Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Legal Education Review |
IS PLAGIARISM INDICATIVE OF PROSPECTIVE LEGAL
PRACTICE?
LILLIAN CORBIN* AND JUSTIN
CARTER**
Plagiarism has become increasingly pervasive in Australian law
schools.1 Universities have implemented policies and
procedures at both the institutional and faculty level to combat the menace to
academic
integrity.2 Plagiarism is elusive, however, in
terms of both conceptualisation and detection. The greatest difficulty in
identifying instances
of plagiarism is the lack of clarity as to its definition.
At its most basic, plagiarism is defined as the theft of literary property
without attribution.3 While the authors contend that
offenders ought to be held strictly liable, some commentators, discussed below,
insist that an element
of intention must be present to make a finding of
plagiarism, or they identify negligence as an excuse for plagiarism.
To
plagiarise in law school is to demonstrate a lack of constant vigilance in
abiding by the ethical dictates of one’s professional
community. Such
disrespect for ethical standards is thus reflective of a lack of ethical
integrity or compliance to university rules.
In Re Humzy-Hancock the
Honourable Justice Philip McMurdo found that an applicant for admission as a
legal practitioner, who had been disciplined for
instances of academic
misconduct during his law degree, had not in fact plagiarised because he did not
deliberately, knowingly present
the work of another person as his own; instead
it was ‘poor work’, ‘carelessness’ and a
‘misunderstanding
of what was required’.4
While the authors recognise that the Court was simply obliged to apply the
definition of plagiarism prescribed by the Griffith Law
School to the facts of
the case, the matter, it is contended, prompts a reconsideration of the extent
to which the commission of
plagiarism reflects the ethical compass of law
students as prospective legal practitioners.
To that end, the authors
respectfully disagree with the decision in Re
Humzy-Hancock,5 which ultimately removed the
impediment to the applicant’s admission. The authors suggest that the
Supreme Court ought to have
exercised its inherent jurisdiction over the legal
profession to disallow admission (or at least delay admission). Chief Justice
de
Jersey of the Supreme Court had previously promoted a zero tolerance policy
towards academic misconduct.6 Had the Supreme Court
followed that policy in Re Humzy-Hancock,7
it would have made a clear statement that, whether due to a lack of ethical
integrity (intention) or unsatisfactory compliance (negligence),
such applicants
are unfit for legal practice.
I PLAGIARISM — A MATTER OF LEGAL ETHICS
While plagiarism is a universal concept, this paper,
having been prompted by a recent Supreme Court case that examined whether or
not
a law student had plagiarised, will particularly consider its significance in
relation to law students and legal practice. In
doing so, this paper will
consider whether a lack of intention on the part of the individual concerned
should result in a decision
that the student has merely been
‘sloppy’ as opposed to having plagiarised.
Plagiarism, in
general, is a matter of morals: a view that sees it as a form of misconduct or
poor behaviour.8 Notwithstanding actual practice in law
schools, there are compelling reasons to suggest that these institutions ought
to do all they
can to guard against plagiarism occurring. One reason is that the
reputation of these institutions can potentially be damaged if
students are
found guilty of plagiarism.9 Therefore law schools
would benefit from endeavouring to educate students about what it entails and
alerting students to its significance
by having students sign a statement that
certifies that the work they are submitting is their own, for example, thereby
adding dishonesty
to the student’s repertoire if plagiarism occurs.
Griffith Law School already adopts this
practice.10
While it is obviously important that
students acquire the legal knowledge required for admission as
solicitors,11 the law schools also see their role as
one of encouraging their students to develop the characteristics of integrity
and honesty
that go into producing the kind of legal practitioners that meet the
admission requirements. It is understood that part of the usual
process is for
law schools to report, via a notation on a student’s transcript, any
issues that are relevant to the requirement
that applicants need to be of good
character and considered fit to practice law. 12
The requirement that practitioners are to be persons of good character is
reflected in the Legal Profession Act 2004
(Qld),13 and this is taken very seriously by the
Admissions Board of the Supreme Court of Queensland. Chief Justice de Jersey, as
the chair
of this Board, has taken a strict line with applicants who have been
found to be plagiarists in recent years. In an oft-cited statement
from a case
in 2004 he said:
Legal practitioners must exhibit a degree of integrity which engenders in the Court and in clients unquestioning confidence in the completely honest discharge of their professional commitments. Cheating in the academic course which leads to the qualification central to practice and at a time so close to the application for admission must preclude our presently being satisfied of this applicant’s fitness.14
Thus the Court,
and Chief Justice de Jersey in particular, see plagiarism as conduct that
questions the applicant’s integrity.
