in the
former, they are asserting some “claim to use” the heat? I
argue the answer is no. It is strained to describe “heating up” as
an ordinary emanation case
and “cooling down” as a
“rare” exception, as going to the limit of the law of private
nuisance, as “so
offensive” or as
unusual.[148] Whilst there is
certainly a physical distinction between the process of “heating
up” and “cooling down” the claimant’s land, this
physical
distinction must not affect the normative basis of the
complaint. Property is not
physics![149] We must reject the
exclusionary basis of the physical invasion view. In both cases, the claimant is
simply seeking to control the
action of the defendant from land that is not
theirs, and this concept leads quite neatly into our next topic of
discussion.
B A Landholder’s Space
We now appreciate
the difference between a landholder’s “right to use” and
“right to exclude” on the
physical invasion view. In particular, we
see that a central thread on this view is treating rights to exclude as
enforceable claims,
whilst treating rights to use land as mere freedoms.
However, it is not sufficient to investigate just a theory of rights because
“the right to exclude others implies something to exclude
from.”[150]
For example, one of its earliest academic proponents, Epstein, described this
“thing” in the following
terms:[151]
Once acquired, the ownership of things is subject to the same entitlements
and limitations as the ownership of the person. With land,
for example, boundary
lines have the same hard-edged quality as foul lines in baseball, while the ad
coelum rule defines (within
limits) the interest in the subsoil below and the
airspace above.
We cease talking about a theory of rights, and we begin
talking about the “field” or “space” over which they
apply.[152] We can now investigate
what one’s land—one’s “object” or
“thing”—is under a physical
invasion view of the tort. The
gist of the physical invasion view is that a landholder’s rights apply, as
intimated by Epstein,
over a three-dimensional space defined by the ad coelum
rule. Moreover, the ideas introduced in this Subpart will become of central
importance in Part V when we discuss how private nuisance
is concerned with
physically proximate interferences. As I intimated at the end of the
preceding Subpart, I argue that private nuisance is about extending (by
some distance) their control to outside that thing.
1 The physical invasion view: a “hard-edged”, three-dimensional space
The ad coelum
rule specifies that a landholder’s interest as such exists within the
boundary of their plot of land, extended vertically both
upward and downward to
encompass a three-dimensional
volume.[153]
More importantly, the ad coelum rule facilitates the logic of the right
to exclude; that is, it distributes all points of space to zero people or
one person (or group of persons) to permit no more than one person (or one group
of persons)
to exclude the world at large from said point of
space.[154]
Trespass
relies on the ad coelum rule to define a qualifying
invasion.[155]
The slightest crossing
suffices.[156] The ad coelum
rule necessarily lends meaning to the tort of private nuisance, as it does
with trespass, by identifying at which point land is physically
invaded on the
physical invasion view.[157]
However, it is important here to note that a landholder’s space, as it is
cognisable to the torts of trespass and private nuisance,
is defined by the ad
coelum rule (or some similar boundary-forming distributive rule), only on
the assumption that trespass and private nuisance recognise only a right
to exclude. That is, the ad coelum rule’s agenda in the torts of trespass
and private nuisance is to provide an answer to the distributive problem,
described above, introduced by the exclusion
right.[158] Indeed, the ad
coelum rule is itself just one possible normative answer to the
distribution of space
problem.[159]
2 Critique and the superior view: their normative space
The
“thing”, then, that is capable of being interfered with is, on the
physical invasion view, the three-dimensional object
defined by the ad coelum
rule. Douglas and McFarlane are quite explicit about this, for they use the
phrase “thing” and “physical thing”
interchangeably.[160] The reason
that this is important for the physical invasion view is because it provides the
view some rhetorical finesse.[161]
It likens, as did Epstein, one’s land’s integrity with one’s
bodily
integrity[162]—private
nuisance is a tort against
land,[163] and without a physical
invasion, “nothing has happened to your
land”.[164] However, as
established, this “thing” is merely a consequence of assuming that
private nuisance does only or should only
protect one’s interest in
excluding others from something. It is therefore simply a rearticulation of the
point addressed in
Subpart A.
Ben Ohavi gives a more convincing account of
the “thing” that is the subject of the proprietor’s rights
that encompasses
what Douglas and McFarlane might call a “right to
use”:[165]
A better way to understand nuisance is to see it as a reflection of the idea
that ownership rights sometimes extend beyond the physical confines of
the property. So, even if I do not physically invade your premises [your
“physical thing”], I still might invade your
normative
space.
But we may go further. Claims brought in private nuisance in
relation to both what Douglas and McFarlane would call the right to exclude
and
the right to use share the same fundamental quality in that they effect
“control over actions that occur outside the
three-dimensional space if they unreasonably interfere with [the
claimant’s] ability to determine how things will be as
between
[themselves] and others with regard to that
space.”[166] That is, the
claim in both cases is that the defendant, upon premises that are not the
claimant’s, act or not act in a particular
way (or that they were wrong to
act or not act in a particular way). So, when the claimant in Sturges v
Bridgman successfully sought an injunction in relation to the noise and
vibrations emanating from the defendant’s
premises,[167] the effect of the
injunction was to control the defendant on land that was not the
claimant’s. The same is true of the claimant
who successfully sought an
interim injunction in Costaki, a non-emanation
case.[168] Indeed, the same is
true of the claimant who seeks to prevent the defendant from heating up their
land and again of the claimant
who seeks to prevent the defendant from cooling
down their land.[169]
What
private nuisance is really about, then, is enabling proprietors to exert
control, not within the three-dimensional space defined
by the ad coelum
rule, but within some normative space that exceeds their plot of
land.[170] When we realise that
the essential components of private nuisance are (a) control (b) over some
distance, any emanation requirement
loses meaning. The essential questions
become whether a proprietor’s right extends to the origin of the
interference, and then whether the activity is of a kind that the claimant can
(or should) control. Moreover, we see that the “thing” that
private nuisance protects is not some three-dimensional space; in all cases,
it
is one’s normative space that exceeds the boundary of their land. In Part
V, I address the issue of how far someone’s
“normative space”
extends.
C Distinguishing Trespass
1 Merrill’s distinction
If
private nuisance protects against emanations, then it looks a lot like trespass.
Merrill believes that property is primarily about
exclusion,[171] and so private
nuisance, to Merrill, redresses wrongful inclusions by way of
emanation.[172]
Merrill has worked to distinguish trespass and private nuisance on a physical
invasion view of the tort. His distinction has gained
support from other
proponents of the physical invasion view, including Douglas and
McFarlane.[173]
Merrill’s
distinction is based on the “dimensions” of the physical thing
constituting the interference. Invasions
by tangible particles—particles
visible to the naked eye at rest—are governed by trespass, whereas other
physical invasions
may only constitute private
nuisances.[174] To fit the
doctrinal distinction between the torts, Merrill has tactically described this
difference as between those invasions “massive
enough” to displace a
landholder’s possession of (part of) their land and those that are
merely annoying.[175] This is
supposedly important because the tangibility test isolates invasions with
certain characteristics, which, to Merrill, set
the scene for low transaction
cost scenarios:[176]
The source of things large enough to be visible to the naked
eye—buildings, cars, boulders, flooding, and so forth—is
relatively
easy to trace, and hence both the party responsible for the intrusion and
the parcels subject to the intrusion should be easy to match. Moreover,
since
visible things are generally not carried for long distances, disputes
over such intrusions are likely to involve smaller numbers of
parties—typically adjacent landholders. Finally, in contrast to
interferences involving invisible agents—gas, noise, halfway
houses, and
so forth—interferences involving visible things are probably more likely
to involve problems that can be solved
without the need for some long-term
monitoring or enforcement mechanisms.
2 Critique and New Zealand’s distinction
It is unclear why
Douglas and McFarlane have adopted Merrill’s distinction as they do not
necessarily seek to explain the law
in terms of transaction costs. Moreover, a
proponent of the physical invasion view is not necessarily committed to this
particular
distinction.[177] It
would appear that Douglas adopts the distinction to shore up the physical
invasion view by showing that private nuisance “is
based upon the same
physical boundary crossing as that found in trespass” and that,
therefore, private nuisance is merely an extension of trespass to
intangible, yet still physically invading,
interferences.[178] That private
nuisance protects from physical invasions follows from the fact that it is
“mini trespass”;[179]
it performs the same function as trespass in slightly different contexts.
However, Merrill, like other proponents of a physical invasion
view, merely
asserts the proposition that private nuisance is concerned only with the
exclusion of physical entities. Exclusion is
axiomatic.[180] So whilst
Merrill’s tangibility distinction might explain the
consequence of a physical invasion view, the distinction ought not be
relied on for the axiomatic proposition, lest we argue in circles.
It has
been suggested that in New Zealand concurrent liability in both trespass and
private nuisance for an interference is
possible.[181] However, the case
founding such a conclusion,
BEMA,[182] is a
non-emanation case, and it is possible that there still exists a sharp
distinction in emanation
cases.[183] For example, in
Nottingham Forest—the post-BEMA, tree-falling
case—the Court of Appeal articulated the distinction in the following way:
“it is that trespass to land relates
to direct intrusions upon land
by a defendant, whereas private nuisance deals with indirect or
consequential interferences with land affecting a plaintiff’s right to
use or enjoy it.”[184] Any
such distinction was not followed in Austin v Rentrezi where
“significant factual overlap” caused Wylie J to consider a mixed bag
of emanations and non-emanations—including
obstructing a right of way,
disconnection of various
utilities,[185] noise, vibration,
debris and dirt, dust—jointly under (successfully pleaded) causes of
action in trespass and private
nuisance.[186] On a physical
invasion view of the tort, the non-emanatory interferences would be excluded
from consideration and the emanatory interferences,
strictly speaking, ought to
have been considered distinctly depending on whether they were direct or
indirect.
If New Zealand courts are to clarify the distinction, they might be
guided by Nolan’s distinction which treats emanation and
non-emanation
cases differentially:[187]
... (1) if no person or physical object crosses the boundary of the
claimant’s land, then the interference is indirect [and
so governed by
private nuisance]; and (2) where there is a projection of a physical object onto
the claimant’s land, the interference
is direct [and so governed by
trespass] if the act of the defendant was unlawful from the beginning, but
indirect [and so governed
by private nuisance] if the act of the defendant was
initially lawful, but led afterwards to an invasion of the claimant’s
rights.
D No “Free” Rights!
1 The concern
One
of the primary concerns of proponents of the physical invasion view of the tort
is, as intimated by Lord Goff, the improper acquisition
of easements or other
rights in relation to another’s
land.[188] Take, for example,
Wright’s articulation of the
concern:[189]
As with the trespass action, the significant interference with the
plaintiff’s interest in the use and enjoyment of land that
is required for
a private nuisance action must result from a... physical invasion of some entity
(for a nuisance, an intangible entity)
across the borders of the
plaintiff’s land. Otherwise a property owner would be able to acquire
easements for unobstructed views or the flow of (light, radio, television,
telephone, internet, etc) waves across others’ property without the
consent of the owners of the other property and without paying for the
easements.
2 Critique
The concern is
circular. It is inevitably the case that claimants unjustly acquire free,
additional and non-consensual rights when,
by assumption, a claimant only
has a right to exclude physical entities from entering their land. And if the
physical invasion view’s neat,
exclusionary framework fails to account for
the justice meted out in the cases, then such a contradiction says more about
the injustice
of the physical invasion view than the neatness (or lack thereof)
in the case
law.[190]
In
cases where we are concerned with giving landholders free easements—that
is, cases involving nearby landholders as such—Wright’s
concern is
tempered because all landholders have roughly equivalent rights in relation to
each other, coloured by the character of
the neighbourhood. Epstein calls this
“implicit in-kind
compensation”:[191]
Suppose that owners A through Z each have identical plots of
land. A legal rule not in conformity with [a physical invasion model] is then
used in all disputes between
members of the group. To the extent that the
rule’s incidence upon class members is uniform, and the rule does not
benefit
some third parties not members of the original group, then no
compensation is in principle required, in spite of the universal deprivation
of
original rights brought about by collective means.
So, for example, a
hypothetical right, cognisable to private nuisance tomorrow (but not today), to
the effect of generally requiring
landholders in residential localities to not
point their CCTV cameras at particular parts of one another’s land would
constitute
a reciprocated redistribution of rights not warranting
compensation.[192]
Indeed, the right to exclude intangible interferences originating from
neighbouring land is such reciprocal right, but it is a long-established
natural
right,[193] not an acquired (or
newly recognised natural) one.
Moreover, when a claim is based upon an
emanatory interference, the claimant is asserting a right in relation to what
must or must
not be done on land that is not
theirs.[194] This does not fall to
be unjust on the physical invasion view, nor should it. That we should be
concerned about giving landholder’s
“free rights” in relation
to others’ land is not a reason to adhere to a physical invasion view of
private nuisance.
If Wright’s (and others’) concern extends to
the possibility of recognising any one of the rights Wright
mentioned—unobstructed
views, for example—then we need not adopt a
physical invasion view of the tort to preclude their adoption. For example, in
Hunter, the ratio of the decision might be that one has no right in
private nuisance to the unobstructed passage of television
signals.[195] This suffices,
without adopting a physical invasion view, to preclude the acquisition of this
right if it is perceived to be
unjust.[196]
It is this fact
that prompts some to describe the emanation requirement as
“mechanistic”:[197]
its blanket application invites an unnuanced appreciation for those sorts of
non-emanatory interferences which nonetheless call for
a remedy. Without it, we
can more readily distinguish between the types of non-emanatory interferences
that ought to be the subject
of private nuisance (perhaps interference with
water, electricity and access as in
Guppys)[198] and those that
ought not to be (perhaps the obstruction of television signals as in
Hunter).[199] When a New
Zealand court is presented with a case like Fearn—a non-emanatory,
visual intrusion case—it will be more apt to analyse whether visual
intrusions should be capable of being actionable nuisances as opposed to
whether non-emanatory interferences should be capable of being actionable
nuisances.[200]
E Conclusion
A physical invasion
view is generally propped up by an a priori understanding of property
rights that a proprietor’s position as such shall involve only the ability
to control what happens
in a three-dimensional
space.[201] All the features of
the physical invasion view—the importance of the ad coelum rule,
distinctions with trespass and the perception of non-exclusion rights as
unjust—flow from this assumption. In this Part,
I have established that
Costaki, Fearn, BEMA and Guppys—all examples
of successfully brought, non-emanation cases—are inconsistent with this
view of property rights.[202] As a
matter of description, the physical invasion view fails.
