Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
THE SOCRATIC METHOD: SILENCING COOPERATION
JENNY MORGAN*
Feminist law teachers in North America, as in Australia, have been grappling
with the issue of the silencing of women students,1 and
have added their voices to the growing chorus of criticism of the Socratic
method.2 This paper tentatively explores the
relationship between teaching styles and the silencing of women students in
classrooms. The paper
arises out of the experience of becoming a law student
after being a law teacher for some eighteen months, and my subsequent return
to
the front of the classroom. In other words, as with much feminist work, this
paper is grounded in my own experience, the experiences
of my student colleagues
that I observed and shared and in empirical work in and outside law classrooms.
I aim to explore various teaching styles and pose tentative views on the
effect they may have on student behaviour, particularly student
cooperation,
both in the classroom and outside it. The other related aim of the paper is to
raise specific questions about women’s
participation in law school
classrooms. In order to do this, I set up various ideal types, which may not
necessarily reflect actual
classroom practices in either North America or
Australia, but are used as a shorthand way of exploring the effect of teaching
styles.
The first style I discuss is the Socratic method. By this I
understand a form of teacher-student interaction in which the teacher
vigorously
cross-questions a student on her or his understanding of a particular case or
legal principle. The vast majority of the
interaction occurs between teacher and
student (rather than student and student) and is teacher-initiated. The second
teaching style
is the lecture. In this form of teaching, the teacher does most
of the talking. Traditionally, student contribution is not encouraged
and, where
student contribution occurs, it is likely to take the form of clarificatory
questions. The third teaching style is the
seminar or tutorial, where, ideally,
the majority of contributions come from students, and students engage in a
dialogue with each
other, as well as with the teacher.
In some senses this
article is, in the Australian context, a cautionary tale. It has been suggested
that Australian law teachers do
not often use the Socratic style of teaching.
This may be true, though I would suggest that it is used, perhaps not identified
under
the particular Socratic rubric. What concerns me is the possibility of its
increased use in Australian classrooms. Whilst I accept
that the Socratic method
is more commonly used in North America than in Australia, and certainly more
extolled there, it is often
seen here as a cure for non-participatory students.
As we encourage the lecturer in a large lecture class to allow more student
contribution,3 I am cautioning against using the
Socratic style as our favoured means of encouraging that contribution. The
dyadic teacher-student
Socratic style models more than crucial analytical
skills.4
CRITICS AND DEFENDERS OF THE SOCRATIC METHOD
Critics of the Socratic method have commented on its
ability to subordinate students, regardless of their
gender;5 the patterning of hierarchical relationships
that occurs — “manipulating vulnerable people is an acceptable form
of professional
behaviour”6 — a pattern
which may carry over into the professional practice in which students will
ultimately engage;7 and the alienation of students
which the Socratic method induces.8
Kennedy has
noted that the American first year law class invades the “sense of
autonomy one has in a lecture”; and while
his characterisation of the
lecture does not make it sound very engaging — “you must let the
teacher drone on without
interruption” — he points to the payoff
— “the teacher can’t do anything to
you.”9 The payoff for the law professor in
utilizing the Socratic style has been described in this way: “Any half-way
decent academic
could walk into a Socratic class with 10 minutes preparation and
a few off-the-wall questions for students, whereas preparing lectures
was very
time consuming.”10 This implies that the Socratic
style need not be any more engaging, for either teacher or student, than the
oft-repeated lecture.11
Stone, in an early response
to Kennedy’s polemic, identifies what he sees as a number of virtues in
the Socratic method. It
aims to,
develop crucial analytic skills, to accustom the student to the lawyer’s adversary style of exchange, and to provide a forum in which the student speaks in public. Also prized in and of itself is the intense electric quality of Socratic classrooms as contrasted with the atmosphere supposedly characteristic of the British school ... where the lecture has been the predominant classroom instrument.12
It seems
obvious that lectures and seminars can and do teach crucial analytical skills
— after all, much British, Australian
and even American legal education
takes this form.13 Others have questioned the need for
a concentration on the adversary method. For example, Carrie
Menkel-Meadow14 has noted that there are many more
skills involved in being a lawyer than adversarial interchange and much legal
work, even that
involved in preparation for litigation, is cooperative rather
than adversarial. As to the provision of a public forum, the Socratic
method
provides a forum that may be particularly congenial for men students and
uncongenial for at least some women and creates an
environment in later year
seminars which continues this difference.