In a speech in December
2004,15 His Honour again asserted his belief that
disclosure of these offences is vital in determining whether applicants are
worthy of admission
as practitioners in Queensland. His Honour stated that
practitioners are expected to act ethically and be professionally efficient
as
officers of the court. In other words, it is his view that the public has a
right to expect a high standard of behaviour from
legal practitioners. It is
suggested that the public’s confidence in the legal profession could be
undermined if the court
admits those who have plagiarised without some sort of
rebuke. In the context of the profession of social work, Saunders comments
that
professional bodies ought to require prospective entrants to have achieved
‘scrupulous adherence ... to ethical codes
of conduct’ which in turn
is evidenced in honesty.16
While Chief Justice de
Jersey has not outlined the specific consequences that might occur if people who
lack integrity are admitted
to the legal profession, the work of Parameswaran in
a recent article mentions some possibilities.17 By
referring to the work of numerous academics who have taken an empirical
approach, he argues that a vigilant approach to cheating
is the most influential
determinant and warns that a lenient approach to
cheating18 — one that allows students to simply
suggest that the offending behaviour was caused because they were stressed
— is
perceived by the student body as a devaluing of honesty and integrity
of those in authority.19 Parameswaran also posits that
students who successfully use other people’s work are more than likely
going to continue their
dishonesty when they enter the
workforce.20
In other words it is thought that
people who cheat in law school may have a propensity to engage in unsatisfactory
professional conduct
— defined usually as a breach of the ‘standard
of competence and diligence that a member of the public is entitled to
expect of
a reasonably competent Australian legal
practitioner’.21 Cheating in law school may also
amount to the more serious standard of ‘professional misconduct’
which involves conduct
that amounts to ‘a substantial or consistent
failure to reach or maintain a reasonable standard of competence and
diligence’.22 A failure to meet the latter
standard is considered to logically result when a person resorts to cheating in
their studies. They
will not have the requisite knowledge necessary to fulfil
their future role, thereby questioning their ability to be proficient
practitioners.23
II DEFINING PLAGIARISM
Plagiarism comes from the Latin word
‘plagiare’ meaning to trap or snare something and use it for your
own purposes.24 Initially this referred to the
kidnapping of a person to make them a slave.25 More
recently, this concept has been adopted in a literary sense, that is, thieving
the ideas and imaginings of others.26 While there are
many definitions, plagiarism is generally defined as the use of another’s
words, research or ideas without
attribution to the original author.
However, the matter is now more complex than this. As Hawley notes,
‘definitional precision constitutes one of the most salient
problems in
any discussion of acceptable versus unacceptable
documentation’.27 All universities now articulate
what they mean by plagiarism, many of which are open to an interpretation that
suggests that without
intent there is no plagiarism. This implies, then, that
careless work does not constitute plagiarism. Mawdsley has written extensively
on this topic and he divides the approaches taken as objective and subjective.
The objective approach entails simply proving plagiarism
by examining the paper
and the source, whereas the subjective inquiry entails determining whether
students have intended their actions.28
The latter
approach was taken in the recent Supreme Court case of Re
Humzy-Hancock.29 While there were numerous
occasions where the student did not correctly attribute the words to the correct
authors, it was found that
he did not mean to represent the work as his own.
This was a case that arose from an application for admission as a solicitor in
the State of Queensland, Australia, where the person’s transcript from
Griffith University, noted that he had been held guilty
of three instances of
academic misconduct. Justice Philip McMurdo correctly considered the
student’s application in accordance
with the law school’s own
definition of plagiarism: ‘Plagiarism is the knowing presentation of the
work or property of
another person as if it were the student’s
own’.30 Using this definition His Honour found
that in each of the three instances of academic misconduct, the student was
careless in failing
to attribute the words that he used to the
authors.31 An objective approach was adopted insofar as
the student was held to have used the words of others, which a reader would
believe
were his own words, but His Honour also adopted the subjective approach
in noting that the student had ‘no intention to pass
off the work of
another’ as his own.32
This can be compared
with the objective approach taken by the Appellate Division of the Superior
Court of New Jersey in the case of
Napolitano v Princeton University
Trustees.33 In that case, however, it seems
that there were two definitions of plagiarism operating, including an earlier
version that mentioned
an ‘absence of intent’ which was later
replaced with ‘deliberate’.34 In that case
the court preferred this objective approach, an approach that does not require
the institution to look further than
the documents presented by the
students.