The unified account
of private nuisance that helps us to explain the emanation cases and
non-emanation cases focuses not on the boundary
of the proprietor’s land;
it focuses on the (a) control that a proprietor exerts (b) beyond the
boundary of their land. The example I emphasised in this Part—heating up
and cooling down someone’s land—tends
to undermine the whole of the
physical invasion view and supports the superior view.
As a normative
position, the physical invasion view of the tort must be rejected. That the
essence of property is exclusion might
be theoretically sound, but the
limitations the position places on the tort of private nuisance, and the
circumstances in which it
deprives claimants of remedies in relation to
interferences with the use and enjoyment of land, call for it to be rejected to
the
extent that it manifests itself in New Zealand law through Hunter and
Wu.
The BEMA Court is vindicated. It was right to denounce the
emanation requirement, even though it did so on an improper reading of Wu
and Hunter.[203]
V Private Nuisance is Concerned with Physical Proximity
In
the foregoing Part of this contribution, I challenged the physical invasion view
of the tort of private nuisance given the existence
of an emanation requirement
is a somewhat open question in New Zealand. The support it receives in the case
law should be reconsidered.
This Part addresses the contention that, given the
deficiencies in the physical invasion view, Fearn is the way
forward—that, per Lord Leggat JSC for the majority, “there is no
conceptual or a priori limit to what can constitute
a
nuisance.”[204] I reject
this view on the basis that there does exist a conceptual limit: physical
proximity. When presented with competing arguments,
a New Zealand court should
avoid the apparent false dichotomy—that the Fearn majority
is wholly correct or the Fearn majority is wholly incorrect.
I argue that private nuisance is concerned with disputes arising from a
sufficient degree of physical proximity between the thing
for which the
defendant is responsible and the plaintiff’s land. In convenient
shorthand, it is concerned with disputes within
“neighbourhoods”,
although it is not necessarily concerned with disputes between literal
neighbours.[205]
I flag that
in this Part, I focus on the proximity aspect of the tort of private
nuisance, not the control aspect, even though, as I articulated in Part
IV, both are central to the model of private nuisance proposed here. Scholars
have
developed various ideas about the control aspect, and it is apt to refer to
their formulations. Essert’s formulation is that
private nuisance is about
entitling the claimant to control the defendant where, by their own conduct, the
defendant has unreasonably
controlled the claimant’s use of the
claimant’s land.[206]
Penner’s is that private nuisance protects a proprietor from being
constructively ousted from the subject-matter of their right
(to occupy land, to
pass over land and so forth), where the defendant has not taken it for
themselves.[207]
Nolan proposes that private nuisance protects the “abstract
usability” (as opposed to specific uses) of a claimant’s
land.[208] Beever advances the
view that private nuisance prioritises more fundamental uses over less
fundamental uses of land where they
conflict.[209] At least the three
first views are largely
reconcilable,[210] and they share
a rejection of the notion that a claimant is may only exert control by excluding
physical things from some three-dimensional
space.[211] These ideas do not
form the focus of this
Part.[212]
In Subpart A, I
articulate the connection between emanation and physical proximity: emanation
implies physical proximity. Emanation
cases are paradigmatic of private nuisance
cases,[213] and this is a
consequence of the more fundamental concept that private nuisance is concerned
with “disputes within neighbourhoods”.
In Subpart B, I illustrate
the role of physical proximity in various cases. These cases are principally
non-emanation cases given
emanation implies physical proximity. In Subpart C, I
build on the analysis in Part B; I justify, referring to some normative
concerns,
why the tort of private nuisance ought to be concerned
only with such disputes.
A Emanation Implies Physical Proximity
Bagshaw identified
three possible tests towards an account of what might constitute an interference
actionable in private nuisance.
The first is the most familiar to us and is what
Bagshaw calls “physical emanation”, “which clearly covers
transfers
of tangible things... across the
boundary”.[214] The second,
“behaviour having an effect that alters the physical condition of the
claimant’s
premises”,[215] lead to our
discussion of conditions which cause the claimant’s land to become
unbearably cold.[216]
Finally,
the affront cases, Costaki and Laws v
Florinplace,[217]
attract the conclusion at least that “such a private nuisance requires
there to be a special link (perhaps one of physical
proximity) between the
source of the claimant’s disquiet and the particular premises” even
though “a private nuisance
by affront does not require any alteration in
the physical condition of the claimant’s
premises.”[218] In his
recent analysis of Fearn, Bagshaw developed this idea by suggesting that
in that case, too, the spatial proximity of the overlooking in the case was
material:[219]
The author should confess that he adheres to beliefs about the tort of
private nuisance that share more in common with “the
physicalist
heresy” than with Lord Leggat’s “there is no conceptual or
a priori limit to what can constitute a nuisance.”; for example,
the author believes that most of the catalogued private nuisance situations
that
involve “no physical invasion”, such as cases involving
“mental disturbance” caused by knowing that
prostitution is
occurring nearby, nonetheless have a physical dimension (i.e. the objectionable
activity being “nearby”
makes a difference). For what it is worth,
being stared at appears to have such a physical dimension: the experience varies
in accordance
with the physical proximity of the observer (or the use of
technology to ‘overcome the distance’).
In sum, Bagshaw
thinks that nearness matters. I argue that Bagshaw is correct, but I go further.
In all circumstasnces, private nuisance is concerned with disputes within
physically bounded neighbourhoods.
In particular, emanation is a proxy for
physical proximity because, as Merrill noticed, tangible, physical things tend
not to be carried
long
distances.[220] The same is
generally true of intangible, physical things when compared to non-physical
things.[221] There are three types
of emanations, all of which imply physical proximity. (1) Immaterial, physical
things—by noise and light,
for example—tend to emanate by dispersing
from the thing for which the defendant is responsible. Generally, their
intensity
decreases as the distance from the origin increases according
to the inverse square
law.[222] (2) Material, but
intangible, physical things—fine dust and unpleasant-smelling particles,
for example—generally emanate
in the same way, except that extraordinary
extraneous conditions may alter their
course.[223] (3) Finally,
material, tangible things emanate in a more targeted or focused
fashion—the trees in Nottingham
Forest[224] or the
projectiles in Matheson v Northcote
College,[225] for
example—and, by their mass, are only capable of travelling short
distances.[226]
Some difficult
or borderline cases are the dazzling glare in Greenwood and the bodies of
the licensees in
Matheson.[227] The former
represents a focused, intangible interference, yet the intensity of such an
interference reduces as the distance increases.
The bodies of the licensees in
Matheson are tangible, but they can travel long distances. However, the
ground of responsibility in that case, “whether what the plaintiff
complain[ed] of was a natural and probable consequence of [the defendant]
letting pupils [the licensees] play
unsupervised”,[228]
nonetheless admits consideration of physical proximity.
When, then, a
plaintiff perceives an emanatory interference and pleads private nuisance, this
is equivalent to them saying that the
source of the interference is physically
proximate or else that technology has overcome the distance. Emanation implies
physical
proximity. Indeed, some have pointed out that private nuisance is an
inadequate tool for dealing with physical invasions thought
to be originating
from a distant source because of the impracticality of being able to prove
causation.[229]
An insistence upon an emanation requirement may, in part, be attributable to a
desire to impose some physical proximity restraints.
B The Descriptive Claim: Physical Proximity Explains the Law
I now demonstrate
that physical proximity clarifies the case law. Although I have explained that
emanation implies physical proximity,
it is nonetheless helpful to take, for an
emanatory example, Bagshaw’s defendant who “plays the[ir] car stereo
loudly
whilst parked outside a [person’s]
house”.[230] On the
principles of private nuisance which we have adopted for our purposes, such a
defendant might be liable for private nuisance,
and the question might turn on
the character of the locality of which the defendant is not necessarily
resident. But notice that
the defendant’s physical proximity to the
claimant’s land renders information about the locality available because
sound
implies physical
proximity.[231]
1 The affront cases
Physical proximity
does more in non-emanation cases, where physical proximity is not implied.
Recall that Bagshaw’s third test
of physical proximity relied on an
analysis of the affront cases. Consider, first,
Costaki,[232] and accept,
for the sake of argument, the antiquated analysis of the case. Physical
proximity does some basic work to insulate the
defendant from liability in
relation to the affront to the whole
world.[233] Would we, in
Costaki, find in favour of a claimant on the other side of London
notwithstanding that they are similarly repulsed by the defendant’s
activities because they are repulsed by prostitution in general?
No.[234]
Moreover, physical
proximity distinguishes those activities that a court may consider in
determining whether an interference is substantial
and unreasonable. Whilst the
physically proximate “perambulations” of the defendants and their
clients were given weight,
no consideration was given to the more general,
“undesirable” nature of their usually distant
clients.[235] In other words, that
the defendants attracted people into the community who may have committed
“immoral” acts elsewhere was of no moment because those
immoral acts did not occur within physical proximity to the claimant’s
land.[236]
In Laws v
Florinplace, another antiquated affront case concerning the operation of a
pornography shop, Vinelott J considered whether the shop’s clientele
might
be a physically proximate danger to residents as a part of whether the
shopkeeper was committing a nuisance, but his Honour
did not consider the
concern simply about the mere presence of so-called
“undesirables”.[237]
The point is that those acts or behaviours making someone
“undesirable” are, in and of themselves, irrelevant to the
nuisance
enquiry.[238] Further, this is so
because they do not occur physically proximately. Those proximate acts or
behaviours which did make the shop’s clients
“undesirable”—such
as their perceived propensity to commit
crimes nearby or the fact that they purchase and consume pornography
nearby—were relevant to the
enquiry.[239]
2 Private nuisance and easements
Consider Douglas and
McFarlane’s example of the defendant who blockades a local petrol station.
The claimant, who has run out
of petrol, is thereby precluded from exercising
their vehicular right of way over the servient tenement, some significant
distance
away.[240] The claimant
generally has a right to sue the servient owner and third parties in private
nuisance,[241]
but, because an easement is non-possessory, they cannot sue in
trespass.[242] Douglas and
McFarlane suppose correctly that the defendant commits no wrong in this
particular hypothetical against the claimant
(at least in private nuisance) and
they use this example to bolster their claim that the claimant has no
“right to use”
the servient tenement in the claim sense, but rather
that they have a freedom to pass, coupled with the claim to
exclude physical obstructions from within
it.[243] The claimant’s
ability to exclude physical obstructions is limited; they can only do so where
the interference
substantially[244]
“interferes with the part of the [servient tenement] over which the
easement is exercised, and in such a way as to impede [the
claimant’s]
right of way.”[245] However,
the servient owner or their predecessor in title is, to Douglas and McFarlane,
unable to confer more than the claim to physically
exclude things from within
the three-dimensional space defined by the ad coelum rule, and so the
dominant owner, like the servient owner, is unable to do anything about
interferences with the so-called “right
to use” (including the
“negative Immissionen” from the hypothetical
blockade).[246]
There exists
authority to the contrary.[247]
If, for example, the servient owner parks vehicles on a public highway, close
to the way to make it more difficult for the dominant owner to access the
way, then they may commit a private
nuisance.[248] In Balfour
Beatty v Persons Unknown, the High Court of England and Wales considered
that third party protest action from a public highway might
constitute a private nuisance in relation to the claimant’s private right
of way because of the obstruction
caused.[249] Recall that
although such an interference might involve physical invasion of the servient
tenement in the form of noise and light,
such physical invasions are not
necessary for the interference complained of (that is, the obstruction),
and so Balfour Beatty is a non-emanation
case.[250]
We could, according
to the principles espoused in these cases, modify Douglas and McFarlane’s
example such that the blockade
exists immediately outside the boundary of the
way. The distinction between Douglas and McFarlane’s hypothetical and
those
cases just mentioned is the physical proximity to the servient tenement.
The relevant question is therefore not necessarily one of
physical invasion but
of physical proximity. Equivalently, the servient owner, too, has such a right
to confer.[251] Indeed, we have
already seen this right recognised in Guppys and the picketing
cases.[252]
Of course,
emanation may serve as a proxy for physical proximity in this type of scenario.
In Waterman v Boyle, Arden LJ (as she then was) suggested in
obiter that if, for example, “there was a right to take cattle down a lane
and the owner
of adjacent land creates some persistent loud noise on its land
that [emanates to the lane and therefore] makes it impossible to bring
the cattle down the lane, that would be an interference with the right of
access”.[253] But the key
feature in this example is not emanation; it is physical proximity between the
origin of the interference and the adjoining
land over which the interference is
suffered implied by the emanation of
sound.[254]
3 Physical proximity in Wu and Fearn
Admittedly, there is
one case that appears to not fit this model:
Wu.[255] I have so far
suggested that such a case should in principle be actionable in private
nuisance generally and that we can achieve this by rejecting the emanation
requirement, as
did the Court of Appeal in its sister case,
BEMA.[256] However, it is
difficult to see how the defendant’s activity and the claimant’s
land were physically proximate. The Court
of Appeal in Wu perceived that
the thing for which the defendant was responsible was the defendant’s
agent’s decision to refuse access which “could have resulted
from a decision made by [the agent] inside or outside the [claimants’]
building.”[257] On this
understanding, there is physical proximity if the decision was made within the
building[258]
but not necessarily if it was made outside the building. Justice Asher of the
High Court in Wu perhaps elucidates the existence of physical proximity
best: the “act of nuisance” was the physically proximate act of
“maintaining electronic locks on the common areas that the
proprietors could not
use.”[259]
Physical
proximity also appears to have been operating in the background of the minority
decision in Fearn. After deciding that overlooking is in principle
actionable, Lord Sales JSC stated of the case
that:[260]
The application of the “give and take” principle as a way of
modulating and reconciling the property rights of neighbouring landowners is
particularly important where the issue is visual intrusion or overlooking.
Many types of nuisance, such as those to do with smell, vibration and noise,
naturally tend to occur over relatively short distances.
But lines of sight may
be open across considerable distances, and where a landowner can look out from
their property then others
can look in. Particularly in an urban environment, a
degree of overlooking and visual intrusion is inevitable.