I want to focus on the effect on
students of teaching styles. Kennedy has graphically described the degradation
and infantilization
of students. My own experience as a recipient of the
Socratic style (not in Paper Chase form, I hasten to add), has alerted me to
a
particular aspect of the pseudo-participation15 of the
style: the way it appears to work to discourage student-student interaction.
This is the aspect on which I shall concentrate.
While I may be accused of
extolling the virtues of the best lecture or seminar and presenting a picture of
the worst-case Socratic
class — after all, many professors do prepare
quite thoroughly for Socratic classes — surely Stone has taken the Kennedy
image of the lecturer droning on to its extreme and neglected the quite electric
atmosphere that can be generated in seminars and
even lectures — an
electricity that does not need to damage those who participate. Stone comments
on, “the effect [that]
the Socratic method has upon interpersonal
relationship. Indeed perhaps the most impressive aspect of the law school milieu
is the
unpleasant quality of interpersonal relationships among
students.”16 Rather than celebrating this
atmosphere, it is necessary to address the effect that this atmosphere has on
students’ learning
and, in particular, the effect on women students’
participation in the classroom, especially in later year seminars.
The Teacher as Centre of Attention
While the focus on the teacher in any class may be
unavoidable,17 the focus in a Socratic class is
particularly stark. Perhaps the focus is even more obvious in a traditional
lecture where the lecturer
is the only one speaking but in a lecture there is
often little pretence of student participation. Student questions may be allowed
but not necessarily encouraged and student comments are almost non-existent.
Once it is assumed that others are supposed to participate,
the nature of that
interaction becomes particularly important.
It may be more accurate to
describe the focus of a Socratic class as the professor-student pair. Typically,
the professor calls on
a student, asks a question and follows with a series of
related questions. The interaction is dyadic. Another student will be called
on,
not usually to respond to the first student’s points, but to answer
further professorial questions. Occasionally, a student
will be asked to oppose
another student in a mini mock moot. While this latter process symbolically
gives some validity to the students’
contributions, it is not so much a
model for student cooperation as a model of the adversarial process; by
definition, it is oppositional.
In my ideal-type seminar, student questions
and comments are not only allowed but encouraged, and ideally dialogue occurs
not just
between professor and students, but between student and student.
Student and teacher are engaged in a shared learning
exercise.18 As a student once again, albeit in an
American law school and avowedly non-Socratic seminars, I was struck that
students rarely if
ever addressed each other. My suggestion is that this
reflects the greater emphasis in American legal education on the use of the
Socratic method in first year law classes. In one American later year seminar, a
student commented that I was the only person who,
after five weeks of class, had
addressed a comment directly to another student, rather than to, or, at best,
via the professor.19 Although I am sure women spoke
less frequently in seminars during my Australian legal education than their
numbers in the class would
warrant, I did not have a sense that we as students
were unable to talk to each other, but only to or through the teacher.
Student Cooperation Occurs Elsewhere?
Some may argue that student cooperation occurs
outside the classroom rather than inside. Students see themselves as engaged in
a joint
battle against the professor and form study groups to prepare themselves
for the professorial onslaught. Dillon draws attention to
this in his
description of Paper Chase, and outlines a limited form of cooperation depicted
there which is withdrawn at exam-time
and not in evidence in the
classroom.20 I doubt that such cooperation is
deliberately withdrawn at exam time, but I would suggest that the depiction of
lack of support in
the classroom is accurate. I do not believe that many
students consciously relish a colleague being placed on the spot, but I observed
little effort at supporting the student in a typical Socratic
cross-questioning.21 Even if cooperative student
behaviour does occur outside the classroom, I suggest it does not transfer to
later year classroom interaction.
From the teacher’s viewpoint, it is
not adequate that student cooperation occurs outside the classroom. The
professor has to
take responsibility for what occurs in the classroom and cannot
rely on student activity outside to remedy the classroom experience.