III INTENTION AS AN ELEMENT OF PLAGIARISM
There appears to be a trend in higher education circles to try to educate students on the meaning of plagiarism.35 There is also the view that there needs to be a recognition that students live in a pressured environment. A statement made by Saltmarsh illustrates this view:
In this context, students-as-consumers in turn find themselves under growing pressure to compete and excel in their studies, often in addition to working to meet the not inconsiderable costs associated with higher education. In a climate which measures ‘success’ (rather than learning) according to quantifiable ‘results’, in which the process of learning is reconstituted as a financial transaction for which individuals are increasingly responsible and in which the urgency to complete and progress is mirrored in a competitive results-driven labour market, it is hardly surprising that plagiarism has come to be seen by some as a viable alternative to overload, poor performance or failure.36
To a certain
extent this approach could be perceived as ‘watering down’ the
seriousness of plagiarism. There are authors
who take a strict approach to
plagiarism believing that, although intent is an important factor in considering
plagiarism issues,
it is not an essential element that must be present
‘for the wrong to exist’.37 More
specifically, one author clearly states: ‘It is no defense for the
plagiarist to say “I forgot.” or “it is only a rough
draft.” or “I did not know it was
plagiarism”’.38 Another implicates the
institution involved by stating: ‘Instead of condemning all plagiary, a
school signals that some transgressions
are acceptable, and that sloppy or
careless work could be claimed as an “accident” that provides a
defense’.39
Two authors, writing in support of
this view, take a novel approach. Parameswaran reasons that a person allowing
something to happen
is just as bad as doing the act. He argues that if parents
fail to feed their children they will die and if a gardener fails to water
houseplants, they will wilt.40 He then reasons that
inaction caused these results and therefore concludes that a student’s
excuse that he did not do it, is
not a ‘valid defence for shirking moral
responsibility’.41
Papay-Carder extends this
line of thinking. She suggests that plagiarism is not the ‘use of
another’s words or ideas,
but in the passing them off as one’s
own’.42 Passing off occurs when there is no
accreditation given to the original source.43 She
reasons therefore that any reader assumes that the work produced is that of the
person writing it, regardless of whether or not
the writer intended this to
happen.44
While it is acknowledged that the court in
Re Humzy-Hancock45 were tied to the
definition inserted into the Griffith Law School’s academic misconduct
policy, it is still useful to note
that the arguments presented in this article
would not support a finding that accepted the student’s careless work
habits as
a defence to plagiarism. These arguments assert that the words
‘intent’ or ‘knowing’ ought to be deleted
from
definitions of plagiarism.46 This will have the effect
that ‘any student who is found to have used another’s literary
property without attribution
for academic credit is automatically guilty of
plagiarism’.47 This may sound harsh at first
blush, but it should be noted that this course of action does not eliminate a
consideration of ‘intent’
altogether. It simply reduces it to the
role of a mitigating factor in determining the penalty that should be
applied.48 This proposition is often expressed by
suggesting that ‘there are different degrees of plagiarism
...’.49
This approach would make explicit the
standard of behaviour that ultimately determines whether or not an applicant is
admitted as
a legal practitioner in Queensland. This approach very clearly
represents to students that they are entering a culture where integrity
is
valued.
However, is this really the case? Does the legal profession keep to
the same standards as those that would be demanded of students
in training to be
legal practitioners?
IV PLAGIARISM AND LEGAL PRACTICE
Despite the concerns of academics to protect
scholarship from plagiarism, many of the practices in the legal profession do
not conform
to a strict definition of it.50 In fact,
the practice is systemic; more than that, it is
inherent.51 Consider the use of forms and precedents in
the legal profession. In the interests of preventing the reinvention of the
wheel,52 solicitors have increasingly moved to a
knowledge management model. Pursuant to this model, firms have appointed
specialised lawyers
whose primary task it is to draft precedents and manage the
legal documents used by the firm.53 It is believed this
practice is becoming increasingly widespread in the legal profession, without
question as to any ethical dilemmas.
A similar absence of ethical inquiry
pertains to ghost-writing within the firm. Often junior lawyers research and
prepare draft legal
documents that are ultimately presented under their
supervising lawyers’ name.54 The justification
for such a practice is that these tasks are undertaken pursuant to their service
contract with the firm and, upon
production, intellectual property in the
document vests in the firm to dispense with as it
pleases.55 Such an argument, however, focuses on the
legal aspect of the scenario without sufficient regard to the ethical quandary
that attaches.