Of course,
Fearn did involve neighbouring proprietors, separated by no more than 40
meters.[261] But Lord Sales
JSC’s view of the tort—that the unifying principle of the tort
reasonableness between
neighbours[262]—necessarily
limits the tort to disputes arising within physical proximity to the
claimant’s land, and this limitation
suffices to address his concern about
lines of sight “across considerable distances”. We may extrapolate
from this the
principle that, where the defendant is not a neighbouring
proprietor,[263] the
defendant’s activity must nonetheless be conducted within physical
proximity to the claimant’s land.
C The Normative Claim: Private Nuisance Ought to Impose this Limit
In this Subpart, I
build on some of the ideas alluded to in the preceding Subpart insofar as they
are relevant to the normativity
of a physical proximity limit. I argue that
physical proximity properly serves three functions. Firstly, it properly limits
the control
which a proprietor may exert. Secondly, it ensures that, in relation
to non-emanation cases, the harm is one to land. Finally, it
sets the scene for
a defendant to have a basic appreciation of their potential liabilities.
1 A proprietor’s control must not extend indefinitely
It would be an
overstep if we permitted a proprietor’s control to extend too far
beyond the boundaries of their land because real property is justifiable to
the extent it permits us to control the activities within
some location (some
“neighbourhood”) defined in relation to the physical space
surrounding the land which we own. Thus,
Essert
provides:[264]
Private ownership of land is only justifiable, if it is justifiable at all,
because it is valuable for us to be able to control others
to have a right that
they not act in certain ways defined roughly by reference to location, so that
there can be the possibility
of our being in charge of a location, so
that we can experience a degree of sovereignty there and realize the
value of a place of refuge in a way that cannot be realized except by being in
charge of it in the sense of having
a right over it.
The concern is more
evident when we consider that the correlative of a claimant’s control is,
when exercised, the defendant’s
being
controlled.[265]
Recall our analysis of Costaki in the preceding
Subpart:[266] it would be undue to
give all proprietors the ability to sue someone using land for
prostitution. Those activities that are generally lawful (such as prostitution)
would not be permitted to occur anywhere because, given our existence in
physical space, “everything that is done has to be done
somewhere.”[267]
This
grates against the intuition that “harm is harm”, wherever its
origin. This intuitive response should be rejected
for three reasons. The first
is that, in the majority of private nuisance cases, physical proximity is
implied by emanation,[268] and the
role of physical proximity in relation to non-emanation cases is
modest.[269] The second is that
private nuisance is not and never has been a solely claimant-focused cause of
action. Ronald Coase’s infamous
work on private nuisance gets right the
fact that nuisance enquiry is reciprocal in
nature,[270] and some tests are
employed in the defendant’s
favour.[271] For example, factors
such as the character of the locality and any malice on the defendant’s
part affect the enquiry into whether
the interference is substantial and
unreasonable.[272] The enquiry is,
in part, geared towards keeping liability in private nuisance “under
control”.[273] Physical
proximity performs the same function. The third reason is that, as I explain in
the next justification, physical proximity
ascertains those harms that are
relevant to the private nuisance action: harms to land.
2 Private nuisance is a tort against land
The second
justification flows from the idea that private nuisance is a tort against
land.[274] I argue that it cannot
be said that an interference is suffered by land unless the origin of an
interference is physically proximate
to the land either (a) because the
interference is emanatory and physical proximity is
implied[275] or (b) otherwise by
carefully examining the case. We saw this idea emerge in the distinction between
Douglas and McFarlane’s
non-actionable, blockaded petrol station in
comparison to the physically proximate obstruction in Balfour Beatty.
Justice Kenneth Martin in Shogunn explicitly acknowledged this idea in
loss of access cases
generally:[276]
Physical obstructions [occurring some distance from an entryway] would
typically constitute... not a direct interference with the
access to the land
(by means of a particular entry point) but only an obstruction to the general
navigation of the roadway (ie the
public right of passage). However, an
obstruction in a roadway may nonetheless be said to interfere with a private
right of access if the obstruction is reasonably proximate
to an entryway to a
property and the effect of that obstruction is to prevent or substantially
impede the use of that entryway and thus to inhibit direct access
to the
property[.]
His Honour described the enquiry as “somewhat
metaphysical” and “abstract” in character. The enquiry is
whether
the injury is one that the law can “fix upon” the
land.[277] The law cannot so fix
an injury upon the land where the obstruction—or, more generally, the
origin of the interference—is
not physically proximate to the land.
A
related concern is the excessive costs or liabilities that might become of the
defendant. Lord Hoffman raised this point in relation
to the respondents in
Hunter,[278] and McBride
supposes that the physical invasion view of the tort acts appropriately to limit
the number of potential claimants in
relation to any potential
invasion.[279] This concern is
distinct from the one in Costaki. It is not about precluding just anyone
from complaining; it is about the disproportionately large impact that may
proceed—that
may metaphorically emanate—from the
defendant’s activity, and it is also about preventing the massive
coordination problem that arises in
relation to these sorts of
interferences.[280] The
characteristics of the three types of emanatory interferences ensure there is a
limit to the defendant’s liability. However,
some notion of physical
proximity precludes too large a class of potential claimants from bringing
claims in private nuisance against
defendants without resorting to the physical
invasion view of the tort.
Physical proximity may likewise permit us to
locate an injury to land within what appears to be an injury to the person. In
Hunter, Lord Goff disapproved of the Court of Appeal decision in
Khorasandjian v Bush, a successfully pleaded, non-emanation
case,[281] where the defendant
repeatedly harassed the complainant by telephoning to her mother’s
house:[282]
... the gravamen of the complaint lies in the harassment which is just as
much an abuse, or indeed an invasion of [the complainant’s]
privacy,
whether she is pestered in this way in her mother’s or her husband’s
house, or she is staying with a friend,
or is at her place of work, or even in
her car with a mobile phone.
In other words, the Court of Appeal confused
“a tort designed to protect property with the desire to protect
people.”[283]
But
Fearn illustrates that non-emanatory interferences ordinarily thought to
be personal harms—in that case, an injury to privacy—may
be harms to
land where they occur in proximity to the
land.[284] If, in
Khorasandjian, the complaint was about harasser yelling abuse from the
edge of the complainant’s home, this is, to the extent it is about
the
invasion of sound, a simple, actionable emanation
case.[285] The same must be true
if the complaint was about the harasser’s menacing presence on the edge of
the complainant’s land.[286]
In both hypotheticals, that the origin of the interference is necessarily nearby
implies an injury to the land
itself,[287] and it is only
injuries to land which are within the purview of private nuisance.
3 Ex ante assessments of liability and modularity
The final
justification builds on a policy of the physical invasion view. I will first
present the justification as it applies to
the physical invasion view of the
tort and then extrapolate from it a principle justifying some physical proximity
limit.
Private nuisance benefits “from the simplicity of a defined
thing.”[288]
If emanation is a requirement, the law sends the same, easy-to-communicate and
simply-understood message to potential tortfeasors
as it does with trespass:
“keep off”.[289] This
is relevant to Henry Smith’s explanation in terms of transaction costs,
but he suggests that a physical invasion view
is “also valuable for those
who simply need to respect rights in order to avoid liability for violating
them. And because the
rules of exclusion are simple, it is easy to announce them
ex ante.”[290] The physical
invasion view also organises plots of land into modules—third parties need
not concern themselves with any of
the particular uses being made of a plot of
land nor the complex relationships
thereof.[291] They need only to
avoid physically interfering with it.
But the physical invasion view does
more than just organise individual plots of land into modules; it also
groups nearby plots of land into modules. Potential tortfeasors can
roughly determine the “neighbourhood” about themselves
containing all those plots of land that may be exposed given the
nature of the
physical thing emanated and the intensity of the thing over which they are
responsible. The potential tortfeasor can
act without regard to those too
physically distant. This is because, as established in Subpart A of this Part,
emanatory interferences
travel predictable distances.
So, if we move from
demanding emanation to demanding physical proximity, we again impose some
modular structure by grouping nearby
plots of land
together.[292] This is a
precondition for the locality rule. Courts consider the character of
“the” or “a particular” locality to determine
whether the interference is substantial and
unreasonable,[293] and such an
assessment is not possible if physical proximity is not a precondition for
liability in private nuisance. Moreover, in
the context of all private nuisance
disputes, information about the locality bearing on a potential
tortfeasor’s liability
is available. That this basic information is
available, and that potential tortfeasors may make rudimentary approximations of
their
potential liabilities, is important not only so that their freedoms are
not unduly limited,[294] but so
that they can properly navigate the restrictions on their freedoms that
others’ interests
impose.[295] Provided the
character of the locality within which you vend pornography precludes
your immediate neighbours from complaining about your business, you can and
should go about your business without concern for the character of any
“extramodular”
locality.[296]
D Conclusion
We have seen in this
Part that emanation implies physical proximity. Equivalently, emanation cases
are physical proximity cases. The
real work of physical proximity is therefore
explaining and justifying the non-emanation cases.
In the non-emanation
cases, physical proximity does three things: it ensures that private nuisance
protects the object of rights in
land; it ensures that a proprietor’s
normative boundaries do not extend unduly far; and, perhaps most importantly, it
permits
us to act freely. In sum, it keeps the tort under control.
VI Looking Forward with Fearn
New Zealand courts
may be confronted again with a non-emanatory interference and will be presented
with the conflicting dicta in Hunter, Wu and
Fearn.[297] Lord
Goff’s dictum in Hunter endorses the physical invasion view of the
tort of private nuisance. The decision in Wu stands for the proposition
that Lord Goff’s dictum is good law, and later courts have
interpreted Wu as standing for as
much.[298] Lord Goff’s
dictum applies to “emanations” which are interferences (a) involving
invasion of the claimant’s
land (b) by something physical (c) which is a
necessary and sufficient condition for the interference. The view of the tort
that
private nuisance protects from emanations must be rejected because it lacks
coherence, descriptive power, and normative value.
The categorical assertion
in Fearn—that there is no conceptual limit as to what may
constitute a private nuisance—must not be adopted as the alternative.
Instead, courts should recognise that private nuisance is concerned with
disputes within neighbourhoods. Indeed, in most cases, physical
proximity will
not be an issue; the “paradigmatic” case of private nuisance (that
is, an emanation case) involves physically
proximate parties. Notice that I have
not yet cited a case lacking an element of physical proximity. But Lord Leggat
JSC’s
sweeping statements in Fearn have invited at least one novel
claim in private nuisance in the United Kingdom concerning the failure to
develop land,[299] and it is
conceivable that some novel claims may be brought here too.
One emergent
line of cases identified by Hariharan might be the liability of major technology
companies in private nuisance where,
for example, “employees listen to
conversations captured using smart
speakers”[300] or where they
are complicit in broadcasting or distributing the videotaping of another’s
land over the internet.[301]
Because private nuisance is about controlling others’ actions in respect
of some neighbourhood, in rejecting these claims or
claims like them, want of
physical proximity may be proffered as a reason.
Bibliography
A Cases
1 New
Zealand
Austin v Rentrezi 2 Ltd [2021] NZHC 1027, (2021) 23
NZCPR 77.
Barns v Nixon (1898) 17 NZLR 95 (SC).
Bank of
New Zealand v Greenwood [1983] NZHC 150; [1984] 1 NZLR 525 (HC).
BEMA Property
Investments Ltd v Body Corporate 366611 [2016] NZHC 1434.
BEMA
Property Investments Ltd v Body Corporate 366611 [2017] NZCA 281, [2018] 2
NZLR 514.
Boatswain v Crawford [1943] NZGazLawRp 7; [1943] NZLR 109
(SC).
Body Corporate 366611 v Wu [2012] NZCA 614, [2013] 3 NZLR
522.
BP Oil New Zealand Ltd v Ports of Auckland Ltd [2003] NZHC 1139; [2004] 2 NZLR
208 (HC).
Byrne v Judd [1908] NZLR 1106 (CA).
C v
Holland [2012] NZHC 2155, [2012] 3 NZLR 672.
Clearlite Holdings
Ltd v Auckland City Corp [1976] 2 NZLR 729 (SC).
Easton
Agriculture Ltd v Manawatu-Wanganui Regional Council [2011] NZHC 1005; [2012]
1 NZLR 120 (HC).
Faesenkloet v Jenkin [2014] NZHC
1637.
Fortesque v Te Awamutu Borough [1918] NZGazLawRp 201; [1918] NZLR 991
(SC).
French v Auckland City Corporation [1974] 1 NZLR 340
(SC).
Hamilton Cosmopolitan Club Inc v Lewis [2022] NZHC
2555.
Harbourcity Developments Ltd v Owen HC Auckland
CIV-2006-404-1400, 30 March 2007.
Hawkes Bay Protein Ltd v Davidson
[2003] 1 NZLR 536 (HC).
Hill v Waimea County Council HC Nelson
A8/84, 12 March 1987.
Hosking v Runting [2004] NZCA 34; [2005] 1 NZLR 1
(CA).
Karmarkar v Kajol Enterprises Ltd [2024] NZHC
683.
Leisure Investments NZ Ltd Partnership v Grace [2023] NZCA
89, [2023] 2 NZLR 724.
Matheson v Northcote College Board of Governors
[1975] 2 NZLR 106 (SC).
Nottingham Forest Trustee Ltd v Unison
Networks Ltd [2021] NZCA 227, [2021] 3 NZLR 823.
Relk Holdings Ltd
v Manawatu Wanganui Regional Council HC Hamilton CP172/92, 27 April
1993.
Simunac v Lu [2024] NZHC 363.
Smith v Fonterra
Co-operative Group Ltd [2024] NZSC 5, [2024] 1 NZLR 134
SPAK
(1996) Ltd v LeRoy [2022] NZCA 564, (2022) 23 NZCPR 769.
Unison
Networks Ltd v Nottingham Forest Trustee Ltd [2019] NZHC
2280.
Varnier v Vector Energy Ltd [2004] NZRMA 193
(HC).
Waugh v Attorney-General [2006] NZHC 352; [2006] 2 NZLR 812
(HC).
Wu v Body Corporate 366611 [2011] NZHC 561; [2011] 2 NZLR 837
(HC).
Wu v Body Corporate 366611 [2014] NZSC 137, [2015] 1 NZLR
215.