A classroom
can provide powerful models for behaviour and the public nature of the class
makes it even more important that appropriate
behaviour is modelled.
Student Competition and the Inarticulate Student
I suggested above that there is little effort to
support the cross-questioned student against the teacher in normal classroom
interaction.
In America, if anything, there appears to be competition for the
professor’s attention. An oft-repeated complaint is, “the
professor
never calls on me.” This competition is antithetical to cooperation. One
reason for the competition is that in the
Socratic style the vast majority of
the questions come from the professor rather than the students.
In seminars,
questions are much more likely to come from students. Dillon suggests that
student questions are likely to lead to a
more effective transfer of legal
knowledge than professorial questions. While this may be true, it is the effect
on student-to-student
behaviour that concerns me here. Where students are asking
the questions, there is less incentive to divine the right answer for
the
professor, for the answer the student offers is at least in part for the other
student. Of course, at times the process is short-circuited
and the teacher
responds directly to the question without attempting to involve other students.
Even so, the teacher is less likely
to give out verbal rewards for good
questions than good answers, so if student participation occurs in the form of
genuine questions
as well as answers, a less competitive environment is likely
to be created. In the traditional lecture, if there is any student
participation,
it is most likely to be student initiated and come in the form of
questions rather than answers and once again the rewards and the
competition are
lessened.
My particular concern here is with the thoughtful inarticulate
student who may require time to formulate a response. The Socratic
style appears
to do nothing to encourage those students. Neither, of course, does the lecture
but it, at least, does not actively
discourage the hesitant response. A properly
run seminar does allow for the hesitant student;22 I am
not sure that the Socratic style ever can. This is, in part, because of the
dyadic nature of the Socratic interaction: the interrogator,
the law teacher, is
almost always articulate. In a seminar, if students are both questioning and
responding, there is more likelihood
of a shared sense of uncertainty and a
shared development of confidence as opposed to the individualised demonstration
of verbal
skill or degradation.
WOMEN, MEN AND THE LAW CLASSROOM
Cooperation among students may not, of course, be the
aim of any of the teaching methods I have described. By the same token, none
have as their aim discouraging cooperation; it is, I have suggested, an
unintended side-effect of the Socratic style of teaching.
Even without embracing
the much broader tenets of a humanistic education in law, this unintended
byproduct must interfere with efforts
“to produce lawyers who are
creative, sensitive, and open to new ideas.”23
And the focus on competition rather than cooperation may particularly exclude
and silence women.
Women at Yale Law School have documented the
disproportionate frequency with which men speak in
classes.24 I observed a particular pattern. When
contributions are controlled by the teacher, and students are expected to bid
for attention
by raising their hands, women almost invariably lower their hands
when someone else is speaking while men are much more likely to
keep their hands
raised — to press their bids for attention. In practical terms, this also
means the teacher is more likely
to call on those persistently attempting to
participate instead of the one who ceased to interrupt while another was
talking. Pauline
Treichler and Cheris Kramarae, summarising Maltz and
Borker’s work suggest that boys learn, “to be assertive when others
have the floor,” and my anecdotal observation certainly supports the
thesis.25
The silencing of women appears to occur
in classrooms at university, college26 and school
level27 suggesting that a link with a Socratic style of
teaching may be misguided. I am not aware of any studies which attempt to
compare
women’s level of participation in law school classrooms with that
in other disciplines but I suspect that the Socratic style
has its own peculiar
contribution to make.28 Nor would I wish to discount
the complex interaction of various factors which may more fully account for
differential participation.
At the most obvious level, the gender of the
professor can affect the interaction of women.29
Frug30 and other31 have
documented how the construction of casebooks and courses disenfranchise women
by, among other things, excluding issues of particular
concern to women, and
this exclusion is likely detrimentally to affect women’s willingness to
participate.32 But this more complex analysis is beyond
the scope of this paper. I merely suggest that not only does the Socratic style
discourage
students from utilising cooperation rather than competition, but in
doing that, it may also exclude women’s voices. For as
boys are trained
assertively to take the floor and have, “an apparent ability to sustain a
monologue in the absence of overt
support, [girls have a] preference for shared
story telling,”33 — a preference which
means that as women they are particularly alienated from the monologue that is
expected from them as participants
in the Socratic process.
