AustLII Home | Databases | WorldLII | Search | Feedback

Melbourne University Law Review

Melbourne Law School
You are here:  AustLII >> Databases >> Melbourne University Law Review >> 2011 >> [2011] MelbULawRw 1

Database Search | Name Search | Recent Articles | Noteup | LawCite | Author Info | Download | Help

Aronson, Mark --- "Misfeasance in Public Office: A Very Peculiar Tort" [2011] MelbULawRw 1; (2011) 35(1) Melbourne University Law Review 1


MISFEASANCE IN PUBLIC OFFICE:
A VERY PECULIAR TORT

MARK ARONSON[*]

[Misfeasance in public office is the common law’s only public law tort, because only public officials can commit it, and they must have acted unlawfully in the sense that they exceeded or misused a public power or position. This article examines who might be treated as a public official for these purposes, and whether the tort might extend to government contractors performing public functions. The article also discusses the tort’s expansion beyond the familiar administrative law context of abuse of public power, to abuse or misuse of public position. Misfeasance tortfeasors must at the very least have been recklessly indifferent as to whether they were exceeding or abusing their public power or position and thereby risking harm. That parallels the mens rea ingredient of the common law’s criminal offence of misconduct in public office, and reflects a further reason for restricting the tort’s coverage to public officials, who must always put their self-interest aside and act in the public interest. Upon proof of the tort’s fault elements, there beckons a damages vista apparently unconstrained by negligence law’s familiar limitations upon claims for purely economic loss. This article questions the capacity of the ‘recklessness’ requirement to constrain claims for indeterminate sums from an indeterminate number of claimants, some of whom may have been only secondary (or even more remote) victims of the public official’s misconduct. Finally, it questions (and finds wanting) the assumption common in Australia that government will not usually be vicariously liable for this tort. It argues that the personal wealth (or otherwise) of a public official should not set the boundary for a truly public tort. The article undertakes a comparative analysis of the law in Australia, New Zealand, England and Canada.]

I INTRODUCTION

Misfeasance in public office is a very peculiar tort. It is generally regarded as the common law’s only truly public tort,[1] because the only people who can commit it are those holding public office,[2] and the only occasions on which it can be committed are those in which public office-holders misuse their public power.[3] Because government’s tort liability is usually judged by private law principles, there is no generalised common law right of action for damages for loss caused by invalid administrative action.[4] That is an absence that some have lamented,[5] although most have recognised that government liability for invalidity per se would be financially crippling (particularly in light of the rapid expansion of the grounds of invalidity for judicial review), as well as being counterproductive to good administration.

Law reformers have long sought to articulate factors additional to invalidity which might form a coherent and justifiable basis for a new right of action.[6] However, their calls for legislative reform along those lines have failed; indeed the political mood seems to be heading in the opposite direction.[7] Human rights legislation has created a new species of government liability for damages, but these are discretionary, and are assessed according to principles that are usually less generous than tort’s aim of replacing the entirety of a loss with a monetary award.[8] Common law developments have been mixed. At least in Australia and England, government liability for negligence seems to be in retreat, although the pace of retreat differs between the two countries, and their courts now have different approaches to the resolution of novel negligence claims.

The misfeasance tort, however, has risen to some prominence in the last 20 or so years. A sequence of four leading cases has sketched its most basic outline. Speaking very generally, misfeasance now offers damages on a tort scale for loss inflicted by public officials guilty of ‘conscious maladministration’,[9] a concept which catches abuses of power by public officers who either knew they were breaking the law or recklessly decided not to care that this might be so. The judges in each of the four cases nodded to the tort’s lengthy antecedents, but they did not proceed as legal historians disinterring an ancient and well-settled doctrine. Nor did they see themselves as law reformers, imposing new duties of care or new standards of administration on government officers. Their implicit premise was the need for a tort that catches some of the things that individuals outside of public office simply cannot do — government officials regulate, license and coerce in ways that often have no private sector analogue nor any court-based remedy aside from judicial review. Explicitly, however, the cases insisted that they were not about to create a whole new compensation right for government incompetence or inertia (which are popularly regarded as the bureaucracy’s chief pathologies). They have instead sharpened their focus on those hopefully exceptional cases where officials deliberately take the law into their own hands.

The four leading cases have worked mostly in unison across national boundaries, starting in Australia, and from there to New Zealand, England and Canada in that order. Their sketch of misfeasance was only ever intended as preliminary; its edges are blurred, there are several gaps, and a lot of the detail remains to be filled in. It is therefore an appropriate time to take stock, to speculate on the loose ends so far, and to point to some of the hard choices that must now be made.