Young v Attorney-General [2021] NZHC 463.
Young v
Attorney-General [2022] NZCA 391, [2023] 2 NZLR 24.
Young v
Attorney-General [2023] NZSC 142, [2023] 1 NZLR 596.
2 Australia
(All)
Cosentino v Peter Medich Properties Pty Ltd [2003] NSWSC
606.
Goldman v Hargrave [1966] UKPC 2; [1967] 1 AC 645 (PC).
Hargrave v
Goldman [1963] HCA 56; (1963) 110 CLR 40.
Kidman v Page [1959] Qd R 53
(SC).
Kraemers v Attorney-General [1966] TASStRp 15; [1966] Tas SR 113
(FC).
Onus v Telstra Corp Ltd [2011] NSWSC 33.
Shogunn
Investments Pty Ltd v Public Transport Authority of Western Australia [2016]
WASC 42.
Victoria Park Racing and Recreation Grounds Co Ltd v Taylor
[1937] HCA 45; (1937) 58 CLR 479.
3 Canada (All)
Antrim Truck
Centre Ltd v Ontario (Transportation) 2013 SCC 13, [2013] 1 SCR
594.
Mann v Saulnier (1959) 19 DLR (2d) 130
(NBCA).
Martin v Lavigne 2011 BCCA 104, 17 BCLR (5th)
132.
Newell v Izzard [1944] 3 DLR 118 (NBSC).
Zhang v
Davies 2017 BCSC 1180, [2017] BCJ No 1350.
4 England and
Wales
Anchor Brewhouse Developments Ltd v Berkley House (Docklands
Developments) Ltd [1987] 2 EGLR 173 (Ch).
Anglian Water Services
Ltd v Crawshaw Robbins & Co Ltd [2001] BLR 173 (EWHC).
Balfour
Beatty Group Ltd v Persons Unknown [2022] EWHC 874 (QB).
Bamford v
Turnley (1862) 3 B & S 67, 122 ER 27 (Exch Ch).
Bernstein of
Leigh (Baron) v Skyviews & General Ltd [1975] QB 479
(QB).
Birmingham Development Co Ltd v Tyler [2008] EWCA Civ
859.
Bocardo SA v Star Energy UK Onshore Ltd [2010] UKSC 35,
[2011] 1 AC 380.
Bradford v Pickles [1895] AC 587
(HL).
Cambridge Water Co v Eastern Counties Leather plc [1993] UKHL 12; [1994] 2
AC 264 (HL).
Christie v Davey [1892] UKLawRpCh 185; [1893] 1 Ch 316
(Ch).
Colls v Home and Colonial Stores Ltd [1904] AC 179
(HL).
Deane v Clayton [1817] EngR 472; (1817) 7 Taunt 489, 129 ER 196 (Comm
Pleas).
Delaware Mansions Ltd v Westminster City Council [2001]
UKHL 55, [2002] 1 AC 321.
Dennis v Head Start Day Nursery Ltd
[2024] EWHC 1248 (Admin).
Esso Petroleum Co Ltd v Southport Corp
[1956] 1 AC 218 (HL).
Fairhouse v Woodward CC Oxford G00MK61,
12 October 2022.
Fearn v Board of Trustees of the Tate Gallery
[2019] EWHC 246 (Ch), [2019] Ch 369.
Fearn v Board of Trustees of
the Tate Gallery [2020] EWCA Civ 104, [2020] Ch 621.
Fearn v Board
of Trustees of the Tate Gallery [2023] UKSC 4, [2024] 1 AC
1.
Goodtitle v Duke of Chandos [1760] EngR 733; (1760) 2 Burr 1065, 97 ER 710
(KB).
Guppys (Bridport) Ltd v Brookling (1984) 14 HLR 1
(EWCA).
Halsey v Esso Petroleum Co Ltd [1961] 1 WLR 683
(QB).
High Speed Two (HS2) Ltd v Persons Unknown [2022] EWHC 2360
(KB).
Hilton v James Smith & Sons (Norwood) Ltd [1979] 2 EGLR
44 (EWCA).
Hubbard v Pitt [1976] QB 142 (CA).
Hunter v
Canary Wharf Ltd [1997] 1 AC 655 (CA).
Hunter v Canary Wharf Ltd
[1997] 1 AC 655 (HL).
Ineos Upstream Ltd v Persons Unknown
[2017] EWHC 2945 (Ch).
Island Gas Ltd v Persons Unknown [2018]
EWHC 3743 (Ch).
J Lyons & Sons v Wilkins (No 2) [1898] UKLawRpCh 178; [1899] 1 Ch
255 (CA).
Jalla v Shell International Trading and Shipping Co Ltd
[2023] UKSC 16, [2024] AC 595.
Jelbert v Davis [1968] 1 WLR
589 (CA).
Khorasandjian v Bush [1993] EWCA Civ 18; [1993] QB 727
(CA).
Lawrence v Fen Tigers Ltd [2014] UKSC 13, [2014] AC
822.
Laws v Florinplace Ltd [1981] 1 All ER 659
(Ch).
Lippiatt v South Gloucestershire Council (1999) EWCA Civ 1151; [2000] QB 51
(CA).
Matania v The National Provincial Bank Ltd [1936] 2 All ER
633 (CA).
Midwood & Co Ltd v Manchester Corp [1905] UKLawRpKQB 136; [1905] 2 KB 597
(CA).
Miller v Jackson [1975] QB 966 (CA).
Paine &
Co Ltd v St Neots Gas & Coke Co [1939] 3 All ER 812
(CA).
Partakis-Stevens v Sihan [2022] EWHC 3249
(TCC).
Pettey v Parsons [1914] UKLawRpCh 92; [1914] 2 Ch 653 (CA).
R v
Rimmington [2006] UKHL 63, [2006] 1 AC 459.
Read v J Lyons &
Co Ltd [1946] UKHL 2; [1947] AC 156 (HL).
Reinhardt v Mentasti [1889] UKLawRpCh 140; (1889) 42 Ch D
685 (Ch).
Robinson v Kilvert [1889] UKLawRpCh 47; (1889) 41 Ch D 88
(CA).
Rothwell v Chemical & Insulating Co Ltd [2007] UKHL 39,
[2008] AC 281.
Sanders-Clark v Grosvenor Mansions Co Ltd [1900] UKLawRpCh 109; [1900] 2
Ch 373 (Ch).
Sedleigh-Denfield v O’Callaghan [1940] UKHL 2; [1940] AC 880
(HL).
Smith v Scott [1972] Ch 314 (Ch).
Southport Corp v
Esso Petroleum Co Ltd [1953] 3 WLR 773 (QB).
Southport Corp v Esso
Petroleum Co Ltd [1954] EWCA Civ 5; [1954] 2 QB 182 (CA).
St Helens Smelting Co v
Tipping (1865) 11 HLC 642, 11 ER 1483 (HL).
Sturges v Bridgman
[1878] Ch D 852 (CA).
Tandem Properties Ltd v Sheffield City
Council [2024] EWHC 1926 (Ch).
Tapling v Jones [1865] EngR 333; (1865) 11 HLC
290, 11 ER 1344 (HL).
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki [1956] 1 WLR 335
(CA).
Transco plc v Stockport Metropolitan Borough Council [2003] UKHL 61; [2004]
2 AC 1 (HL).
Wall v Collins [2009] EWHC 2100
(Ch).
Waterman v Boyle [2009] EWCA Civ 115, [2009] 2 EGLR
7.
Weston v Lawrence Weaver Ltd [1961] 1 QB 402
(QB).
Williams v Network Rail Infrastructure Ltd [2018] EWCA Civ
1514, [2019] QB 601.
5 Germany
G v City of Hamburg
(1983) 88 BGHZ 344.
6 Ireland
Dublin (South) City Market
Co v McCabes Ltd [1953] IR 283
(HC).
7 Scotland
Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562
(HL).
8 United States of America (All)
Burke v Smith
37 NW 838 (Mich 1888).
Fontainebleau Hotel Corp v Forty-Five
Twenty-Five Inc 114 So 2d 357 (Fla Dist Ct App 1959).
Lucas v
South Carolina Coastal Council [1992] USSC 111; 505 US 1003 (1992).
Mark v
Department of Fish and Wildlife 974 P 2d 716 (Or App 2004).
Penn
Central Transportation Co v New York City [1978] USSC 180; 438 US 104 (1977).
San
Diego Gas & Electric Co v City of San Diego [1981] USSC 62; 450 US 621
(1981).
Wernke v Halas 600 NE 2d 117 (Ind App,
1992).
Wendt v Kerkhof 594 NE 2d 795 (Ind App,
1992).
B Legislation
1 New Zealand
Property
Law Act 2007.
Unit Titles Act 1972 (repealed).
Unit Titles Act
2010.
2 Germany
Bürgerliches
Gesetzbuch.
C Books and Chapters in Books
Alphonse A Adler
The Theory of Engineering Drawing (D Van Nostrand Co, New York,
1912).
Bill Atkin “The Tort of Nuisance: “Trucking
On”” in Shelley Griffiths, Mark Henaghan and MB Rodriguez Ferrere
(eds) The Search for Certainty – Essays in Honour of John Smillie
(Thomson Reuters, Wellington, 2016) 60.
Bill Atkin
“Nuisance” in Stephen Todd (ed) Todd on Torts (9th ed,
Thomson Reuters, Wellington, 2023) 579.
Roderick Bagshaw “The Edges
of Tort Law’s Rights” in Donal Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds)
Rights and Private Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2012) 407.
John
Baker An Introduction to English Legal History (5th ed, Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 2019).
Lawrence C Becker Property Rights: Philosophic
Foundations (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1977).
Allan Beever
The Law of Private Nuisance (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2013).
Peter
Benson “The Basis for Excluding Liability for Economic Loss in Tort
Law” in David G Owen (ed) Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law
(Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1995) 427.
Herbert Broom, Joseph Gerald Pease
and Herbert Chitty A Selection of Legal Maxims, Classified and Illustrated
(8th ed, Sweet and Maxwell, London, 1911).
RA Buckley The Law of
Nuisance (2nd ed, Butterworths, London, 1996).
Richard A Buckley
Buckley – The Law of Negligence and Nuisance (5th ed, LexisNexis,
London, 2011).
R Buckley “Nuisance, Rylands v Fletcher and Similar
Liabilities” in Andrew Tettenborn and others (eds) Clerk & Lindsell
on Torts (24th ed, Sweet & Maxwell, London, 2023) 1387.
Dan B
Dobbs The Law of Torts (West Group, Saint Paul (MN), 2001) vol
2.
Simon Douglas “The Content of a Freehold: A ‘Right to
Use’ Land?” in Nicholas Hopkins (ed) Modern Studies in Property
Law vol 7 (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2013) 359.
Simon Douglas and Ben
McFarlane “Defining Property Rights” in James Penner and Henry Smith
(eds) Philosophical Foundations of Property Law (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 2013) 219.
Richard A Epstein Torts (Aspen Law &
Business, New York, 1999).
Wolfgang Frisch, Martin Meschede and Ronald
Blakey Plate Tectonics: Continental Drift and Mountain Building
(Springer, Heidelberg, 2011).
Leon Green Rationale of Proximate
Cause (Vernon Law Book, Kansas City, 1927).
James Goudkamp and Donal
Nolan Winfield and Jolowicz on Tort (20th ed, Sweet & Maxwell,
London, 2020).
RFV Heuston Salmond on the Law of Torts (12th ed,
Sweet & Maxwell, London, 1957).
Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld Fundamental
Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning (Yale University Press,
New Haven, 1919).
Samuel Johnson Taxation no Tyranny – An Answer
to the Resolutions and Address of the American Congress (T Cadell, London,
1775).
Lewis N Klar Tort Law (4th ed, Thomson Carswell, Toronto,
2008).
Richard Macrory Nuisance (Oyez Longman Publishing, London,
1982).
Nicholas J McBride “Rights and the Basis of Tort Law”
in Donal Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds) Rights and Private Law (Hart
Publishing, Oxford, 2012) 331.
Nicholas J McBride and Roderick Bagshaw
Tort Law (6th ed, Pearson, Harlow (UK), 2018).
Thomas W Merrill,
Henry E Smith and Dennis Patterson (ed) The Oxford Introductions to US Law:
Property (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010).
DW McMorland
McMorland on Easements, Covenants and Licences (5th ed, LexisNexis,
Wellington, 2023).
Thomas W Merrill “trespass and nuisance”
in Peter Newman (ed) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law
(Palgrave Macmillan, London, 2002) vol 3 617.
Nicholas J Mullany and
Allen M Linden (eds) Torts Tomorrow: A Tribute to John Fleming (LBC
Information Services, Sydney, 1998).
Stephen R Munzer A theory of
property (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990).
John Murphy
The Law of Nuisance (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010).
Jason
W Neyers, Erika Chamberlain and Stephen GA Pitel (eds) Emerging Issues in
Tort Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2007).
Donal Nolan
“Nuisance” in Andrew Grubb and Ken Oliphant (eds) The Law of Tort
(2nd ed, LexisNexis Butterworths, London, 2007) 1101.
Donal Nolan
“‘A Tort Against Land’: Private Nuisance as a Property
Tort” in Donal Nolan and Andrew Robertson
(eds) Rights and Private Law
(Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2012) 459.
Donal Nolan “The Essence
of Private Nuisance” in Ben McFarlane and Sinéad Agnew (eds)
Modern Studies in Property Law vol 10 (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2019)
71.
James William Norton-Kyshe The Dictionary of Legal Quotations
(Sweet and Maxwell, London, 1904).
David G Owen (ed) Philosophical
Foundations of Tort Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1995)
James Penner
The Idea of Property in Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1997).
JE Penner Property Rights: A Re-Examination (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2020).
William L Prosser Handbook of the Law
of Torts (West Publishing, Saint Paul (MN), 1941).
WVH Rogers
Winfield & Jolowicz on Tort (18th ed, Sweet & Maxwell, London
2010).
Barry Smith “On Place and Space: The Ontology of the
Eruv” in Christian Kanzian and Edmund Runggaldier (eds) Cultures:
Conflict - Analysis - Dialogue (Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt, 2007)
403.
James Y Stern “What Is the Right to Exclude and Why Does It
Matter?” in James Penner and Michael Otsuka (eds) Property Theory:
Legal and Political Perspectives (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
2018) 38.