Carole
Edelsky34 describes the results of a detailed
linguistic analysis of a series of informal university committee meetings. She
found that while
men dominated what she described as Fl’s, that is a
singly developed floor, women participated much more in developing F2’s,
defined as a collaborative venture where several people seemed to be either
operating on the same wavelength or engaging in a
free-for-all.35 Indeed, not only did men participate
less in F2’s than Fl’s, they also often participated less than
women.36 She suggests that
Fl’s, characterized by monologues, single-party control and hierarchical interaction where turn takers stand out from non-turn takers and floors are won or lost, share features with other contexts in which women have learned they had best not assert themselves. F2’s, however, are inherently more informal, cooperative ventures that provide both a cover of “anonymity” for assertive language use and a comfortable backdrop against which women can display a fuller range of language ability.37
In other words, it would appear that the use of the
Socratic style, which I have suggested models competition rather than
cooperation,
may work differentially to silence women in the classroom. Implicit
in much of the previous discussion has been an awareness of Gilligan’s
work on women’s different voice.38 Gilligan
criticises the limited nature of much of the theoretical and empirical work on
moral development because it is focussed
only on a concept of justice, with its
emphasis on a hierarchy of rights and developed through empirical work on male
children only.
She suggests that moral reasoning can, and does, especially for
women, also focus on relationships between people and between people
and their
social context; and rather than seeing self and other as separate, it
emphasises, “a view of self and other as interdependent
and of
relationships as networks sustained by care-giving and
response.”39 In the classroom this conception of
morality is likely to be expressed in a model of cooperative rather than
competitive behaviour.
Catharine MacKinnon40 takes
Gilligan to task for failing to identify a causal mechanism for the expression
of a web of connection rather than a hierarchy
of rights that she, or at least
those following her41 identify as a woman’s
voice. MacKinnon argues that voice arises out of the oppression of women and she
suggests a marked ambivalence
about celebrating this
difference.42 If we celebrate this difference, we are
playing into the hands of a male defined feminine stereotype which is likely to
do women
more harm than good. I agree with MacKinnon that we need to be very
wary of the political costs of privileging difference: are there
not shadows of
Bradwell v Illinois43 in the
descriptions of women’s’ lack of participation in the classroom? By
the same token, identifying the structural
causes of that lack of participation,
and the over-participation of men in classrooms, and re-emphasising the value of
cooperation,
may challenge in a small way the hierarchy of oppression. As
MacKinnon says, “that does not mean I throw out those values.
Those are
nice values; everyone should have them.”44
Clearly the relatively narrow concerns raised in this paper play into a much
larger debate about whether the law can receive a different
voice, a debate
which cannot be properly addressed here. Some will argue that the Socratic style
models perfectly appropriate behaviour
for traditional legal interaction: the
descriptions of a Socratic classroom are reminiscent of a court — the
judge speaks directly
to the prosecution and defence lawyers, not they to each
other. And Edelsky’s description of Fl’s could be a description
of a
court.45 Apart from the fact that there is obviously a
lot more even to traditional legal work than court interaction, it is
nevertheless
a matter for concern that courtrooms have been seen as arenas of
battle where the male norm of conflict prevails and where women
are seen as
inappropriate or ineffective participants. We should look at the causes that
make some forms of lawyering more effective
than others. The assumption that the
Socratic style is the, or even a, best way of teaching law, a fundamentally
different exercise
to practicing it, also needs rethinking.
IMPLEMENTING COOPERATION AND PARTICIPATION
Despite my creation of ideal types, it is obvious
that the mere classification of teaching styles into Socratic-method, lecture
and
seminar does not tell us how to move to a situation where students are
engaged with their own learning and assisting others to learn.