There are, of course, more than four leading cases, but this article will start (in Part II) with the quartet of cases that laid the tort’s modern foundations, before backtracking to some early history (Part III). It will then investigate the tort’s mental elements, starting first with the general place of malice in tort and public law (Part IV), followed by a discussion of the criminal offence of misfeasance (Part V), and the misfeasance tort’s recent and potential borrowing from its criminal namesake (Part VI). In a sense, the discussion to that point will have reflected the principal preoccupations of the four modern leading cases, but the article will then turn to other issues. The cases have been at pains to tell us what the tort is not — it is neither an action for breach of duty (Part VII), nor a subset of negligence (Part VIII). Nor is it limited to the provision of compensation for government violation of common law or statutory rights, or at least, not ‘rights’ in any narrow and legalistic sense (Part IX). It is a tort defined in large part by the state of mind of officials who either knew they were law-breakers or decided not to care about their legal constraints. In the latter case, the decision must have been ‘reckless’, which is a requirement with considerable potential that is yet to be explored (Part X). Although the cases all treat misfeasance as a purely public law tort, they have yet to define how closely, if at all, it must track the law of judicial review. The remedy is clearly a supplement of sorts to judicial review, but is it confined to powers or duties supervised by judicial review, or can it extend further to deliberate abuse of government’s private law powers such as its commercial powers (Part XI)? Must its defendants hold public office, or can they be government contractors exercising public functions (Part XII)?[10] And if misfeasance is indeed a public tort, why do the Australian cases doubt the ability to hold government vicariously liable for the misfeasance of its individual officers (Part XIII)?

II THE MODERN QUARTET OF LEADING CASES

The facts of the four leading cases need only a brief introduction here. Government stock inspectors in Northern Territory v Mengel (‘Mengel’)[11] had told the heavily indebted Mengels not to take their cattle to market and the law-abiding Mengels had complied. The inspectors suspected (wrongly, as it transpired) that the herd had fallen prey to a particularly virulent stock disease. Both the inspectors and the Mengels had thought that the inspectors were acting validly under a statutory scheme, which empowered them to intervene and impose restrictions on the movement of cattle in the event of a mere ‘suspicion’ of disease. That scheme, however, had applied only to agreements existing between government and stock owners, and the Mengels’ agreement had expired some time ago. There was a statutory power in default of agreement, but it was never used and in any event, it applied only where inspectors ‘believed’ the stock to be infected, and their suspicions in this instance had not risen to the level of a positive belief. The inspectors had acted beyond their powers, but in good faith, and this was held to be sufficient to exclude liability in misfeasance.

Garrett v Attorney-General (NZ) (‘Garrett’)[12] was the next leading case of the quartet, this time from the New Zealand Court of Appeal. A police constable had raped the plaintiff, and the constable’s sergeant had covered it up until the evidence had gone cold. The sergeant’s excuse was that the plaintiff had initially asked that the matter be dealt with unofficially, wanting only for her rapist to be relocated to any place that would be far away from her. The jury appears to have believed the sergeant, which might have raised an interesting question as to whether it is misfeasance to knowingly break the law at the plaintiff’s request or in the mistaken belief that it was for the plaintiff’s benefit. However, the Court ruled out misfeasance for a different (and one would have thought less compelling) reason, namely, that there was no evidence that the sergeant either knew or actually suspected the reputational loss or psychiatric harm that the plaintiff would suffer from a cover-up. Given that the rape occurred in a small town where the plaintiff resided, the plaintiff’s reputation was ruined for want of official acceptance of her story against the constable’s denials.

The third case in the quartet was the decision of the House of Lords in Three Rivers District Council v Bank of England [No 3] (‘Three Rivers’).[13] Building on Mengel and Garrett, their Lordships said that misfeasance required either deliberate harm or knowingly illegal conduct in circumstances where the official had suspected that the plaintiff would suffer harm and consciously chose to run that risk.[14] The main concern in Three Rivers was to confine reasonable foreseeability or objective fault to negligence actions, and to insist that at the very least, misfeasance required that its defendants knew they were running the risk that their actions were illegal and harmful but recklessly went ahead anyway. Three Rivers was a class action against the Bank of England for not pulling the plug earlier on a dodgy bank that took a long time to fail, and like a lot of misfeasance claims, House of Lords guidance came not after a trial but on an application to strike out the pleadings.