The ethical question appears to be this: beyond the legal
justifications for the practice of junior lawyers ghost writing for senior
partners, do lawyers feel an innate wrongness about this practice? The answer,
resoundingly, is no. Justice Philip McMurdo extols
the ethical neutrality of
such a position in Re Humzy-Hancock56 where he
states:
It is significant that this was an answer to a legal problem; it was not an essay. Had the applicant made the attribution ... I do not see that it would have affected the assessment of his answer. He was to be assessed for his ability to identify the relevant terms and to apply them to the facts of the hypothetical problem, which it seems that he did.57
Thus, answers to
legal problems require no attribution. The economic reality is that there is no
currency — that is, value —
in the legal documents composed by
lawyers. The business literature that has developed a dichotomy between goods
and services speaks
to this: what lawyers are selling is not a good, but a
service.58 The legal documents alone are worthless.
They are not marketable products. The achievement of some result, however, is
that lawyers
market their ability to deliver a particular
result.59 That is their product. The legal documents
produced in the process of achieving that goal are valueless, divorced from the
wider
project. In such circumstances, ‘[t]o impose ... a cost when there
is no appreciable benefit is inefficient and prevents productive
reuse of
information’.60
Yet the position of judges is
different. The defining feature of the common law — the doctrine of
stare decisis — has resulted in the characterisation of common law
judgments as one endless chain novel that is amended and added to by subsequent
authors.61 Judges are in error, however, if they fail
to cite the requisite authority for the propositions they make. That is, the
ultimate
authority of the second judgment collapses without the support of an
often lengthy chain of prior cases. It is thus necessary that
judges, having
left the ranks of academia for professional practice and subsequently being
appointed to the bench, are aware of what
conduct may amount to
plagiarism.
Recent allegations against a Federal Magistrate are instructive
on this point. It was reported that the Federal Magistrate had duplicated,
without permission or attribution, 2000 words from the judgment of a fellow
magistrate.62 Upon further investigation, another two
allegations of plagiarism were raised.63 Echoing the
necessity of citing valid authority in the common law tradition described above,
Mr. Rob Davis, then President of the
Queensland Law Society, commented that:
Our big concern is of course that wherever there is copying without attribution of sections of a judgment, then there must be a question as to whether or not appropriate judicial process has been entered into in arriving at the decision. And where there are sections of a judgment quoted without attribution, there must always be a question as to whether or not that appropriate judicial process has been undertaken.64
Further,
Davis remarked that the ‘critical issue’ in the case was that of
workload.65 As discussed above, Justice Philip McMurdo
in Re Humzy-Hancock66 also referred to
the pressures upon today’s law students.67
Further, Saltmarsh comments that the emergent consumerism of higher education
has resulted in the situation where ‘students-as-consumers’
are
under growing pressure to compete and excel in their studies, often in addition
to working to meet the not inconsiderable costs
associated with higher
education. This pressure turns ‘results’ (as opposed to
‘learning’) into a marketable
product, which students-as-consumers
can more easily acquire via plagiarism than more traditional
means.68
Such views seem to indicate a relaxing of
the applicable standards where one is faced with hardship or difficulty. This
approach is
concerning given that, taken to extremes, it can be seen to offer a
justification for what is at best, negligence and, at worst,
an ethical breach.
Despite the allegations of plagiarism the Federal Magistrate remained in that
role for a period of nine months
before resigning.69 In
other words, the Federal Magistrate continued to carry out the duties associated
with that role notwithstanding accusations that
the legal profession was
protecting one of its own.70 In this respect there were
implications that the system was treating law students applying for admission
more harshly than established
operators within the
profession.71
The different standard was made
explicit in the case of Re Lamberis72 in the
United States. In that case, an attorney was charged with plagiarising his
Masters thesis, and claimed that he made no ‘intentional
effort to deceive
his thesis examiners’.73 Whilst the court was not
swayed by his arguments and did make a finding of plagiarism, a somewhat lenient
penalty was applied. LeClercq
suggests that new entrants to the profession are
treated more harshly than practicing lawyers given the lighter
sentence.74 Yet contrary to such arguments that
different ethical standards are applied in these respects, the authors contend
that different
ethical communities exist. The ethical standards being applied
are in fact different, but they are being applied by different authorities:
a
community of scholars in the former case, and a community of legal professionals
in the latter.