Robert Stevens “The Conflict of Rights” in Andrew
Robertson and Tang Hang Wu (eds) The Goals of Private Law (Hart
Publishing, Oxford, 2009) 139.
Laura S Underkuffler The Idea of
Property – Its Meaning and Power (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2003).
Christian von Bar and Jason Grant Allen (tr) Foundations of
Property Law: Things as Objects of Property Rights (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 2023).
Joseph William Singer Entitlement: The Paradoxes of
Property (Yale University Press, New Haven, 2000).
Jeremy Waldron
The Right to Private Property (Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1988).
Tony Weir An Introduction to Tort Law (2nd ed, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2006).
George Frederick Wharton Wharton’s
Legal Maxims (3rd ed, Law Times, London, 1903).
Richard W Wright
“Private Nuisance Law: A Window on Substantive Justice” in Donal
Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds) Rights and Private Law (Hart Publishing,
Oxford, 2012) 491.
D Journal Articles
JB Ames “How
Far an Act May be a Tort Because of the Wrongful Motive of the Actor”
(1905) 18 Harv L Rev 411.
Roderick Bagshaw “Private Nuisance by
Third Parties” (2000) 8 Tort L Rev 165.
Roderick Bagshaw
“Rylands Confined” (2004) 120 LQR 388.
Roderick
Bagshaw “Private Nuisance: The UK Supreme Court Take a View” (2023)
16 J Tort Law 173.
Antoinette Besier “Leaving it all to the
Resource Management Act 1991: The Demise of the Tort of Private Nuisance”
(2004) 35 VUWLR 563.
Lynton K Caldwell “Rights of Ownership or
Rights of Use?—The Need for a New Conceptual Basis for Land Use
Policy”
(1974) 15 Wm & Mary L Rev 759.
Peter Cane “What a
nuisance!” (1997) 113 LQR 515.
Robert S Chambers “Nuisance
– Judicial Attack on Orthodoxy” [1978] NZLJ 172.
RH Coase
“The Problem of Social Cost” (1960) 3 JLE 1.
Felix S Cohen
“Dialogue on Private Property” (1954) 9 Rutgers L Rev
357.
Timothy Crawford “The Problems of Causation in Private Legal
Remedies for Damage from Acid Rain” (1984) 17 Nat Resources
Law
413.
Senara Eggleton “The Supreme Court on Visual Intrusion and
Private Nuisance: Fearn v Board of Trustees of the Tate Gallery
[2023] UKSC
4” (2023) 13(2) KSLR 22.
Richard A Epstein “Nuisance Law:
Corrective Justice and Its Utilitarian Constraints” (1979) 8 J Legal Stud
49.
Richard A Epstein “The Harm Principle – And How it
Grew” (1995) 45 UTLJ 369.
Christopher Essert “Nuisance and
the Normative Boundaries of Ownership” (2016) 52 Tulsa L Rev
85.
Christopher Essert “Property and Homelessness” (2016) 44
Phil & Pub Aff 266.
John Finnis “Some Professorial Fallacies
About Rights” [1972] AdelLawRw 7; (1972) 4 Adel L Rev 377.
Conor Gearty “The
Place of Private Nuisance in a Modern Law of Torts” (1989) 48 CLJ
214.
Shelley Geiszler “Nuisance Most Fowl: The Problem with
Chicago’s Permissive Livestock Ordinance and How to Fix it”
(2020)
95 Chi-Kent L Rev 367.
PR Ghandhi “Orthodoxy Affirmed: Hunter
and others v. Canary Wharf Ltd and Hunter and others v. London Docklands
Development Corporation [1997] 2 All E.R. 426” (1998) 62 Conv
309.
Jeevan Hariharan “The View from the Top: Visual Intrusion as
Nuisance in Fearn v Tate Gallery” (2024) 87 MLR 697.
Paul
Henty “Dr Mary Fairhurst v Mr Jon Woodard: Lessons in CCTV and data
protection” (2022) 11(3) Comp & Risk 8.
Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld
“Faulty Analysis in Easement and License Cases” (1917) 27 Yale LJ
66.
Maria Hook “Nuisance and Rylands in need of
direction” [2021] NZLJ 229.
Maria Hook “Strict liability in
nuisance — a fork in the road” [2021] NZLJ 136.
Maria Hook
“The Rylands Compromise” [2023] OtaLawRw 5; (2023) 18 Otago LR
65.
Stephen D Hudson and Douglas N Husak “Legal Rights: How Useful
is Hohfeldian Analysis?” (1980) 37 Philos Stud 45.
GAI
“Sic Utere Tuo ut Alienum Non Laedas” (1907) 5 Mich L Rev
673.
Jay L Johnson “Acid Rain: Minnesota Remedies” (1983) 1
William Mitchell Envtl LJ 82.
Gregory C Keating “Nuisance as a
Strict Liability Wrong” (2012) 4(3)(2) J Tort Law 1.
Richard Kidner
“Television Reception and the Tort of Nuisance” (1989) 53 Conv
279.
Richard Kidner “Nuisance and Rights of Property” (1998)
62 Conv 267.
Maria Lee “Visual Intrusion, Public Interests and
Private Nuisance: Fearn v Tate” (2023) 82 CLJ 208.
Emma Lees
“Fearn v Tate Galleries: Privacy and the law of nuisance”
(2021) 23 Env L Rev 49.
Janet Loengard “The Assize of Nuisance:
Origins of An Action at Common Law” (1978) 37 CLJ 144.
Ben
McFarlane “Property: Duties, Diversity, and Limits” (2022) 33 KLJ
23.
Geoff McLay “The Once and Future Law of Nuisance?” [1997]
NZLJ 222.
Francis McManus “Liability in nuisance: Fearn v Board
of Trustees of the Tate Gallery [2023] UKSC 4” (2023) NILQ
643.
Thomas W Merrill “Trespass, Nuisance, and the Costs of
Determining Property Rights” (1985) 14 J Legal Stud 13.
Thomas W
Merrill “Property and the Right to Exclude” (1998) 77 Neb L Rev
730.
Thomas W Merrill “The Property Strategy” (2012) 160 U Pa
L Rev 2061.
Thomas W Merrill and Henry E Smith “What Happened to
Property in Law and Economics?” [2001] YaleLawJl 34; (2001) 111 Yale LJ 357.
Thomas W
Merrill and Henry E Smith “The Morality of Property” (2007) 48 Wm
& Mary L Rev 1849.
Nancy Hughes Milstone “A Common Law Solution
to the Acid Rain Problem” (1986) 20 Val U L Rev 277.
Noga
Morag-Levine “The Case of Proclamations (1610), Aldred’s
Case (1610), and the Origins of the Sic Utere/Salus Populi
Antithesis” (2022) 40 LHR 383.
John Murphy “The Merits of
Rylands v Fletcher” (2004) 24 OJLS 643.
David Neild
“Nuisance through emanation” [2016] NZLJ 333.
JW Neyers and
Jordan Diacur “What (is) a Nuisance? Antrim Truck Centre Ltd v Ontario
(Minister of Transportation)” (2011) 90 Can Bar Rev 213.
FH
Newark “The Boundaries of Nuisance” (1949) 65 LQR 480.
Donal
Nolan “The Distinctiveness of Rylands v Fletcher” (2005) 121
LQR 421.
Donal Nolan “Nuisance and privacy” (2021) 137 LQR
1.
Ben Ohavi “Why Metaphysics Matters: The Case of Property
Law” (2024) 43 Law and Philosophy 367.
JE Penner “Nuisance
and the Character of the Neighbourhood” (1993) 5 J Envtl L 1.
JE
Penner “The “Bundle of Rights” Picture of Property”
(1996) 43 UCLA L Rev 711.
Ben Pontin “A room with a view in English
nuisance law: exploring modernisation hidden within the ‘textbook
tradition’”
(2018) 38 Legal Stud 627.
Richard A Posner
“The Concept of Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law”
(1981) 10 JLS 187.
Margaret Jane Radin “The Liberal Conception of
Property: Cross Currents in the Jurisprudence of Takings” (1988) 88 Colum
L Rev 1667.
Cheng Lim Saw and Aaron Yoong “Throwing Stones in Glass
Houses: Protecting Privacy under the Law of Nuisance” (2022) 28
Tort L Rev
145.
Joseph A Schremmer “Ad Coelum and the Design of
Property Rights” (2023) 9 Texas A&M J of Prop L 707.
Ted
Sichelman and Henry E Smith “A network model of legal relations”
(2024) 382 Phil Trans R Soc.
Henry E Smith “Exclusion and
Property Rules in the Law of Nuisance” (2004) 90 Va L Rev
965.
Henry E Smith “Modularity and Morality in the Law of
Torts” (2011) 4(2)(5) J Tort L 1.
Henry E Smith “Property as
the Law of Things” (2012) 125 Harv L Rev 1691.
Henry E Smith
“The Persistence of System in Property Law” (2015) 163 U Pa L Rev
2055.
Christina Spaulding “Anti-Pornography Laws As A Claim For
Equal Respect: Feminism, Liberalism & Community” (1988) 4
Berkeley Women’s LJ 128.
Brandon D Stewart “Contamination as
a chemical interference with land: Where the (private nuisance) truck should
stop after
Antrim” (2015) 23 Tort L Rev 98.
Jeremy Waldron
“Homelessness and the Issue of Freedom” (1991) 39 UCLA L Rev
295.
John Wightman “Nuisance – the Environmental Tort?
Hunter v Canary Wharf in the House of Lords” (1998) 61 MLR
870.
E Unpublished Works
Michael JR Crawford “The
Tort of Nuisance: From the Outside Looking In” (Melbourne University Law
Review, Volume 47, No
3, 2024) (forthcoming).
Jordan Grimmer
“Untangling our land-based torts: the woes of Wu v Body Corporate
366611” (LLB (Hons) Dissertation, University of Otago,
2015).
Matthew Mazenier “The law of private nuisance following
Wu: emanation and access” (LLB (Hons) Dissertation, Victoria
University of Wellington, 2013).
Nicholas J McBride “‘A
Straightforward Case of Nuisance’: A Note on Fearn v Board of
Trustees of the Tate Gallery [2023] UKSC 4” (Legal Studies Research
Paper Series Paper, University of Cambridge, 2023).
Ryona Winwood
“A Path to Reciprocity: Rebalancing the Tort of Private Nuisance after
Fearn v Tate Gallery” (LAWS 489 Research Paper, Victoria University
of Wellington, 2023).
F Internet Resources
Andy Giddings
“Lawyers set out River Wye pollution claim” British Broadcasting
Company (online ed, London, 9 July 2024).
“emanate, v.”
(March 2024) Oxford English Dictionary
<www.oed.com>.
“emanation, n.” (March 2024) Oxford
English Dictionary <www.oed.com>.
James Lee and others
“Nuisance in the UK Supreme Court” (3 February 2023) Obligations
Discussion Group <www.stevehedley.com/odg>.
“Thousands sue
PNG miner for environmental damage” Radio New Zealand (online ed,
Wellington, 8 February 2020).
Marty Sharpe “Neighbours’
dispute leads to shipping containers blocking sea views” Stuff
(online ed, Wellington, 26 March 2024).
Robert Stevens, Donal Nolan
and Matthew Hoyle “Nuisance in the UK Supreme Court” (2 February
2023) Obligations Discussion
Group
<www.stevehedley.com/odg>.
G Other
Resources
Christine French “Rylands v Fletcher and
Nuisance” in Christine French and Stephen Todd (presenters) Update on
Torts (New Zealand Law Society seminar, October 1998) 58.
Smith v
Fonterra Co-operative Group Ltd [2022] NZSC Trans 19.
[1] Fearn v Board of Trustees of
the Tate Gallery [2023] UKSC 4, [2024] 1 AC 1 at
[13].
[2] Parts II–III,
below.
[3] Wu v Body Corporate
366611 [2014] NZSC 137, [2015] 1 NZLR 215 at
[124].
[4] At
[125].
[5] Smith v Fonterra
Co-operative Group Ltd [2024] NZSC 5, [2024] 1 NZLR 134 at [134]–[135]
and [165].
[6] New Zealand courts
have mentioned Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, but not as it relates to any emanation
requirement: see, for example, Young v Attorney-General [2023] NZSC 142,
[2023] 1 NZLR 596 at [90]–[94]; and Simunac v Lu [2024] NZHC 363 at
[44]–[47].
[7] Hunter v
Canary Wharf Ltd [1997] 1 AC 655 (HL) at 687 per Lord Goff and 702 per Lord
Hoffman and see 726 per Lord Hope; Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above
n 3, at [120], n 100; FH Newark
“The Boundaries of Nuisance” (1949) 65 LQR 480 at 482; and see
generally Donal Nolan “‘A Tort Against Land’: Private Nuisance
as a Property Tort” in Donal
Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds) Rights
and Private Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2012)
459.
[8] See, for example, the
formulation in Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[120].
[9] See Brandon D Stewart
“Contamination as a chemical interference with land: Where the (private
nuisance) truck should stop after
Antrim” (2015) 23 Tort L Rev 98 at
98–99 (citations
omitted).
[10] See, for example,
Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [18]–[21] per Lord Leggat
JSC.
[11] St Helens Smelting
Co v Tipping (1865) 11 HLC 642 at 650, 11 ER 1483 at 1486 (HL) per Lord
Westbury LC.
[12] Hawkes Bay
Protein Ltd v Davidson [2003] 1 NZLR 536 (HC) at [18]; and Colls v Home
and Colonial Stores Ltd [1904] AC 179 (HL) at 185 per Earl of Halsbury
LC.
[13] See Christie v Davey
[1892] UKLawRpCh 185; [1893] 1 Ch 316 (Ch) at
327–328.
[14] See Hawkes
Bay Protein Ltd v Davidson, above n 12, at
[3].
[15] Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7, at 692 per
Lord Goff.
[16] At 707 per Lord
Hoffman; and see Nolan, above n 7, at
473–475.
[17] At
692–695 per Lord Goff.
[18]
See, for example, Sturges v Bridgman [1878] Ch D 852
(CA).
[19] See, for example,
Boatswain v Crawford [1943] NZGazLawRp 7; [1943] NZLR 109
(SC).
[20] See, for example,
Sedleigh-Denfield v O’Callaghan [1940] UKHL 2; [1940] AC 880 (HL) at 895 per
Viscount Maugham.