The fourth member of the quartet also involved an allegation that the police had deliberately (and in breach of police regulations) destroyed any chance of a proper investigation. The subject matter was a police killing of a bank robber whose family sought misfeasance damages for their distress at the lack of a proper investigation. The Supreme Court of Canada decided in Odhavji v Woodhouse (‘Odhavji’)[15] to allow the misfeasance claim to go to trial, endorsing the requirement of Three Rivers that at the very least, the relevant police must have chosen not to care that they were risking the infliction of mental harm on the family members.[16] Odhavji’s principal concerns were to insist that misfeasance applied as much to omissions as to acts, and as much to acts or omissions beyond power as to acts or omissions that were illegal for having abused power.[17]

III OFFICIALS BEHAVING OUTRAGEOUSLY: AN INTRODUCTION

Holt CJ’s judgment in Ashby v White (‘Ashby’)[18] is usually said to have created the earliest version of the tort of misfeasance in public office.[19] Four borough constables were ordered to pay £200 to a poor cobbler (Mr Ashby) because they had fraudulently and maliciously prevented him from casting his vote at a parliamentary election. By doing so, they had acted in breach of electoral duties that the sheriff’s writ had imposed upon them for election day.[20] The elements of moral outrage and punishment were very clear in Holt CJ’s judgment:

If public officers will infringe men’s rights, they ought to pay greater damages than other men, to deter and hinder other officers from the like offences. … To allow this action will make public officers more careful to observe the constitution of cities and boroughs, and not to be so partial as they commonly are in all elections, which is indeed a great and growing mischief, and tends to the prejudice of the peace of the nation.[21]

The principal difficulty for the Chief Justice was the lack of precedent for Mr Ashby’s ‘right to vote’, so he created it; Holt CJ had to fall back on ‘the reason of the law’ for want of ‘particular instances and precedents’.[22] Ashby is striking to modern readers for having retained so little of its doctrine but so much of its sense of a need for some sort of tort remedy for outrageous behaviour on the part of public officials.

Ashby’s connection with antecedent rights has gone. If the quoted passage from Holt CJ’s judgment meant that lesser damages would have been ordered against a private individual who had hindered Mr Ashby’s right to vote, then the action would have lain against both public and private defendants alike. Misfeasance nowadays no longer lies against private individuals, and the common law is now more tolerant of malice and selfishness in a private individual. Misfeasance no longer follows from a simple breach of duty, nor from a simple breach of public or statutory duties.[23] The House of Lords in Watkins v Secretary of State for the Home Department (‘Watkins’)[24] disowned Ashby’s award of punitive damages in the absence of material loss, with the result that moral outrage per se warranted neither punishment nor condemnation via the misfeasance tort.[25] Even in Watkins, however, Lord Bingham admitted the validity of the same policy drivers that had underpinned Holt CJ’s judgment in Ashby:

There is great force in the respondent’s submission that if a public officer knowingly and deliberately acts in breach of his lawful duty he should be amenable to civil action at the suit of anyone who suffers at his hands. There is an obvious public interest in bringing public servants guilty of outrageous conduct to book. Those who act in such a way should not be free to do so with impunity.[26]

What has emerged since Ashby is a set of countervailing policy concerns, calling for the courts to set a ‘balance’. The balance in Sanders v Snell[27] was between providing compensation for abuse of public power, and avoiding a liability rule that ‘may deter officials from exercising powers conferred on them when their exercise would be for the public good.’[28] Watkins added a more general consideration said to apply to all torts, namely, that the ‘primary role’ of tort is compensation, not punishment.[29] The tort’s characterisation as a fault-free action for breach of duty was dropped for obvious reasons of economy — it would have been far too expensive in an age of statutes, let alone an administrative state. The tort’s fault elements have been set at deliberate wrongdoing rather than objective (even spectacular) incompetence,[30] partly to avoid making public servants overly cautious about the legality of their actions,[31] but also (in Australia) out of a misplaced sense that individual officers would ‘ordinarily’ obtain no indemnity from their employers.[32]

If these were the only issues in play, the misfeasance action would still apply to both private and public defendants alike, as Holt CJ appeared to contemplate in Ashby itself.[33] Its retraction to the public sphere therefore needs further explanation. For more than a century now, the common law grounds of judicial review of administrative action have been driven by a sense that public officials must act altruistically. It is said that private individuals can act from selfishness, greed, revenge, spite, malice, prejudice and other base motives, and even for no reason at all, but that public officials are different.[34] One might cavil with that proposition at several points, the most obvious being that trustees must also put selfishness to one side. That this has some relevance to misfeasance appears clearly from Paul Finn’s ‘epigrammatic statement of the essence of the fiduciary obligation’,[35] namely, ‘[a] fiduciary must act honestly in what he alone considers to be the interests of his beneficiaries.’[36]

Lord Millett said much the same thing about misfeasance in Three Rivers, explicitly analogising to the law relating to a trustee’s obligations.[37] The dual requirements of honesty and altruism were perhaps more prominent in the days before misfeasance expanded beyond deliberately inflicted harm for an improper purpose.[38]