Thus, as noted previously, there is no value in the legal
documents. For academics, publications are a measure of career
performance.75 An academic’s publication output
is deemed to be indicative of their scholarly stature. It is the primary means
by which an
academic presents to the employment market, insofar as a strong
research profile allows an academic to attract grants that ultimately
benefits
her host institution. To this end, as demonstrated previously, scholarly
communities zealously protect authorship. These
communities have thus developed
strong defences against such misconduct in the form of plagiarism policies and
an ethos that condemns
the practice.
The concern with law students committing
plagiarism is one of both ability and character. As Justice Philip McMurdo
remarked in Re Humzy-Hancock,76
‘This was simply poor work’.77 Yet
according to the Honourable Murray Gleeson in a speech he delivered while Chief
Justice of the Supreme Court of New South Wales
and cited in a report of the Law
Council of Australia — ‘Whilst, in practice, the great number of
applications are processed
by the Barristers Admissions Board or the Solicitors
Admissions Board, which certifies to the court fitness for admission, the Court
has the power to admit or decline to admit regardless of what the Boards
certify.’78 Therefore the court has an inherent
jurisdiction to ensure that only applicants who meet the rigorous professional
standards of the
Supreme Court of Queensland are admitted. Insofar as the
Supreme Court has this role as gatekeeper of the legal profession one must
question the wisdom of allowing the admission of an individual who has already
demonstrated a flagrant disregard for such standards
of professionalism. This is
especially so given the saturation of the market,79 and
the fact that there has been a steady increase in disciplinary hearings in
recent years.80
Referencing effectively is a
meticulous task. It requires a pedantic attention to detail. The Australian
standard, the Australian Guide to Legal Citation (the
Guide),81 extorts an extensive framework for the
authoritative citation of materials used in one’s work. The Guide,
however, pales in
comparison to the Bluebook used by American law
schools.82 One might suggest that ‘near enough is
good enough’, though the authors would contend otherwise. It might seem
unnecessarily
strict to enforce referencing to this extreme, but law students
are in training for immersion in a world that prides itself on rules
and strict
adherence to those rules. The legal universe is one of compliance. Failure to
appropriately formulate pleadings, or lodge
forms within limitation periods, or
meet formal requirements in the preparation of documents are all pitfalls of
practice. One who
falls afoul of these requirements wastes both time and money
for the courts and the client.83 Such behaviour is not
tolerated by practitioners and the propensity for such conduct should not be
overlooked during the admissions
process.
Beyond this, one must query the
character of such an individual. Chief Justice de Jersey is cited above —
and it warrants repeating
— stating that ‘Legal practitioners must
exhibit a degree of integrity which engenders in the Court and in clients
unquestioning
confidence in the completely honest discharge of their
professional commitments’.84 The ethical dilemma
inherent in not properly attributing the work of another is that it constitutes
a flagrant disregard of the ethical
norms held by the community in which one is
practicing.85 Thus, though lawyers might not value
authorship in this sense in the course of practice, whilst at law school the
academic community
places high priority on defending scholarly integrity. By
acting contrary to this norm — whether due to intentional disregard
or
mere negligence — the individual in question has demonstrated a lack of
commitment to those norms.
The field of legal ethics is a difficult one. As
Canadian scholar Hutchinson has suggested, lawyers face countless discretions in
daily practice.86 Unrelentingly, legal practitioners
are called upon to deliver their services in a manner congruent with the ethical
dictates of the
profession. There are numerous areas where the rules of
professional responsibility fall short of providing a definitive course of
action.87 The major difficulty with plagiarism is that
it is largely unenforceable: when it occurs, the only person aware of its
occurrence
is the perpetrator. Lawyers of good character are indispensable to
practice in the vacuum that exists between legal and ethical obligations.
To
that end, we respectfully suggest that the Supreme Court should resume its zero
tolerance policy regarding plagiarism and academic
misconduct.
A legalistic
reading of the case of Re
Humzy-Hancock88 would challenge this
conclusion. Adopting such an approach, one would contend that on the basis that
plagiarism was not in fact found
to exist, the Court did not detract from its
zero tolerance policy since it was merely interpreting the definition set out in
the
Griffith Law School’s assessment policy. It is respectfully suggested,
however, that such an approach misses the broader point
in terms of legal
ethics. As a matter of the formal requirements of plagiarism as formulated in
the university policy, plagiarism
did not exist. The conduct alleged and
ultimately found to have occurred nonetheless amounts to conduct that ought to
be unacceptable
to the Supreme Court on the basis discussed above insofar as the
conduct in question demonstrated a disregard for the legal and ethical
norms of
the academic community. These are not characteristics becoming of a prospective
legal practitioner.