[21] See, for
example, Matheson v Northcote College Board of Governors [1975] 2 NZLR
106 (SC) at 112.
[22] See, for
example, Harris v James (1876) 45 LJQB
545.
[23] See further RA Buckley
The Law of Nuisance (2nd ed, Butterworths, London, 1996) at 92 and
following; Richard A Buckley Buckley – The Law of Negligence and
Nuisance (5th ed, LexisNexis, London, 2011) at [11.40] and following; Allan
Beever The Law of Private Nuisance (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2013) at 125
and following; and James Goudkamp and Donal Nolan Winfield and Jolowicz on
Tort (20th ed, Sweet & Maxwell, London, 2020) at [15-042] and
following.
[24] See, for example,
Miller v Jackson [1975] QB 966 (CA) at 980 per Lord Denning
MR.
[25] See, for example,
Kraemers v Attorney-General [1966] TASStRp 15; [1966] Tas SR 113 (FC) at 118 per Burbury CJ,
135 per Gibson J and 153 per Neasby J; and see Nolan, above n 7, at
475–476.
[26] Southport
Corp v Esso Petroleum Co Ltd [1953] 3 WLR 773 (QB) at 776; see Esso
Petroleum Co Ltd v Southport Corp [1956] 1 AC 218 (HL) at 235 per Earl
Jowitt; Halsey v Esso Petroleum Co Ltd [1961] 1 WLR 683 (QB) at
700–701; but see Southport Corp v Esso Petroleum Co Ltd [1954] EWCA Civ 5; [1954] 2 QB
182 (CA) at 196 per Denning LJ; and Esso Petroleum v Southport (HL) at
241–242 per Lord Radcliffe. This must be correct to avoid anomalies:
Buckley Negligence and Nuisance, above n 23, at [11.41]. Moreover, the understanding
that this is incorrect flows from an improper application of
Sedleigh-Denfield v O’Callaghan, above n 20: Roderick Bagshaw “Private
Nuisance by Third Parties” (2000) 8 Tort L Rev 165 at
167.
[27] See, for example,
Clearlite Holdings Ltd v Auckland City Corp [1976] 2 NZLR 729 (SC) at
735–740; and see Bill Atkin “Nuisance” in Stephen Todd (ed)
Todd on Torts (9th ed, Thomson Reuters, Wellington, 2023) 579 at
[9.2.6(1)].
[28] See Goudkamp
and Nolan, above n 23, at [15-042];
Nicholas J McBride “‘A Straightforward Case of Nuisance’: A
Note on Fearn v Board of Trustees of the Tate Gallery [2023] UKSC
4” (Legal Studies Research Paper Series Paper, University of Cambridge,
2023) at 8–9; but see Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at [124] citing with approval Robert S
Chambers “Nuisance – Judicial Attack on Orthodoxy” [1978] NZLJ
172 at 176; Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [9] per Lord Leggat JSC citing with
approval Newark, above n 7, at 489 and
[158] per Lord Sales JSC.
[29]
Nolan, above n 7, at 476; and Donal
Nolan “Nuisance” in Andrew Grubb and Ken Oliphant (eds) The Law
of Tort (2nd ed, LexisNexis Butterworths, London, 2007) 1101 at
[22.11].
[30] Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[122], n 101–103.
[31]
Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7,
at 685–686 per Lord Goff and see also 700 per Lord
Lloyd.
[32] Fearn v Board of
Trustees of the Tate Gallery [2019] EWHC 246 (Ch), [2019] Ch 369 at
[167].
[33] Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7, at
700.
[34] Donal Nolan
“Nuisance and privacy” (2021) 137 LQR 1 at
4.
[35] Part I, Subpart C,
above.
[36] Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[122]–[123]; and see also Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [178] per Lord Sales
JSC.
[37] Wu v Body Corporate
366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[123].
[38] Shogunn
Investments Pty Ltd v Public Transport Authority of Western Australia [2016]
WASC 42 at [72] citing Hargrave v Goldman [1963] HCA 56; (1963) 110 CLR 40; and
Harbourcity Developments Ltd v Owen HC Auckland CIV-2006-404-1400, 30
March 2007 at [61] citing Varnier v Vector Energy Ltd [2004] NZRMA 193
(HC).
[39] Nottingham Forest
Trustee Ltd v Unison Networks Ltd [2021] NZCA 227, [2021] 3 NZLR 823 at
[46]–[47]; and see Unison Networks Ltd v Nottingham Forest Trustee Ltd
[2019] NZHC 2280 at
[87(b)].
[40] Matheson v
Northcote College, above n 21, at
108–109; and see also Lippiatt v South Gloucestershire Council
(1999) EWCA Civ 1151; [2000] QB 51 (CA) at 60 per Evans
LJ.
[41] Williams v Network
Rail Infrastructure Ltd [2018] EWCA Civ 1514, [2019] QB 601 at [43] per Sir
Terrence Etherton MR; and see Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [13] per Lord Leggat
JSC.
[42] But see Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[26], n 15; Body Corporate 366611 v Wu [2012] NZCA 614, [2013] 3 NZLR 522
at [94], n 82; and Wu v Body Corporate 366611 [2011] NZHC 561; [2011] 2 NZLR 837 (HC) at
[31] and [75]. It is unclear whether access was precluded by an electronic
impulse that physically invaded the claimant’s land or
by reprogramming
the key cards themselves.
[43]
Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[125].
[44] Part III,
below.
[45] “emanation,
n.” (March 2024) Oxford English Dictionary <www.oed.com>; and see
“emanate, v.” (March
2024) Oxford English Dictionary
<www.oed.com>.
[46]
“emanation, n.” (March 2024) Oxford English Dictionary
<www.oed.com> (emphasis
added).
[47] “emanate,
v.” (March 2024) Oxford English Dictionary
<www.oed.com>.
[48]
Fearn v Tate Gallery (HC), above n 32, at [168(iii)]; see also Jeevan
Hariharan “The View from the Top: Visual Intrusion as Nuisance in Fearn
v Tate Gallery” (2024) 87 MLR 697 at 706; and Cheng Lim Saw and Aaron
Yoong “Throwing Stones in Glass Houses: Protecting Privacy under
the Law
of Nuisance” (2022) 28 Tort L Rev 145 at
150.
[49] See Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7, at 686 per Lord
Goff and 720 per Lord Cooke both citing G v City of Hamburg (1983) 88
BGHZ 344 at 348. The German Civil Code currently precludes a claimant from
prohibiting “the introduction of gases, steam, smells, smoke, soot,
warmth, noise, vibrations and similar influences emanating from another plot
of land to the extent that the influence does not impair the use of their
plot of land, or impairs it only to an insignificant extent”
(translated
and emphasis added): § 906(1), Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch
(Germany).
[50] See Part IV,
below.
[51] The Supreme Court
also cited academic commentary consistent with the idea that emanation involves
physical invasion: Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at [122], n 100 citing JW Neyers and
Jordan Diacur “What (is) a Nuisance? Antrim Truck Centre Ltd v Ontario
(Minister of Transportation)” (2011) 90 Can Bar Rev 213 at
219–220.
[52] At [124]
(citations omitted and emphasis added); see also Saw and Yoong, above n 48, at 150; and WVH Rogers Winfield
& Jolowicz on Tort (18th ed, Sweet & Maxwell, London 2010) at
[14-4], n 59.
[53]
Sedleigh-Denfield v O’Callaghan, above n 20, at 903 per Lord
Wright.
[54] The Supreme Court,
in the above passage, cited Herbert Broom, Joseph Gerald Pease and Herbert
Chitty A Selection of Legal Maxims, Classified and Illustrated (8th ed,
Sweet and Maxwell, London, 1911) at 289. Some sources emphasise that only uses
of property injuring the lawful rights of another are caught by the
maxim: see, for example, Fontainebleau Hotel Corp v Forty-Five Twenty-Five
Inc 114 So 2d 357 (Fla Dist Ct App 1959) at 359. But, if the maxim forms the
foundation of the tort of private nuisance (which is itself a metric for
lawfulness),
this is a tautology: Henry E Smith “Exclusion and Property
Rules in the Law of Nuisance” (2004) 90 Va L Rev 965 at
1004.
[55] David Neild
“Nuisance through emanation” [2016] NZLJ 333 at 333–334; and
see, for a counterexample, Deane v Clayton [1817] EngR 472; (1817) 7 Taunt 489, 129 ER 196
(Comm Pleas).
[56] Hunter v
Canary Wharf, above n 7, at 685
(emphasis added).
[57] See Simon
Douglas and Ben McFarlane “Defining Property Rights” in James Penner
and Henry Smith (eds) Philosophical Foundations of Property Law (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2013) 219 at
231–232.
[58] Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (HC), above n 42,
at [30] (emphasis added).
[59]
See Part I, Subpart C,
above.
[60] The
pre-Hunter, above n 7,
cases contain various instances of the use of the word
“emanation” used merely identify the origin of the interference:
see, for example, Southport v Esso Petroleum (QB), above n 26, at 776; Fortesque v Te Awamutu
Borough [1918] NZGazLawRp 201; [1918] NZLR 991 (SC) at 999; Relk Holdings Ltd v Manawatu
Wanganui Regional Council HC Hamilton CP172/92, 27 April 1993 at
15–16; and see also Young v Attorney-General [2021] NZHC 463 at
[110]. But, for an early example of a use of the word consistent with that in
Hunter, see Byrne v Judd [1908] NZLR 1106 (CA) at 1116 per
Denniston J: “[i]n what sense can it be said that the non-repair of the
breastwork [on the
appellant’s land] comes in any way within this
definition [of private nuisance]? Nothing emanated from the land of the
appellant”.
[61] Body
Corporate 366611 v Wu (CA), above n 42, at [94] (emphasis
added).
[62] Guppys (Bridport)
Ltd v Brookling (1984) 14 HLR 1
(EWCA).
[63] See Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [13] per
Lord Leggat JSC; and Simon Douglas “The Content of a Freehold: A
‘Right to Use’ Land?” in Nicholas
Hopkins (ed) Modern
Studies in Property Law vol 7 (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2013) 359 at
373.
[64] Thompson-Schwab v
Costaki [1956] 1 WLR 335 (CA); and Bank of New Zealand v Greenwood
[1983] NZHC 150; [1984] 1 NZLR 525 (HC).
[65]
Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at
[5].
[66] Fearn v Tate Gallery
(HC), above n 32, at [168(ii)]
(emphasis added).
[67]
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64, at
339.
[68] See, for example,
Roderick Bagshaw “The Edges of Tort Law’s Rights” in Donal
Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds) Rights and Private Law (Hart Publishing,
Oxford, 2012) 407 at 419.
[69]
Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7,
at 685–686 per Lord Goff; and see Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above
n 64, at 337–338 per Lord Evershed
MR and 341 per Romer LJ.
[70]
Douglas and McFarlane, above n 57, at
232 (emphasis added); and see Saw and Yoong, above n 48, at
149–150.
[71] See Bagshaw,
above n 68, at 419; and compare Ben
Pontin “A room with a view in English nuisance law: exploring
modernisation hidden within the ‘textbook
tradition’” (2018)
38 Legal Stud 627 at 641.
[72]
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64, at 340 (emphasis
added).
[73] At 339 (emphasis
added).
[74] BNZ v
Greenwood, above n 64; see also
Cosentino v Peter Medich Properties Pty Ltd [2003] NSWSC 606 at [41]; and
Zhang v Davies 2017 BCSC 1180, [2017] BCJ No 1350 at
[106].
[75] Christine French
“Rylands v Fletcher and Nuisance” in Christine French and
Stephen Todd (presenters) Update on Torts (New Zealand Law Society
seminar, October 1998) 58 at 70; Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7, at 700 per Lord Lloyd; and Fearn v
Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at
[178] per Lord Sales JSC citing Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7, per Lord Goff. However, it is not clear
that Lord Goff considered BNZ v Greenwood, above n 64, a non-emanation case: see Hunter v
Canary Wharf, above n 7, at
685–686; and compare Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [77] per Lord Leggat
JSC.
[76] See Karmarkar v
Kajol Enterprises Ltd [2024] NZHC 683 at [27] per Robinson
J.
[77] Anglian Water Services
Ltd v Crawshaw Robbins & Co Ltd [2001] BLR 173 (EWHC) at [137]; Douglas
and McFarlane, above n 57, at 232, n 59;
and see Thomas W Merrill “trespass and nuisance” in Peter Newman
(ed) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law (Palgrave
Macmillan, London, 2002) vol 3 617 at
619.
[78] See Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [16] per
Lord Leggat JSC.
[79] Fearn v
Tate Gallery (HC), above n 32, at
[178]; see Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [12]–[17] per Lord Leggat JSC
and [178]–[179] per Lord Sales JSC; and compare John P Jarecki
“Privacy in the
Panopticon: The Fourth Amendment Case Against Perpetual
Surveillance” (2022) 48(1) U Dayton L Rev 41 at 42–43 explaining
the
“invisible omnipresence” within Jeremy Bentham’s
panopticon penitentiary.
[80]
Compare Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7.
[81]
Christopher Essert “Nuisance and the Normative Boundaries of
Ownership” (2016) 52 Tulsa L Rev 85 at 97; see also Donal
Nolan “The
Essence of Private Nuisance” in Ben McFarlane and Sinéad Agnew
(eds) Modern Studies in Property Law vol 10 (Hart Publishing, Oxford,
2019) 71 at 83.
[82] Wernke v
Halas 600 NE 2d 117 (Ind App, 1992) at
122.
[83] Compare BNZ v
Greenwood, above n 64.
[84]
Wernke v Halas, above n 82, at
121. The Court provided a somewhat different formulation of the threshold test
citing Wendt v Kerkhof 594 NE 2d 795 (Ind App, 1992) at
797.
[85] See Dan B Dobbs The
Law of Torts (West Group, Saint Paul (MN), 2001) vol 2 at §
466.
[86] Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7, at 685 (emphasis
added).
[87] At 685 citing
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64.
[88]
Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7,
at 686.
[89] Anglian Water v
Crawshaw Robbins, above n 77, at
[137].
[90] At
[143].
[91] Shogunn v Public
Transport Authority, above n 38, at
[257]–[258] and [275].