The obvious questions are why misfeasance does not apply to trustees, and why some of equity’s more demanding obligations placed upon trustees do not apply equally to public officials. In other words, why does the law provide two sets of rules for those who must act altruistically, depending on whether they (or, perhaps, their functions) belong to the public or private sector? No judgment has ever addressed that issue directly, although some do insist that misfeasance should not swamp the private sector’s torts[39] and that the development of private law’s economic torts should not swamp the misfeasance tort.[40] Brennan J said that if the existing dividing lines were not maintained, the law would ‘speak with a forked tongue’, sending out conflicting messages depending only on the pleader’s ability to select the most favourable tort.[41] These are largely concerns for doctrinal coherence,[42] and none of them have addressed the areas where legally mandated altruism crosses the divide between public and private. It is suggested that if the issue were to arise, the answers would necessarily be pragmatic. Generally speaking, there is no shortage of common law rules applying to those from either sector who must subordinate their own interests, and no obvious reason for supposing that doctrinal coherence across the sectors would produce a better result.[43] A further complication for any coherence project would arise from the fact that in Australia, at least, many public officials and their institutions have some measure of statutory protection from damages claims so long as they act in good faith.[44] Finally, trustees owe their duties to a defined class of beneficiaries, whilst public officials serve the public interest more generally.

IV MALICE IN TORT AND PUBLIC LAW

The role of malice in tort law varies between different torts, and also according to whether the defendant is public or private. That was not always the case. Holt CJ forgot to mention fraud or malice in his first report of Ashby, although they were clearly implied.[45] He inserted them in to a revised report in time for consideration by the House of Lords on appeal.[46] The role of malice in tort law kept changing over the ensuing centuries. For example, we learnt around two centuries later, and in a nod to the free market’s need for competitive selfishness,[47] that in actions against private sector defendants, and aside from conspiracy,[48] malice does not make otherwise lawful competitive behaviour tortious, just as good faith does not exonerate conduct which would otherwise be tortious.[49]

The position has long been different for defendants who are public officials of some kind. Well before the common law had rejected the contention that malice in a private defendant could make conduct that was otherwise lawful in a free market tortious, the tort liability of any public official exercising a discretionary function[50] (other than a superior court judge) had become conditional on establishing fraud or malice.[51] Inferior court judges enjoyed that protection plus one more, namely, that they must also have acted wholly outside their ‘jurisdiction’, taking that term in a very narrow sense.[52] In other words, by the early 1900s, a gap in tort law had already opened up between public and private defendants. Malice was not a good plea against a superior court judge, and it would count against inferior court judges only in combination with a plea of want or excess of jurisdiction. Aside from the judiciary, however, the presence of malice would remove any lingering common law protection for all other public officials exercising discretionary powers and was irrelevant to the liability of a private individual’s market-oriented conduct.

The gap between public and private defendants widened over the course of the 20th century. It would appear that the common law had in that period extended to inferior court judges the complete immunity previously enjoyed only by superior court judges,[53] but it had also retracted immunity altogether from anyone else exercising a discretionary function.[54] One cannot be absolutely sure of this,[55] however, because statutory protections have replaced the common law in most places. The legislative trend has been to grant absolute immunity to all judicial officers, high or low,[56] and to grant many others in public life an immunity conditional on their acting in good faith.[57] Good faith protection clauses abound in Australia’s regulatory statutes, and were once common in Britain. Lord Steyn spoke of Ashby as the misfeasance tort’s ‘first solid basis’,[58] but also acknowledged the contributions of old cases concerning liability for discretionary and judicial acts to the current mix.[59] As his Lordship noted, the net result is that misfeasance in public office now stands as an exception to the usual position that the presence of malice will not make a non-tortious act tortious, just as its absence will not excuse an otherwise tortious act.[60]

The reasons for distinguishing between private and public malice are not hard to find. Lord Hoffmann once wrote of private sector defendants that ‘there is little which can be said in defence of a right to cause loss out of sheer malice.’[61] He wondered aloud whether England might adopt something approximating America’s prima facie tort theory for harm caused deliberately or maliciously,[62] a theory similar to the civilian doctrine of abuse of rights.[63] Forty years later, his Lordship entertained no doubts in rejecting the American option so far as it might apply to private sector companies and individuals,[64] saying that in the cut-throat world of competitive markets, it would produce too many uncertainties for too little gain.[65]

Malice and an intention to harm are very different. The very essence of competitive behaviour in the marketplace is to gain an advantage at the expense of one’s rivals, but the public official is not conceived as a free agent in a free market. Public officials are supposed always to be constrained to act in the public interest or, at least, not in their own personal interest. The archetypal government body or official has no commercial motivations, adheres to proper process and standards of propriety, and has long been required to act not selfishly but altruistically. As explained below,[66] the misfeasance tort can be proved in alternative ways, one of them (targeted malice) amounting in essence to a prima facie tort.