Although I have
clearly extolled the virtue of the seminar as the teaching method most likely to
lead to both cooperative behaviour
between students and increased positive
participation by women in law school classrooms, the suggestion clearly has some
flaws. At
the most obvious level, not all law schools are funded in such a way
as to allow for this form of teaching. It is also clear that
one could use a
Socratic style in a seminar. It is thus necessary to focus more closely on
teaching techniques and climates for learning.46
One obvious teaching technique which can both model cooperative behaviour
and encourage women to speak is the use of smaller groups
within a group or buzz
groups. Students can be broken up into smaller groups of two or more, depending
on the size of the class and
the physical arrangement of the classroom, to
discuss a particular issue, case or theory. One member of the group is asked to
report
back to the whole group.47 This method comes
close to ensuring that all students have a chance to participate at least within
their small group. Because the
focus of attention is away from the
teacher,48 students have to talk to each other and
given the less formal atmosphere, the quality of discussion within the small
group is more
likely to approach the shared floor-taking described above.
Another technique is to nominate a small number of students especially
to
prepare the reading for the coming week and be ready to lead class discussion on
that topic. Whilst both these techniques appear
most suitable for seminar-size
classes, they can be used in much larger groups.
Both of these techniques
create a learning climate which is less hierarchical and authoritarian than
either the traditional lecture
class or the typical Socratic style and should
encourage an environment where all students feel inclined to participate.
While the Socratic method is clearly not the sole explanation for
men’s disproportionate participation in law school classrooms,
it is
certainly a powerful model of a male-preferred style of interaction. And I
believe, even if the voice of cooperation stems
from oppression, all students
are missing out if we reinforce competition through the use of a Socratic style,
so that students appear
incapable of talking with each other in a classroom.
* Law Faculty, Melbourne University. I would like to thank the many people
who discussed the issues raised here with me or read various
versions of the
paper. These include Kathleen Daly, Lucinda Finley, Beth Gaze, Reg Graycar,
Peter Hanks, Judith Miller, Mary Jane
Mossman, Janet Richards, Susan Russell,
Barb Safriet, Joe Sommer and Jamie Studley.
© (1989). 1 Legal Educ
Rev 151.
1 This statement is based on numerous discussions I have had with teachers and students in Australia, Canada and the USA, as well as published and unpublished material. I am not aware of any detailed empirical research on the comparative participation of women and men in law school classrooms in Australia, but such work has been done in North America. See the submission to faculty from women students at Yale Law School on women’s silence in the classroom discussed in C Weiss & L Melling, The Legal Education of Twenty Women (1988) 40 Stan L Rev 1299. Harvard Women’s Law Association has demonstrated a similar concern. Informal discussion and observation convince me that the situation is likely to be little different in Australian law schools. See also J Taber et al, Gender, Legal Education, and the Legal Profession: An Empirical Study of Stanford Law Students and Graduates (1988) 40 Stan L Rev 1209; CL Hill, Sexual Bias in the Law School Classroom: One Student’s Perspective (1988) 38 J Legal Educ 603; S Wildman, The Question of Silence: Techniques to Ensure Full Class Participation (1988) 38 J Legal Educ 147; TL Banks, Gender Bias in the Classroom (1988) 38 J Legal Educ 137.
2 See, for example, D Kennedy, Legal Education and the Reproduction of Hierarchy: A Polemic Against the System (Cambridge, Massachusetts: AFAR, 1983) [hereinafter cited as Reproduction of Hierarchy]; D Kennedy, Legal Education as Training for Hierarchy, in David Kairys ed, The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982) at 40; K Klare, The Law School Curriculum in the 1980’s: What’s Left, (1982) 32 J Legal Educ 336; J Rifkin, Teaching Mediation: A Feminist Perspective on the Study of Law, in M Culley & C Portuges, eds, Gendered Subjects: The Dynamics of Feminist Teaching (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985) at 96.
3 This certainly appears to be the approach adopted by the Australasian Law Teaching Workshop. At the most recent workshop held in Warburton Victoria, July 1989, despite the scepticism of at least some participants, it was constantly suggested that techniques having obvious applicability to small group teaching such as brainstorming or buzz groups could be used successfully in large lecture classes. See B Boer, Australasian Law Teaching Clinic [1989] LegEdRev 12; (1989) 1 Legal Educ Rev 145.