V CONCLUSION
Band and Schruers state that ‘[n]orms serve as society’s means to fill in the gray area between what it wants people to do and what law can tell people to do.89 Norms develop because groups have incentives to regulate themselves beyond the extent of the law’.90 The university policies that seek to subvert academic misconduct provide a black letter formulation of plagiarism. It forms part of the code of conduct that students are expected to adhere to in the pursuit of their studies. In a similar vein, the ethical guidelines promulgated by the professional bodies in the legal profession serve to shape practitioner behaviours. Both regimes recognise, however, that between regulation and enforcement, conduct occurs in the shadows of ethical discretion. Within each ethical community there are instances where individuals are prompted to make decisions beyond the watchful gaze of an authority figure. It is in these instances that we are comforted by the fact that the individuals we engage as both law students and legal practitioners are persons of integrity. In this way, law schools act as a crucible for the retention of people of strong character that have demonstrated, among other things, a commitment to a community ethos. Failure to live up to expectations at university thus raises serious questions as to a person’s capacity for the similar dedication demanded of legal professionals.
* Dr., Senior Lecturer and Undergraduate Program Convenor, Griffith Law School, Griffith University, Queensland..
** LLB (Hons) BIntBus. The authors would like to thank the anonymous referees for their very valuable comments, as well as Professor Jeff Giddings for his constructive feedback.
1 As to universities generally, see eg, Shelley Yeo, ‘First-Year University Science and Engineering Students’ Understanding of Plagiarism’, (2007) 26 Higher Education Research & Development 199, 201. In relation to law schools in particular, see the comments of de Jersey CJ in Re AJG [2004] QCA 88 (Unreported, de Jersey CJ, Jerrard JA, and Philippides J, 15 March 2004).
2 See eg, the policies adopted at Griffith University: Griffith University, Policy on Academic Misconduct (2007) <http://www62.gu.edu.au/policylibrary.nsf/alldocscat/352f26aa1a1011e64a256bbb0062fd5f?opendocument> at 8 December 2007; Griffith Law School, Law School Assessment Policy (2007) [4.0] <http://www.griffith.edu.au/school/law/assets/assessment_policy_mar07.pdf> at 8 December 2007. It is interesting to note that these policies have both been altered as a direct consequence of the instant case under consideration.
3 Debbie Papay-Carder, ‘Comments: Plagiarism in Legal Scholarship’ (1983) 15 University of Toledo Law Review 233, 234.
4 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
5 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
6 Re AJG [2004] QCA 88 (Unreported, de Jersey CJ, Jerrard JA, and Philippides J, 15 March 2004).
7 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
8 William Harris, Plagiarism in Academe (2007) <http://community.middlebury.edu/~harris/plagiarism.html> at 8 December 2007.
9 Robert A. Lupton and Kenneth J. Chapman, ‘Russian and American College Students’ Attitudes, Perceptions and Tendencies towards Cheating’ (2002) 44 Educational Research 17.
10 See eg, Griffith University: Griffith University, Assignment Cover Sheet (2007) <http://www.griffith.edu.au/ins/assignments/forms/fa-003.pdf> at 8 December 2007.
11 Supreme Court (Admission) Rules 2004 (Qld) r 6.
12 It should be noted, however, that a notation about plagiarism is only made on the student’s transcript when students are removed from their program of study for a period.
13 Legal Profession Act 2004 (Qld) s 13(1)(a). The same requirement is reproduced in the current Act: Leal Profession Act 2007 (Qld) s 9(1)(a).
14 Re AJG [2004] QCA 88 (Unreported, de Jersey CJ, Jerrard JA, and Philippides J, 15 March 2004) [4].
15 Chief Justice Paul de Jersey, ‘Queensland Law Society Christmas Breakfast’ (Speech delivered at the Brisbane Club, Brisbane, 8 December 2004) <http://www.courts.qld.gov.au/publications/articles/speeches/2004/dj081204.pdf> at 8 December 2007.
16 Peter J. Larkham and Susan Manns, ‘Plagiarism and Its Treatment in Higher Education’ (2002) 26 Journal of Further and Higher Education 339, 341.
17 Ashvin Parameswaran, ‘Student Dishonesty and Faculty Responsibility’ (2007) 12 Teaching in Higher Education 263, 267–68.