In Ashby, Holt CJ awarded £200 in damages, even though Mr Ashby’s preferred candidate had won the election without Mr Ashby’s vote, and even though Mr Ashby himself had suffered no material loss. The judgment spoke of deterring ‘like offences’,[67] and the sheer size of the award[68] showed that it was clearly intended as a fine. Neither malice nor fraud would attract a figure of equivalent size through the tort system these days, because the dominant view is that only the criminal courts should deal with crime,[69] leaving tort focused on compensation. Indeed, some would say that tort law should focus solely on claims for compensation.[70] However, there have always been areas which undeniably use tort law for other means.[71]

The only issue in Ashley v Chief Constable of Sussex Police[72] was whether a police killing of a man had been lawful. In an attempt to avoid that issue going to trial, the police were prepared to admit the quantum of damages as well as liability for false imprisonment and negligence, but the majority let the man’s family proceed to trial for assault and battery. Despite those concessions, the majority held that the family was entitled to use the court solely for vindication of their belief that a wrong greater than the admitted torts had been committed.[73]

Punitive damages can be claimed for misfeasance,[74] provided that the plaintiff has also sustained some material loss.[75] It is in fact difficult to find modern misfeasance cases in which they have been awarded,[76] doubtless because it is so easy to disguise a punitive award as aggravated damages — but even the theoretical availability of punitive damages represents for England an acknowledgment of the special position reserved for claims against public officials for misconduct that is oppressive, arbitrary or unconstitutional. In most other respects, punitive damages are unavailable in that country,[77] and are very much the exception in Australia,[78] New Zealand[79] and Canada.[80] Once again, special treatment is reserved for officials behaving very badly. Lord Devlin’s leading discussion of exemplary damages was not in the context of misfeasance, but his explanation for treating public officials differently has obvious resonance:

Where one man is more powerful than another, it is inevitable that he will try to use his power to gain his ends; and if his power is much greater than the other’s, he might, perhaps, be said to be using it oppressively. If he uses his power illegally, he must of course pay for his illegality in the ordinary way; but he is not to be punished simply because he is the more powerful. In the case of the government it is different, for the servants of the government are also the servants of the people and the use of their power must always be subordinate to their duty of service. It is true that there is something repugnant about a big man bullying a small man and, very likely, the bullying will be a source of humiliation that makes the case one for aggravated damages, but it is not, in my opinion, punishable by [exemplary] damages.[81]

One might question whether corporate bullying is any less of a social evil than government bullying,[82] and that indeed appears to have been one of the reasons why his Lordship’s categorical restrictions on the availability of punitive damages failed to catch on in Australia.[83] Professor Birks, however, suggested that England’s reluctant retention of punitive damages might reflect a deep-seated suspicion that government cannot always be trusted to exercise its prosecutorial discretion wisely:

At some point in the rise of the efficient and infinitely resourced … state, the view took hold that the national bureaucracy could be relied upon to do all the punishing and avenging that was necessary. This manifested itself in ostensibly logical doctrine concerning the natural role of the law of civil wrongs. Properly understood, civil wrongs should not meddle with punishment and deterrence. … Declining resources now expose this as no more than a choice made at a time of faith in the power, efficiency and benignity of the state.[84]

That observation has added strength when the wrongdoer is a public officer,[85] although Lord Devlin did not assign that as a reason for allowing punitive damages in such circumstances. When that issue emerged more directly in a subsequent case, two Law Lords warmly endorsed the value of punitive damages in the protection of civil liberties.[86] The context was important — it was a misfeasance case, providing for the first time an occasion for drawing together the common threads running through misfeasance and the wider tort law debates concerning punitive damages. It appears that only Lord Bingham has advocated trusting the state to launch criminal proceedings against its own officers.[87] If the criminal justice system has imposed a substantial punishment on the officer, then exemplary damages will not be available.[88]

V THE CRIMINAL OFFENCE

If, as argued above, the tort of misfeasance is driven in part by a sense of moral outrage at the abuse of collective power, then its sense of punishment can never be far from the surface. It is therefore no digression to look briefly at the crime of misfeasance. Misconduct in public office is a common law indictable misdemeanour with a long history predating Ashby.[89] Its intersection with what is now called the misfeasance tort was obvious in Ashby itself, where Holt CJ noted that the defendants could have been prosecuted on indictment.[90] However, if the defendants had by a single act refused to take the votes of a large number of electors, then in order to avoid a multiplicity of actions, prosecution would have been the only remedy.[91]