[92]
See, for example, Torquay Hotel Co Ltd v Cousins [1969] 2 Ch 106
(Ch).
[93] Onus v Telstra Corp
Ltd [2011] NSWSC 33 at
[148]–[150].
[94]
Harbourcity v Owen, above n 38,
at [17] and [61] (emphasis added).
[95] Wu v Body Corporate
366611 (SC), above n 3, at [122]
(emphasis added).
[96] At [122],
n 103.
[97] BEMA Property
Investments Ltd v Body Corporate 366611 [2017] NZCA 281, [2018] 2 NZLR 514
at [57]. The Court made the same point in relation to Lord Goff’s use of
the words “generally arise” in Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n
7, at 685. See also Fearn v Tate
Gallery (HC), above n 32, at
[167].
[98] See BEMA v Body
Corporate 366611, above n 97, at
[55].
[99] Wu v Body Corporate
366611 (SC), above n 3, at [125]
(emphasis added).
[100] BEMA
v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97,
at [59].
[101] Compare Wu v
Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at [122], n
103.
[102] At [115]–[118]
and [132]; and BEMA v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97, at [47], [51]–[53] and
[59].
[103] See Part II,
Subpart C, above.
[104]
Nottingham Forest v Unison Networks (CA), above n 39.
[105]
At [47]. By focusing on the physical characteristics of the trees, the Court
confirmed that an emanation requirement is concerned
with the form, not the
origin, of the interference. It (briefly) addressed the question of origin
after establishing that the trees were emanations: “the branches
that successively fell onto Unison’s line here can be described
as
emanations from Nottingham Forest’s land where the trees were
growing” (emphasis
added).
[106] At [46] and n
44.
[107] Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [12] and
see [13]–[17] per Lord Leggat
JSC.
[108] See Part IV,
below.
[109] Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at
[13].
[110] At
[178]–[179] per Lord Sales JSC; and Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n
7, at 685 per Lord Goff (emphasis
added).
[111] See generally
Nolan, above n 34.
[112] Nolan, above n 81, at
79–81.
[113] Recall that
not all cases involving physical invasions are emanation cases: Part II,
Subpart D, above.
[114] See,
for example, Neyers and Diacur, above n 51, at
219.
[115] See, for example,
Richard W Wright “Private Nuisance Law: A Window on Substantive
Justice” in Donal Nolan and Andrew
Robertson (eds) Rights and Private
Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2012) 491 at
512.
[116] McBride, above n 28, at
7.
[117] Douglas and McFarlane,
above n 57, at
223.
[118] Waugh v
Attorney-General [2006] NZHC 352; [2006] 2 NZLR 812
(HC).
[119] Anchor Brewhouse
Developments Ltd v Berkley House (Docklands Developments) Ltd [1987] 2 EGLR
173 (Ch).
[120] SPAK (1996)
Ltd v LeRoy [2022] NZCA 564, (2022) 23 NZCPR 769 at
[104].
[121] Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at
231–232.
[122] Hawkes
Bay Protein Ltd v Davidson, above n 12.
[123]
St Helens Smelting Co v Tipping, above n 11.
[124]
Kidman v Page [1959] Qd R 53
(SC).
[125] Sturges v
Bridgman, above n 18.
[126]
Part I, Subpart C, above.
[127]
Douglas and McFarlane, above n 57, at
227–228; Douglas, above n 63, at
370; see also Thomas W Merrill “Property and the Right to Exclude”
(1998) 77 Neb L Rev 730 at 741; and Henry E Smith “Property as the Law of
Things” (2012) 125 Harv L Rev 1691 at
1704–1705.
[128] Douglas
and McFarlane, above n 57, at 225 and
232; and see further JE Penner “The “Bundle of Rights” Picture
of Property” (1996) 43 UCLA L Rev 711 at
743–744.
[129] Douglas
and McFarlane, above n 57, at
226–227.
[130] At
224.
[131] See further Wesley
Newcomb Hohfeld Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial
Reasoning (Yale University Press, New Haven,
1919).
[132] But see Part I,
Subpart C, above. A dispute does not always arise in this
manner.
[133] That is not to
say that, in the absence of emanation, a user of land can commit no wrong: see
Douglas and McFarlane, above n 57, at
220–221. Indeed, in New Zealand, we might locate a personal,
privacy wrong on the very facts of Fearn, above n 1, notwithstanding that the defendant would
be using their land: see generally Hosking v Runting [2004] NZCA 34; [2005] 1 NZLR 1
(CA); C v Holland [2012] NZHC 2155, [2012] 3 NZLR 672; see, in
particular, Faesenkloet v Jenkin [2014] NZHC 1637; and see Part V,
Subpart C, Section 2,
below.
[134] Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7; Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3;
BEMA v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97; and Guppys v Brookling, above n
62.
[135]
See generally James Lee and others “Nuisance in the UK Supreme
Court” (3 February 2023) Obligations Discussion Group
<www.stevehedley.com/odg>; Hariharan, above n 48, at 705; and Michael JR Crawford
“The Tort of Nuisance: From the Outside Looking In” (Melbourne
University Law Review,
Volume 47, No 3, 2024) (forthcoming) at
2.
[136] See Crawford, above n
135, at
2.
[137] See Douglas, above n
63, at 373 saying the same of Guppys
v Brookling, above n 62.
[138]
Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [13]; compare generally Nolan, above
n 81.
[139]
See Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7, at 685 per Lord Goff, 709–710 per
Lord Hoffman and 726 per Lord
Hope.
[140] Thompson-Schwab
v Costaki, above n 64; BEMA v
Body Corporate 366611, above n 97;
Guppys v Brookling, above n 62;
Torquay Hotel v Cousins, above n 92; and see also, for example, Hubbard v
Pitt [1976] QB 142
(CA).
[141] Nolan, above n 7, at 467; see also Fearn v Tate Gallery
(SC), above n 1, at
[13].
[142] Essert, above n 81, at 96–97; and see Wernke v
Halas, above n 82.
[143]
Bagshaw, above n 68, at 418; see also
Hariharan, above n 48, 705–706;
and BEMA v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97, at [55]. Note that “energy
transfers” are capable of constituting emanations: see Part II, Subparts A
and D, above.
[144] See Part
II, Subpart B, above.
[145] R
Buckley “Nuisance, Rylands v Fletcher and Similar Liabilities” in
Andrew Tettenborn and others (eds) Clerk & Lindsell on Torts (24th
ed, Sweet & Maxwell, London, 2023) 1387 at
[19-08].
[146] Robinson v
Kilvert [1889] UKLawRpCh 47; (1889) 41 Ch D 88 (CA) at 94 per Cotton LJ and 96 per Lindley LJ;
Sanders-Clark v Grosvenor Mansions Co Ltd [1900] UKLawRpCh 109; [1900] 2 Ch 373 (Ch) at 374;
Reinhardt v Mentasti [1889] UKLawRpCh 140; (1889) 42 Ch D 685 (Ch) at 687; and Cosentino v
Peter Medich Properties, above n 74,
at [41].
[147] Dublin
(South) City Market Co v McCabes Ltd [1953] IR 283 (HC) at
311.
[148] See Hunter v
Canary Wharf, above n 7, at
685–686 per Lord Goff and 700 per Lord Lloyd; and Wu v Body Corporate
366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[122].
[149] Essert, above n 81, at
96.
[150] James Y Stern
“What Is the Right to Exclude and Why Does It Matter?” in James
Penner and Michael Otsuka (eds) Property
Theory: Legal and Political
Perspectives (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018) 38 at
46.
[151] Richard A Epstein
“Nuisance Law: Corrective Justice and Its Utilitarian Constraints”
(1979) 8 J Legal Stud 49 at
53.
[152] See Laura S
Underkuffler The Idea of Property – Its Meaning and Power (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2003) at
21–24.
[153] Scholars
have described the shape in various, informal ways: see, for example, Essert,
above n 81, at 95, n 48
(“spherical sector”); Thomas W Merrill, Henry E Smith and Dennis
Patterson (ed) The Oxford Introductions to US Law: Property (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2010) at 31 (“column or carrot of space”);
and Douglas, above n 63, at 368
(“vertical column”). It is best described as the space enclosed by a
nappe of the conical surface defined by
the centre of the Earth and the closed
boundary curve: see Alphonse A Adler The Theory of Engineering Drawing (D
Van Nostrand Co, New York, 1912) at
166.
[154] We can limit the
ability of each of a community of proprietors to exercise their rights against
other members of the community: see
Merrill, above n 127, at 750; Smith, above n 54, at 987–988; and Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[116]. Also, the ceiling of a proprietor’s right is effectively limited,
and I therefore say that the ad coelum rule effectively distributes space
to zero people beyond the lower airspace: see Bernstein of Leigh (Baron) v
Skyviews & General Ltd [1975] QB 479 (QB) at 488; and Henry E Smith
“The Persistence of System in Property Law” (2015) 163 U Pa L Rev
2055 at 2080.
[155] Merrill and
Smith, above n 153, at 31; see Ted
Sichelman and Henry E Smith “A network model of legal relations”
(2024) 382 Phil Trans R Soc at 10–11; Douglas, above n 63, at 368; and Bocardo SA v Star Energy
UK Onshore Ltd [2010] UKSC 35, [2011] 1 AC 380 at [6] and
[14].
[156] Ellis v Loftus
Iron Co [1874] UKLawRpCP 81; (1874) LR 10 CP 10 (Comm Pleas) at 12 per Lord Coleridge
CJ.
[157] See Epstein, above n
151, at 53; and Thomas W Merrill and
Henry E Smith “What Happened to Property in Law and Economics?”
[2001] YaleLawJl 34; (2001) 111 Yale LJ 357 at
395.
[158] Smith, above n 127, at 1706 referring to the “things
defined by” the right to exclude (emphasis
added).
[159] Christian von Bar
and Jason Grant Allen (tr) Foundations of Property Law: Things as Objects of
Property Rights (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2023) at
[7.8].
[160] See generally
Douglas and McFarlane, above n 57.
[161]
See Essert, above n, at 94–96 describing the “intuitive
appeal” of the physical invasion
view.
[162] Epstein, above n 151, at
53.
[163] Part I, Subpart C,
above.
[164] McBride, above n
28, at
7.
[165] Ben Ohavi “Why
Metaphysics Matters: The Case of Property Law” (2024) 43 Law and
Philosophy 367 at 379 (emphasis added);
and see also Sichelman and Smith, above
n 155, at
11.
[166] Essert, above n 81, at 107, n 115; see Sichelman and Smith,
above n 155, at 10; and see also
Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7,
at 723 per Lord Hope.
[167]
Sturges v Bridgman, above n 18.
[168]
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64; and see Part II, Subpart D, Secti0n 1,
above.
[169] See Part IV,
Subpart A, Section 2,
above.
[170] Essert, above n 81, at 109, n
126.
[171] See generally
Merrill, above n 127.
[172]
Thomas W Merrill “Trespass, Nuisance, and the Costs of Determining
Property Rights” (1985) 14 J Legal Stud 13 at
14.
[173] Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at 225–226;
Douglas, above n 63, at 369; see also
Wright, above n 115, at 510–511;
and Epstein, above n 151, at
53.
[174] Merrill, above n 172, at
28–29.
[175] At 14 and
see 29; and see Merrill, above n 77, at
619.
[176] Merrill, above n 172, at 34 (emphasis added). Supposedly,
these low transaction cost scenarios, coupled with trespass’ simple rules,
permit communities
to maximise welfare themselves. Intangible invasions do not
share these characteristics and so supposedly lend themselves better
to a post
hoc evaluation under the guise of a private nuisance enquiry: see generally
Merrill, above n 172; and Merrill, above
n 77.
[177]
See, for example, Neyers and Diacur, above n 51, at
235.
[178] Douglas, above n 63, at
369.
[179] I borrow this phrase
from Smith, above n 154, at
2079.
[180] Merrill, above n 172, at 14; Merrill, above n 77, at 617; and see also Neyers and Diacur,
above n 51, at
219–220.
[181] Atkin,
above n 27, at
[9.2.1].
[182] BEMA v Body
Corporate 366611, above n 97, at
[59]; and see Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3, at
[132].
[183] See, for example,
Nolan, above n 7, at
481.
[184] Nottingham Forest
v Unison Networks (CA), above n 39,
at [45].
[185] Compare
Guppys v Brookling, above n 62;
and Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3.
[186]
Austin v Rentrezi 2 Ltd [2021] NZHC 1027, (2021) 23 NZCPR 77 at
[81]–[97].
[187] Nolan,
above n 7, at 481. Nolan’s
distinction is not flawless: Nolan, above n 81, at 84–85. In particular, it is
circular given it relies on lawfulness to determine the applicable standard of
lawfulness.
The superior metric in relation to the second principle might be the
extent to which the defendant controls the thing: see Nicholas
J McBride and
Roderick Bagshaw Tort Law (6th ed, Pearson, Harlow (UK), 2018) at
381–383.
[188] Hunter
v Canary Wharf, above n 7, at
685.
[189] Wright, above n 115, at 512 (emphasis added); and see also
Neyers and Diacur, above n 51, at
220.
[190] I borrow
Nolan’s use of the term “neat”: see Nolan, above n 7, at 467; and see also Geoff McLay
“The Once and Future Law of Nuisance?” [1997] NZLJ 222 at
225.
[191] Epstein, above n 151, at 77–78; and see also Essert,
above n 81, at
99–100.
[192] Such a
right may be the effect of the Supreme Court’s majority decision in
Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1: compare Fairhouse v Woodward CC
Oxford G00MK61, 12 October 2022 at [129] following Fearn v Board of Trustees
of the Tate Gallery [2020] EWCA Civ 104, [2020] Ch 621 at [74]; see
Hariharan, above n 48, at 706; and Paul
Henty “Dr Mary Fairhurst v Mr Jon Woodard: Lessons in CCTV and data
protection” (2022) 11(3) Comp &
Risk 8 at
11.
[193] See Nolan, above n 7, at
465.
[194] See Essert, above n
81, at
98.
[195] Nolan, above n 7, at
466–467.
[196] Part II,
Subpart A, above.
[197]
Buckley, above n 145, at [19-08];
BEMA v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97, at [58], n 72; and Neild, above n 55, at
335–336.
[198] Guppys
v Brookling, above n 62.
[199]
Hunter v Canary Wharf, above n 7.