18 Ibid 267.
19 Ibid 268.
20 Ibid 267–68.
21 Legal Profession Act 2004 (Qld) ss 244. See also Legal Profession Act 2007 (Qld) ss 418.
22 Legal Profession Act 2004 (Qld) ss 245(1)(a). See also Legal Profession Act 2007 (Qld) ss 419.
23 Parameswaran, above n 17, 268.
24 Harris, above n 8. See also Henry Goudy, ‘Plagiarism – A Fine Art’ (1909) 20 Juridical Review 302.
25 Robert D. Bills, ‘Plagiarism in Law School: Close Resemblance of the Worse Kind?’ (1990) 31 Santa Clara Law Review 103.
26 Papay-Carder, above n 3, 234: suggesting a Roman poet named Martial was the first to use the word in the literary sense of ‘literary kidnapping, or the theft and enslaving as one’s own the free ideas of another or his servants of the imagination’.
27 Larkham and Manns, above n 16, 340.
28 Ralph Mawdsley, ‘Plagiarism Problems in Higher Education’ (1986) 13 Journal of College and University Law 65, 67–68.
29 Re Humzy-Hancock [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
30 Griffith Law School, above n 2, [4.1.5].
31 Re Humzy-Hancock [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007) [42].
32 Ibid.
33 453 A 2d 263 (NJ, 1982). This case has featured in a number of articles on plagiarism, but was analysed in depth by Mawdsley, cited in Bills, above n 24, 113. Mawdsley’s arguments are more succinctly made in Mawdsley, above n 27, 67–68.
34 Bills, ibid. Although as note 77 of Bills’ article reports, note 6 of Mawdsley’s article states that the University, after this case, removed the word ‘deliberate’ from its plagiarism definition.
35 Australian Universities Teaching Committee, Minimising Plagiarism (2003) <http://www.cshe.unimelb.edu.au/assessinglearning/03/plagMain.html> at 27 January 2007.
36 Sue Saltmarsh, ‘Graduating Tactics: Theorizing Plagiarism as Consumptive Practice’ (2004) 28 Journal of Further and Higher Education 445, 448.
37 Bills, above n 24. See also Hawley, cited in Larkham and Manns, above n 16: ‘views plagiarism as being a continuum ranging from sloppy paraphrasing to verbatim transcription with no crediting of sources’. See also Steve Buttry, When Does Sloppy Attribution Become Plagiarism? (2006) <http://www.americanpressinstitute.org/pages/resources/2006/09/when_does_sloppy_attribution_b> at 8 December 2007. Rawson reports that the American Historical Association ‘considers plagiarism to be the failure to properly acknowledge the work of another, regardless of intent’: Michael Rawson, Plagiarism: Curricular Materials for History Instructors (2005) <http://www.historians.org/governance/pd/Curriculum/Curriculum_Plagiarism.pdf> at 8 December 2007; Joe Mirarchi, ‘Plagiarism: What is It? How to Avoid It? And Why?’ (2001) 4 Thomas M. Cooley Journal of Practical and Clinical Law 381, 383: states that the element of ‘intent to plagiarize is irrelevant’. See also Ronald B. Standler, Plagiarism in Colleges in USA (2000) <http://www.rbs2.com/plag.htm> at 8 December 2007.
38 Ibid.
39 Bills, above n 24, 114.
40 Parameswaran, above n 17, 265.
41 Ibid.
42 Papay-Carder, above n 3, 234.
43 Ibid 235.
44 Ibid 236.
45 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
46 Bills, above n 24, 114.
47 Terri LeClercq, ‘Failure to Teach: Due Process and Law School Plagiarism’ (1999) 49 Journal of Legal Education 236, 245.
48 Bills, above n 24, 111–15.
49 Larkham and Manns, above n 16, 346.
50 See eg, Jeanne L. Schroeder, ‘Copy Cats: Plagiarism and Precedent’ (Working Paper No 185, Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University, 2007).
51 Cf, however, the position in the United States. There the latest edition of the Bluebook referencing system incorporates the ‘Bluepages’, which were developed to provide ‘easy-to-comprehend instruction’ in the intricacies of legal referencing for legal professionals: see, eg, The Bluebook: A Uniform System of Citation (2007) <http://www.legalbluebook.com/index.shtml> at 8 December 2007.
52 On the functional nature of legal documents, see Jonathan Band and Matt Schruers, ‘Dastar, Attribution, and Plagiarism’ (2005) 33 American Intellectual Property Law Association Quarterly Journal 1, 14.
53 See, eg, ‘The Management of Legal Knowledge’, Lawyers Weekly (Australia), 15 September 2006 <http://www.lawyersweekly.com.au/articles/30/0C044E30.asp?Type=53 & Category=853> at 8 December 2007, and Papay-Carder, above n 3, 245, referring to the American context.