This type of crossover between crime and tort was once common, and it is worth adding that a prosecution was indeed a remedy of sorts before the state had assumed a virtual monopoly of policing and prosecution functions. The legal system used to place far greater reliance on economic punishments and rewards for the enforcement of the criminal law generally and public duties in particular. Those derelict in the performance of their public duties could be prosecuted, and compensation of sorts could come from granting to the prosecutor or common informer a share of the fine or reward, or an award of costs to be paid from county funds.[92] The detection, capture and prosecution of thieves was a profitable, and therefore corruptible, system. That system’s acceptance of market-based policing bears some parallels with the re-emergence in modern times of private policing, which implicitly rejects the state’s previous claim to a monopoly of lawful violence.[93]

The common law misfeasance offence retains a degree of flexibility that makes it less certain than statutory offences, and attempts to codify it have been resisted in England in the belief that the advantages of flexibility outweigh the gains of certainty.[94] The common law offence covers acts or omissions of public officers in the course of or in relation to their public office, which amount to misconduct with a degree of culpability that warrants public condemnation and criminal punishment.[95] Speaking for the Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal, Sir Anthony Mason NPJ said that whether the misconduct is sufficiently culpable depends on whether it is serious ‘having regard to the responsibilities of the office and the office-holder, the importance of the public objects which they serve and the nature and extent of the departure from those responsibilities.’[96]

Speaking for the English Court of Appeal, Pill LJ said that

there must be a serious departure from proper standards before the criminal offence is committed; and a departure not merely negligent but amounting to an affront to the standing of the public office held. The threshold is a high one requiring conduct so far below acceptable standards as to amount to an abuse of the public’s trust in the office holder. A mistake, even a serious one, will not suffice.[97]

Misconduct is probably an offence defined by conduct rather than outcome, so that the actuality or risk of harmful consequences serve only as bases for inferring the relevant degree of seriousness,[98] which is a jury issue. In jurisdictions where the common law’s general offence remains, it is charged as misfeasance (or misconduct) in a public office.[99]

Some Australian jurisdictions have replaced the common law offence with statutory offences that appear to be narrower, and are certainly more determinate.[100] Canada’s codification is also narrow, in that its ‘breach of trust’ offence has been held to have codified the crime of misfeasance, but not of nonfeasance.[101]

Clearly, there are differences between the tort and the crime — for example, the crime is a conduct offence,[102] whilst the tort requires both conduct and material damage.[103] There has nevertheless been some cross-referencing in some of the recent tort judgments to their relatives in criminal cases,[104] and some of the recent criminal judgments concerning the common law offence have returned the compliment.[105] The context was a debate as to the meaning of reckless indifference. The House of Lords in R v Caldwell[106] had elided criminal negligence with criminal recklessness by ruling that a person could be criminally reckless if they had given no thought whatsoever to a particular and objectively obvious circumstance or risk.[107] Lord Steyn refused in Three Rivers to import that precedent across to the misfeasance tort,[108] and gave the broadest of hints that R v Caldwell needed overruling, an event that occurred just four years later.[109]

VI THE MENTAL ELEMENTS OF THE MODERN TORT: A GRADUAL PROCESS OF DILUTION

Accounts of the misfeasance tort typically credit it with a long history, but add in the next breath that its reach, content and boundaries still need definition.[110] Both statements are correct; its history is long and tangled, with the result that what has emerged over the last 50 or so years is in reality nothing less than a new tort to meet the needs of people living in an administrative state. Most of the modern changes have occurred through a series of cases in which judges have diluted the requirement of malice, at the same time as they have expressed confidence that their changes leave sufficient protection for public officials against liability to an indeterminate class to an indeterminate extent.

The meaning of ‘malice’ in the early cases was generally straightforward; these cases were all about officials aiming straight for their plaintiffs, with every intention of harming them for reasons that they must have known were unlawful.[111] The moral case for damages in such circumstances is very strong, but it would be rare indeed for a plaintiff to be able to plead and particularise such malice, and even more rare to prove it. It is probably small wonder, therefore, that misfeasance was virtually defunct in England (although not elsewhere in the British Commonwealth) by the beginning of the last century. Lord Halsbury’s Laws of England confused it with tort law’s more general distinction between misfeasance and nonfeasance,[112] and the Court of Appeal forgot its existence entirely.[113]