4 Indeed, part of my interest in going to an American law school was to see the Socratic method in action. Naively perhaps, I had assumed that a Socratic teaching style would force the teacher to engage more closely and intensely with students, would place the teacher on the spot as I am placed in small group teaching, and would engage the students more directly with the material they were required to absorb. My own, albeit brief, experience with the Socratic method encouraged me to rethink my enthusiasm for the method.
5 Reproduction of Hierarchy, supra note 2.
6 Klare, supra note 2, at 341.
7 Id. See also C Menkel-Meadow, Portia in a Different Voice: Speculations on a Woman’s Lawyering Process (1985) 1 Berkeley Women’s LJ 39.
8 S Dallimore, The Socratic Method — More Harm Than Good (1977) 3 J Contemp L 177.
9 Reproduction of Hierarchy, supra note 2, at 3.
10 This particular description comes from a statement made by a law professor in an Issues in Legal Education class at Yale Law School in the fall semester 1986.
11 This is not to suggest that there is no such thing as a well-prepared Socratic class.
12 A Stone, Legal Education on the Couch (1971) 85 Harv L Rev 392, at 409.
13 Accepting for a moment that performance on examinations is the test of success of a method of teaching law, and/or of crucial analytic skills, it would seem that students performance appears to be much the same whatever conventional group method of teaching is used. PF Teich, Research On American Law Teaching: Is There A Case Against The Case System (1 986) 36 J Legal Educ 167.
14 Menkel-Meadow, supra note 7.
15 Reproduction of Hierarchy, supra note 2, at 3.
16 Stone, supra note 12, at 415.
17 See, in particular, T Pickard, Experience as Teacher: Discovering the Politics of Law Teaching (1983) 33 U Toronto LJ 279. Pickard discusses the very real difficulties, both for professor and students, when a law professor attempts to hand control of a course over to students and to de-emphasise the role of the professor.
18 While this by no means occurs in every classroom, it is, at least, usually aimed for and sometimes achieved.
19 In fairness, I should note that the professor concerned had observed the interactional problems and suggested, some seven weeks into the course, that we all make an effort to create some dialogue between students.
20 JT Dillon, Paper Chase and the Socratic Method of Teaching Law (1980) 30 J Legal Educ 529.
21 See Weiss & Melling, supra note 1, at 1338 n 110.
22 Helene Keyssar suggests, “in a seminar ... part of the teacher’s task is to discern the slightest indication that a usually silent student member wants to speak.” H Keyssar, Staging the Feminist Classroom: A Theatrical Model, in M Culley & C Portuges, eds, Gendered Subjects: The Dynamics of Feminist Teaching (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985) 108, at 113.
23 Yale University, Bulletin of Yale Law School 1986–1987 (New Haven: Yale University, 1986) at 13.
24 See Weiss & Melling, supra note 1.
25 PA Treichler & C Kramarae, Women’s Talk in the Ivory Tower (1983) 31 Comm Q 118, at 119.
26 For documentation of women’s experiences at college and university, see RM Hall & BR Sadler, The Classroom Climate: A Chilly One for Women (Washington: Project on the Status and Education of Women, 1982).
27 See, for example, PS Sears & DH Feldman, Teacher Interactions with Boys and with Girls, in J Stacey, S Bereaud & J Daniels eds, And Jill Came Tumbling After: Sexism in American Education (New York: Dell Publishing, 1974); D Spender, Invisible Women: The Schooling Scandal (London: Writers and Readers Publishing Cooperative Society, 1982); D Spender, Talking in Class, in D Spender & E Sarah eds, Learning to Lose: Sexism and Education (London: Women’s Press, 1980); E Sarah, Teachers and Students in the Classroom: An Examination of Classroom Interaction, in D Spender & E Sarah eds, Learning to Lose: Sexism and Education (London: Women’s Press, 1980).
28 Although, for example, many of the interviewees in the Weiss and Melling article were quite persistent participators in their college class rooms but found themselves unable or unwilling to contribute in law classrooms. See Weiss & Melling, supra note 1, at 1333.