54 Band and Schruers, above n 51, 21.
55 Lisa G. Lerman, ‘Misattribution in Legal Scholarship: Plagiarism, Ghostwriting, and Authorship’ (2001) 42 South Texas Law Review 467, 470.
56 Re Humzy-Hancock [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
57 Ibid [36].
58 As to the goods/service dichotomy, see generally James A. Fitzsimmons, Service Management: Operations, Strategy, and Information Technology (5th ed, 2006).
59 See, eg, Connie Irwin, ‘Twentieth Century Law Firm Marketing versus 21st Century Market: The Essential Differences’ (2003) 22 Of Counsel 15; Connie Irwin ‘A Simple Plan to Improve Your Firm’s Marketing Results’ (2007) 7 Law Office Management and Administration Report 1, which highlights the marketability of the service-dimension of legal practice.
60 Band and Schruers, above n 51, 11.
61 See Ronald Dworkin, ‘Law as Interpretation’ (1982) 9 Critical Inquiry 179; Stanley Fish, ‘Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretation in the Law and in Literary Criticism’ (1982) 9 Critical Inquiry 201.
62 ABC Radio, ‘Magistrates and Plagiarism’, The Law Report, 9 May 2006 (2006) <http://www.abc.net.au/rn/lawreport/stories/2006/1633885.htm> at 8 December 2007.
63 Ibid.
64 Ibid.
65 Ibid.
66 Re Humzy-Hancock [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
67 Ibid [38].
68 See, generally, Saltmarsh, above n 35.
69 ‘Magistrate Accused of Plagiarism Quits’, The Australian (Sydney), 19 December 2006 <http://www.theaustralian.news.com.au/story/0,20867,20950913-1702,00.html> at 8 December 2007.
70 See eg, ‘Magistrate Has a Case to Answer’, Courier-Mail (Brisbane), 23 March 2006, 28; ‘Care Must be Taken with Precedents’, Courier-Mail (Brisbane), 20 March 2006, 18. In the United States context, see Papay-Carder, above n 3, and Le Clercq, above n 46, 250.
71 Des Houghton, ‘Double standards – Plagiarism has very different consequences for two Queensland women’, The Courier-Mail (Brisbane), 27 May 2006.
72 433 NE 2d 549 (Ill, 1982).
73 Re Lamberis, 433 NE 2d 549 (Ill, 1982) 500.
74 See LeClercq, above n 46, 250. See also Gino Dal Pont, Lawyers’ Professional Responsibility (3rd ed, 2006) [2.95]–[2.105].
75 Band and Schruers, above n 51, 13.
76 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007Ibid [38].
77 Ibid.
78 Law Council of Australia, Policy Statement on Reservation of Legal Work for Lawyers: Explanatory Memorandum (1998) <www.lawcouncil.asn.au/get/policies/1957352961/2.pdf> at 8 December 2007.
79 The statistics available from Graduate Careers Australia indicate that the percentage of law graduates not in full-time employment upon graduation has increased slightly in recent years and, further, that the number of law graduates pursuing careers outside private practice have increased: Graduate Careers Australia, GradsOnline (2007) <http://www.gradsonline.com.au/gradsonline/> at 8 December 2007.
80 See, generally, Linda Haller, ‘“Solicitors” Disciplinary Hearings in Queensland 1930–2000: A Statistical Analysis’ [2001] BondLawRw 1; (2001) 13 Bond Law Review 1.
81 Melbourne University Law Review Association, Australian Guide to Legal Citation (2nd ed, 2002).
82 Harvard Law Review Association, The Bluebook: A Uniform System of Citation (18th ed, 2005).
83 In addition to wastage, both the solicitor at fault and her client can be subject to an adverse costs order where the solicitor’s errors cause undue costs to be incurred: see, generally, Gino Dal Pont, Law of Costs (2003).
84 Above n 6, [4].
85 Band and Schruers, above n 51, 13–15.
86 Allan C. Hutchinson, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility (1999).
87 The difficulties surrounding the application of principles stated in codes have been mentioned by Australian text writers such as Ysaiah Ross, Ethics in Law: Lawyers’ Responsibility and Accountability in Australia (3rd ed, 2001) 198; Julian Disney, Lawyers (2nd ed, 1986) 598.
88 [2007] QSC 34 (Unreported, McMurdo J, 26 February 2007).
89 Band and Schruers, above n 51, 12.
90 Ibid.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/LegEdRev/2007/10.html