In Farrington v Thomson,[114] Smith J took the first step beyond the old model of the intentional and malicious infliction of harm. A publican had committed three licensing offences in quick succession, so that his second offence occurred before conviction for his first offence. The Licensing Act 1928 (Vic) s 177 provided for forfeiture of the licence upon a third conviction. No-one was empowered to order the publican to cease trading, because the Act made forfeiture automatic. The police had known this when they ordered the publican to close down; they thought that the licence had been forfeited. If the forfeiture provision had in truth applied, then the publican could hardly have claimed that the police order had caused him compensable loss, but the police had misconstrued that provision in complete good faith. Because the publican’s second offence had predated his first conviction, it did not count towards forfeiture, with the result that his licence remained lawfully intact. For this technicality,[115] Smith J held the police liable in misfeasance, which his Honour repackaged into a form that is now familiar. He proposed an action for damages for misfeasance in public office where the public officer either ‘acted maliciously, in the sense of having an intention to injure’, or (and this was the big step) caused damage to the plaintiff by ‘an act which, to his knowledge, amounts to an abuse of his office’.[116]

Professor de Smith publicised Farrington v Thomson for all British Commonwealth readers in 1968.[117] Almost a decade later, Professor Wade switched from sceptic to enthusiast.[118] The following year, an article appeared which explored the commonwealth literature in considerable detail, and urged the English courts to treat this rediscovered tort as more than just an ‘academic curiosity’.[119] Shortly afterwards, and without citing a single authority, the Privy Council said that the tort was ‘well-established’, and that its constituent mental elements were either malice or deliberate excess of power.[120] The English Court of Appeal confirmed that distinction in Bourgoin SA v Ministry of Agriculture, Fisheries and Food (‘Bourgoin’),[121] and applied for the first time the label of ‘targeted malice’ to the old model.[122] As in Farrington v Thomson, the defendant Minister in Bourgoin had borne the plaintiffs no grudge, but his deliberate illegality was hardly technical. He had banned the importation of French turkeys for Christmas on food safety grounds when he knew that these did not apply. His motive was the patriotic protection of English producers, and his plea that he was not aiming to hurt their competitors was to no avail. Bourgoin sought to minimise the step it was taking, by saying that the Minister’s knowledge that his illegal action would harm the French was no different to him having sought that damage — in effect, an intention to harm was imputed from his knowledge.[123]

Bourgoin’s expansion from deliberate harm to deliberate illegality was small compared to the next step. The quartet of leading cases added a third alternative to the mental elements of misfeasance. They reasoned that there was no moral difference between knowing something on the one hand, and being aware of its possibility but not caring whether it might be true or might occur.[124] This third variant is generally referred to as reckless indifference, but it is not to be imputed — the defendant must have consciously adverted to the relevant circumstance or risk and decided not to care about it. Analogising from criminal law principles, the indifference must be subjective.[125]

There were two immediate problems that arose in consequence of watering down the minimum requisite mental elements for misfeasance to reckless indifference. The first problem was whether reckless indifference should be applied to one or both of the principal elements of misfeasance (namely, illegality and resultant harm). The second problem was whether there must be a correlation between the plaintiff’s harm and the level of risk that the defendant consciously chose to disregard. It is clear that the reckless indifference component in New Zealand and England applies both to the harm that the plaintiff has suffered,[126] and to the illegality component of the tort.[127] In all jurisdictions, it remains to be seen if misfeasance will require some degree of correlation between the extent of the risk of harm and the defendant’s deliberate lack of concern.

The House of Lords decided Three Rivers in two parts: the first part considered the tort’s elements, and the second part considered the revamped pleadings and a motion to strike them out on the ground that the claim had no reasonable prospects of success. In part one, their Lordships were very clear that a claim based on reckless indifference had to plead that the harm which the defendant had chosen to disregard was a probable or likely harm.[128] With respect, that was an unnecessary complication, as Lord Hope seemed to realise in part two, when he rejected a challenge to a pleading that alleged that the defendant had consciously adverted merely to a risk of harm, rather than a probable or likely risk of harm. In dismissing the challenge, Lord Hope converted part one’s requirement that harm be ‘probable’ or ‘likely’ into a non-probabilistic requirement that the harm be ‘serious’, with the result that an improbable risk of serious harm might sometimes suffice.[129] In effect, though not explicitly in words, Lord Hope ended up treating the probability of risk as one of the elements, along with the gravity of harm (should it eventuate), that goes not to indifference but to recklessness. Distinguishing between recklessness and indifference is not a mere semantic nicety — as discussed below, it has the potential to counter the possibility of misfeasance liability when that liability is out of all proportion to the blameworthiness of the defendant’s conduct.[130]

Mengel had the least need to descend to this level of detail, because the plaintiffs had come nowhere close to establishing knowledge or conscious indifference on the part of the defendant’s officers to the limits of their lawful powers.[131] The plurality judgment said that even if the plaintiffs’ case had been stronger in this respect, they would also have needed to establish that their harm had been at least foreseeable, and perhaps even probable.[132] Although it is not entirely clear, it is likely that (like Lord Hope in part two of Three Rivers) their Honours wanted at the very least that there be reckless indifference as to harm, but regarded the probability of risk as going to recklessness, rather than treating it as a super-added requirement.[133] However, that is not how Mengel has been interpreted in Australia — currently, the reckless indifference requirement applies only to the illegality issue, and not to the risk of harm.[134] The harm must have been foreseeable, but the defendant need not have adverted to its risk.[135]