29 For example, Karp and Yoels found in their study of college classrooms that,
in male taught classes men account for 75.4% of the interactions, three times the percentage for women — 24.6%. In female taught classes, men still account for more of the interactions than women — 57.8% to 42.2% — but the percentage of female participation increases almost 75% [where the percentage of men and women students was almost equal]. DA Karp & WC Yoels, The College Classroom: Some Observations on the Meanings of Student Participation (1976) 60 Sociology & Soc Res 421, at 425. The Socratic style, delivered by a male professor, may particularly inhibit women. I suggested above that one disadvantage of the Socratic method was that the response to students, given that it came from a professor rather than other students, was almost always artfully expressed. Belenky et al state, “when a male professor presents only the impeccable products of his thinking it is especially difficult for a woman student to believe that she can produce such a thought.” MF Belenky et al, Women’s Ways of Knowing (New York: Basic Books, 1986) at 217.
30 MJ Frug, Re-Reading Contracts: A Feminist Analysis of a Contracts Casebook (1985) 34 Am UL Rev 1065.
31 See for example, C Boyle, Book Review (1985) 63 Can B Rev 427.
32 I am grateful to Joe Sommer for pointing out to me a particular pattern of interaction in a course on feminism at Yale Law School. When the discussion was of feminist theory, a topic women are likely to both know more and care more about than men, women offered about 80% of contributions in the class leaving aside the turns of the male professor. When the discussion turned to more black-letter issues of constitutional analysis, men spoke at least half the time. Men formed 20% of the class.
33 See Treichler & Kramarae, supra note 25, at 119.
34 C Edelsky, Who’s Got the Floor (1981) 10 Language in Soc’y 383.
35 Id.
36 Id at 415.
37 Id at 416.
38 C Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard UP, 1983).
39 C Gilligan, Remapping Development: The Power of Divergent Data, in L Cirillo & S Wapner, eds, Value Presuppositions in Theories of Human Development (Hillsdale, New Jersey: L Erlbaum & Associates, 1986) at 40.
40 C MacKinnon, Feminist Discourse, Moral Values and the Law — A Conversation (1985) 34 Buffalo L Rev 11 [hereinafter cited as Conversation].
41 Interpreters may disagree about the extent to which Gilligan identifies the different voice as being gendered. She states in the Introduction to In a Different Voice, “... this association is not absolute, and the contrasts between male and female voices are presented here to highlight a distinction between two modes of thought and to focus a problem of interpretation rather than to represent a generalization about either sex.” Gilligan, supra note 38, at 2. In a later response to critics, summarizing her own and others’ work, she says,
boys and men who resemble those most studied by developmental psychologists and to define and resolve moral problems within the justice framework, although they introduce considerations of care; and the focus on care in moral reasoning although not characteristic of all women, is characteristically a female phenomenon in the advantaged populations that have been studied.
C Gilligan, On In a Different Voice: An Interdisciplinary Forum (1986) 11 Signs 304, at 330.
42 Conversation, supra note 40, at 73–74. Edelsky’s description quoted above referring to the need to find a cover of anonymity for an assertive voice, suggests very strongly a response to oppression.
43 [1872] USSC 16; (1872) 83 US 130, at 141. In the now infamous words of Justice Bradley, when excluding Myra Bradwell from admission to the legal profession, “... the civil law as well as nature herself, has always recognized a wide difference in the respective spheres and destinies of man and woman. Man is, or should be, woman’s protector and defender. The natural and proper timidity and delicacy which belongs to the female sex evidently unfits it for many of the occupations of civil life.”
44 Conversations, supra note 40, at 74.
45 I am grateful to Jamie Studley and Judith Miller for making these analogies explicit; see also Weiss & Melling, supra note 1, at 1339.
46 See N Gold, Climates for Learning, reproduced in Australasian Law Teaching Workshop, Materials (unpublished, 1989).
47 One version of this technique is described in Wildman, supra note 1. In this article she also describes a variety of other teaching techniques for breaking classroom silence.
48 At least most of the time — although I usually try to talk with each group while they are discussing the problem.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/1989/13.html