[200]
That is, it is more apt to ask whether an interest against any particular
non-emanatory interference constitutes a “natural
right”, one that
can only be acquired or a “no right” such that “[i]n carrying
out that ranking, the courts
consider both the gravity of the threat which the
type of interference in question poses to potential claimants’ security
interests,
and the extent to which granting protection against this type of
interference would threaten the freedom of action of potential
defendants”:
Nolan, above n 7, at
467.
[201] I borrow this
formulation from Essert, above n 81, at
95.
[202] Thompson-Schwab v
Costaki, above n 64; Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1; BEMA v
Body Corporate 366611, above n 97;
and Guppys v Brookling, above n 62.
[203]
Part III, Subpart B,
above.
[204] Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [12] per
Lord Leggat JSC.
[205] I use
“neighbours” in the sense of two people who hold nearby land;
compare Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562 (HL) at 580–581 per Lord
Atkin; and see Delaware Mansions Ltd v Westminster City Council [2001]
UKHL 55, [2002] 1 AC 321 at [29] per Lord Cooke. If we adopt Lord Atkin’s
terminology, we might nonetheless describe land and tortfeasors within a
neighbourhood
circumscribed by private nuisance “neighbours” for the
purposes of private nuisance, but this is liable to
confuse.
[206] Essert, above n
81, at
107.
[207] JE Penner
Property Rights: A Re-Examination (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2020)
at 148–149 and
following.
[208] Nolan, above n
81, at
73–78.
[209] Beever,
above n 23, at 22–25 and see
43–45; and compare Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [24] and [35] per Lord Leggat
JSC.
[210] See Penner, above n
207, at
143–148.
[211] Essert,
above n 81, at 87–88; Penner,
above n 207, at 144; see generally
Nolan, above n 81; and Nolan, above n 7, at
466–467.
[212] See
further Stern, above n 150, at 59 and
following.
[213] BEMA v Body
Corporate 366611, above n 97, at
[54].
[214] Bagshaw, above n 68, at
418.
[215] At
418.
[216] Part IV, Subpart A,
Section 2, above.
[217]
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64; Laws v Florinplace Ltd [1981] 1
All ER 659 (Ch); and see also Mark v Department of Fish and Wildlife 974
P 2d 716 (Or App 2004).
[218]
Bagshaw, above n 68, at 419; and see
Part II, Subpart D,
above.
[219] See Roderick
Bagshaw “Private Nuisance: The UK Supreme Court Take a View” (2023)
16 J Tort Law 173 at 176–177,
n
12.
[220] Merrill, above n 172, at
34.
[221] See Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [212]
per Lord Sales JSC; and McBride, above n 28, at
7.
[222] See Shelley Geiszler
“Nuisance Most Fowl: The Problem with Chicago’s Permissive Livestock
Ordinance and How to Fix it”
(2020) 95 Chi-Kent L Rev 367 at
388.
[223] See Richard A
Epstein Torts (Aspen Law & Business, New York, 1999) at §
14.5.
[224] Nottingham
Forest v Unison Networks (CA), above n 39.
[225]
Matheson v Northcote College, above n 21.
[226]
See Merrill, above n 172, at 34. He, of
course, suggests that the invasions by these entities may only be trespasses:
see Part IV, Subpart C, Section 1,
above.
[227] BNZ v
Greenwood, above n 64; and
Matheson v Northcote College, above n 21.
[228]
Matheson v Northcote College, above n 21, at
112.
[229] In particular, the
literature considers invasion by acid rain. Nancy Hughes Milstone “A
Common Law Solution to the Acid Rain
Problem” (1986) 20 Val U L Rev 277 at
278–279 and 288; Jay L Johnson “Acid Rain: Minnesota Remedies”
(1983)
1 William Mitchell Envtl LJ 82 at 97–98; see generally Timothy
Crawford “The Problems of Causation in Private Legal Remedies
for Damage
from Acid Rain” (1984) 17 Nat Resources Law 413; compare Smith v
Fonterra, above n 5, at
[153]–[167]; and see also Jalla v Shell International Trading and
Shipping Co Ltd [2023] UKSC 16, [2024] AC 595 at [7]. Note that in
Smith, the Supreme Court reinstated the appellant’s claim in
public nuisance. In Jalla, the parties disagreed on whether an oil
spill more than 100 km from the claimants’ land caused the accumulation of
oil on
the claimants’ land. Provided the claimants can establish
causation, emanation implies physical
proximity.
[230] Bagshaw, above
n 26, at 167; see also Lippiatt v
South Gloucestershire, above n 40,
at 65 per Sir Christopher Staughton; and Goudkamp and Nolan, above n 23, at
[15-042].
[231] We return to
this in Part V, Subpart C, Section 3,
below.
[232] Thompson-Schwab
v Costaki, above n 64.
[233]
This appears to be Bagshaw’s primary consideration: see Bagshaw, above n
68, at
419.
[234] We return to this
question in Part V, Subpart C, Section 1,
below.
[235] See
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64, at 339 per Lord Evershed MR and 342 per
Romer LJ; and Laws v Florinplace, above n 217, at
665–666.
[236] But see
Newell v Izzard [1944] 3 DLR 118 (NBSC) at 124. Chief Justice Baxter
issued an injunction in relation to the defendant’s business simply
attracting “loose and disorderly persons”. The description
ought to be in relation to those loose and disorderly things—the
use of
vile language and sexual misconduct, for example—occurring in proximity to
the claimant’s land: see
122.
[237] Laws v
Florinplace, above n 217, at
662–663 and 667.
[238]
Richard Kidner “Nuisance and Rights of Property” (1998) 62 Conv 267
at 278. Note that Kidner characterised the conduct
of the defendants in
both Costaki, above n 64,
and Florinplace, above n 217, as being “mere
presence”, but the complaint was that the defendants were, in fact,
doing something undesirable (having immoral sex or vending
pornography).
[239] Laws v
Florinplace, above n 217, at
666–667.
[240] Douglas
and McFarlane, above n 57, at
236.
[241] Cases in relation to
the liability of non-servient owners are not common, but see, for example,
Paine & Co Ltd v St Neots Gas & Coke Co [1939] 3 All ER 812 (CA);
Balfour Beatty Group Ltd v Persons Unknown [2022] EWHC 874 (QB); High
Speed Two (HS2) Ltd v Persons Unknown [2022] EWHC 2360 (KB) at [86];
Island Gas Ltd v Persons Unknown [2018] EWHC 3743 (Ch) at [3(2)] and
[58]; and Ineos Upstream Ltd v Persons Unknown [2017] EWHC 2945 (Ch) at
[106].
[242] Paine v St
Neots Gas, above n 241, at 823 per
Luxmoore LJ.
[243] Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at 236; and see
Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld “Faulty Analysis in Easement and License
Cases” (1917) 27 Yale LJ 66 at
71–72.
[244] Pettey v
Parsons [1914] UKLawRpCh 92; [1914] 2 Ch 653 (CA) at 662 per Lord Cozens-Hardy
MR.
[245] Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at 236. In New
Zealand, it might be that an assessment is made of the impact of the
claimant’s use of the dominant tenement, except where the easement
is in gross, which precludes such an assessment: see DW McMorland McMorland
on Easements, Covenants and Licences (5th ed, LexisNexis, Wellington,
2023).
[246] See Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at 236, n 70; and
see Part II, Subpart B,
above.
[247] In addition to the
following, see Penner, above n 207, at
144, n 23; and John Baker An Introduction to English Legal History (5th
ed, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2019) at 451 and
following.
[248] Wall v
Collins [2009] EWHC 2100 (Ch) at [33]; compare Guppys v Brookling,
above n 62; and see Penner, above n 207, at
144.
[249] Balfour Beatty v
Persons Unknown, above n 241, at
[41] and [72].
[250] See Part
II, Subpart D, Section 1,
above.
[251] See Douglas and
McFarlane, above n 57, at 236; and Part
V, Subpart C, Section 2,
below.
[252] Guppys v
Brookling, above n 62; and see Part
III, Subpart A, above.
[253]
Waterman v Boyle [2009] EWCA Civ 115, [2009] 2 EGLR 7 at
[20].
[254] See Part V, Subpart
A, above.
[255] Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3.
[256]
BEMA v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97, at
[57].
[257] Body Corporate
366611 v Wu (CA), above n 42, at
[94].
[258] Note that this
raises the issue of whether the interference originated from the
claimant’s land, being the common property.
The Court of Appeal’s
analysis on this point is persuasive, concluding that the defendant’s
“interest in the common
property is quite distinct from that of Mr Wu in
his individual unit”: Body Corporate 366611 v Wu (CA), above n 42, at
[97(a)].
[259] Wu v Body
Corporate 366611 (HC), above n 42,
at [31]. The same issue referred to, above n 258,
arises.
[260] Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at
[212].
[261] At
[2].
[262] At [158] per Lord
Sales JSC; and see Part I, Subpart C,
above.
[263] For example, if
the defendant flew “hot air balloons from the street outside the
Tate Modern” (emphasis added): McBride, above n 28, at 8. See further Jalla v Shell,
above n 229, at [2] and [47]–[49]
per Lord Burrows JSC with whom Lord Sales JSC, amongst the unanimous panel,
agreed. That a private nuisance
may be committed from the sea was assumed
true, but it was not addressed due to procedural
defects.
[264] Essert, above n
81, at
102.
[265] See Jeremy Waldron
“Homelessness and the Issue of Freedom” (1991) 39 UCLA L Rev 295 at
305; and RH Coase “The Problem
of Social Cost” (1960) 3 JLE 1 at
2.
[266] Thompson-Schwab v
Costaki, above n 64.
[267]
Waldron, above n 265, at 296 and see
302; see Essert, above n 81, at 102; and
Christopher Essert “Property and Homelessness” (2016) 44 Phil &
Pub Aff 266 at 275.
[268] Part
V, Subpart A, above.
[269] See
Part V, Subpart B, above.
[270]
Coase, above n 265, at 2; and see
Essert, above n 81, at
104.
[271] Coase, above n 265, at 22 and
following.
[272] Part I,
Subpart C, above.
[273]
Cambridge Water Co v Eastern Counties Leather plc [1993] UKHL 12; [1994] 2 AC 264 (HL) at
299 per Lord Goff; Lawrence v Fen Tigers Ltd [2014] UKSC 13, [2014] AC
822. at [5] per Lord Neuberger PSC; and Fearn v Tate Gallery (SC), above
n 1, at [211] per Lord Sales
JSC.
[274] Part I, Subpart C,
above.
[275] See Part V,
Subpart A, above.
[276]
Shogunn v Public Transport Authority, above n 38, at [261(10)] (emphasis added) and see
also [271].
[277] At
[261(11)].
[278] Hunter v
Canary Wharf, above n 7, at
710.
[279] McBride, above n 28, at
7.
[280] See Merrill, above n
172, at
22.
[281] See Nolan, above n 7, at 467, n 49, asking “[i]s a phone
call an ‘emanation’?” The answer is ‘no’, because
the physical
thing transmitted through the boundary cannot be a private nuisance
by itself: see Part II, Subpart D, Section 2,
above.
[282] Hunter v Canary
Wharf, above n 7, at 691 citing
Khorasandjian v Bush [1993] EWCA Civ 18; [1993] QB 727
(CA).
[283] McLay, above n 190, at
224.
[284] See Fearn v Tate
Gallery (SC), above n 1, at [112]
per Lord Leggat JSC and [204] per Lord Sales JSC; and, in relation to emanation
cases, see Newark, above n 7, at
488–489.
[285] Compare
Christie v Davey, above n 13.
Note that the claimant in Christie was similarly
“targeted” because the defendant acted with
malice.
[286] Compare
Christie v Davey, above n 13; and
Thompson-Schwab v Costaki, above n 64.
[287]
Where, as in Christie v Davey, above n 13, or Khorasandjian v Bush, above n
282, the claimant themselves is
“targeted”, the targeting may form some relationship that sets the
scene for harms to the
claimant in their capacity as a person: see, for example,
Wright, above n 115, at 514 on malicious
injury. But it is the existence of physical proximity to the affected land which
implies that an injury caused
by an interference is one against the claimant in
their capacity as, perhaps amongst others, a
proprietor.
[288] Henry E Smith
“Modularity and Morality in the Law of Torts” (2011) 4(2)(5) J Tort
L 1 at 30; and see further von Bar,
above n 159, at
[7.1]–[7.10].
[289] See
Smith, above n 288, at 1; and Smith,
above n 54, at 978 and
984.
[290] Smith, above n 54, at
984.
[291] See generally Smith,
above n 127; and Douglas and McFarlane,
above n 57, at
239.
[292] See further
Sichelman and Smith, above n 155, at
10–11.
[293] Fearn v
Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1, at
[38] and following per Lord Leggat JSC (but note that his Lordship preferred to
not use the language of reasonableness: see [18]–[21])
and Lord Sales JSC
at [165] and following; Hawkes Bay Protein Ltd v Davidson, above n 12, at [3] and [16]–[23]; see BEMA
v Body Corporate 366611, above n 97,
at [47]; Sturges v Bridgman, above n 18, at 865; and see also Beever, above n 23, at
29–33.
[294] See Part V,
Subpart C, Section 1,
above.
[295] See Thomas W
Merrill and Henry E Smith “The Morality of Property” (2007) 48 Wm
& Mary L Rev 1849 at 1853–1857. However, they make this point in
relation to rights to exclude. The general theme of this Part is that notions
of
physical proximity extrapolate the benefits of the physical invasion
view.
[296] But see Christina
Spaulding “Anti-Pornography Laws As A Claim For Equal Respect:
Feminism, Liberalism & Community” (1988) 4 Berkeley
Women’s LJ 128; and compare Laws v Florinplace, above n 217. The general treatment of pornography
is distinct from its treatment by the law of private
nuisance.
[297] Hunter v
Canary Wharf, above n 7; Fearn v
Tate Gallery (SC), above n 1; and
Wu v Body Corporate 366611 (SC), above n 3.
[298]
Part III, Subpart B,
above.
[299] Tandem
Properties Ltd v Sheffield City Council [2024] EWHC 1926 (Ch) at
[86]–[90].
[300]
Hariharan, above n 48, at
713.
[301] This is a variation
of the facts of Fairhouse v Woodward, above n 192.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/UOtaLawTD/2024/9.html