Most modern cases and commentaries are content to give the standard two-limb definition of misfeasance, which splits it into ‘targeted malice’ and ‘the rest’.[136] Using the same ingredients, Lord Hobhouse said that there are three limbs — purpose, knowledge and consciously reckless indifference.[137] Because it is clear, however, that there are not two (or three) torts but one,[138] it is necessary to consider the point of having alternative limbs. On one view of it, the alternative mental elements (targeted malice, knowledge and conscious indifference) comprise a closed list of the types of fault sufficient to warrant an action for misfeasance.[139] An alternative view is to see these mental elements not as a closed list, but rather as instances (or even evidence)[140] of the types of dishonesty or want of good faith that the tort requires.

In a much-quoted passage, Brennan J said in Mengel that the core of misfeasance lay in ‘the absence of an honest attempt to perform the functions of the office’.[141] His Honour said that there was such an absence if the defendant had acted invalidly and with malice, knowledge or reckless indifference, and he may well have intended that list to be exhaustive. There are passages in Three Rivers that could be interpreted as requiring proof of dishonesty or bad faith as an additional element in all cases.[142] In Australia, proof that defendants knew that they were acting beyond power is all that is needed to establish bad faith.[143]

Lord Millett’s view, however, was that deliberate illegality is insufficient where defendants believe that they are acting in the best interests of the plaintiff.[144] He distinguished such instances from the situation in Bourgoin, where the defendant knew that he had acted against the plaintiff’s interests but had imagined that he was acting in the best interests of the general public.[145] Implicit in that distinction is a welcome recognition that deliberate breaches of the law sometimes merit different responses. In other contexts, judicial condemnation does not automatically follow from proof that public officers have deliberately broken the law,[146] and in their dealings with bureaucracy, the general public has often depended upon the willingness of public officials to bend the rules. Perhaps Lord Millett’s concern might be appropriately addressed by setting tighter limits on the scope of liability where the tortfeasor’s wrongdoing was not self-serving. An official who accedes to the plaintiff’s request to bend the rules should not necessarily incur liability unless, of course, the plaintiff was in a particularly fragile state.[147]

Even where the rules are bent against the plaintiff’s interests, the loss suffered will not always be recognised as compensable in tort. The plaintiff in one case had been convicted on the basis of evidence that the police had obtained, from a third party, by deliberately breaking the law. The plaintiff’s misfeasance claim failed at several points, one being that the police had only ever intended to obtain truthful evidence, and the evidence had in fact been truthful.[148] In effect, the plaintiff’s loss was to have been convicted on reliable evidence after a fair trial — hardly a loss that tort should recognise.

Several of the leading judgments proceed as if liability will always result from proof of targeted malice,[149] but two obvious qualifications are needed. First, there will be no case of targeted malice if the plaintiff’s harm is the very point of the relevant power, and if nothing more is shown than the defendant’s intention to inflict that harm. In these circumstances, the misfeasance claim will need to meet the requirements of knowledge of the illegality or reckless indifference to the risk of illegality.[150] Police, for example, often know that they will harm a person’s interests, but that is no misfeasance provided they act in good faith.[151] The same point emerged from a case involving a public servant’s dismissal, even though there had been bad blood between the defendant and the plaintiff.[152] Similarly, a decision taken in good faith to place the plaintiff in immigration detention could not qualify as targeted malice.[153]

Secondly, malice is not always a shortcut to liability in misfeasance, a point that Harper J made in Grimwade v Victoria.[154] His Honour hypothesised a parking officer giving a ticket with malicious glee to his worst enemy. If the car was in fact parked illegally, the officer’s malice would be irrelevant.[155]

Most cases treat Roncarelli v Duplessis[156] as a modern paradigm of misfeasance, although the term itself played no part in the case. The assumption is that Minister Duplessis would still be found liable under today’s more structured misfeasance tort, but I am not so sure. The famously autocratic Premier and Attorney-General of Quebec had either cancelled or ordered the cancellation of Mr Roncarelli’s liquor permit, attached to a profitable and well-run restaurant that had been in the family for many years. That he wished harm to Mr Roncarelli was indisputable, and if it was relevant, his reasons were also clearly ultra vires, although his intervention was even more clearly invalid because the power of permit cancellation belonged to the Liquor Commissioner, not the Premier. However, only Abbott J said that Minister Duplessis knew he was breaking the law;[157] the other judgments treated Duplessis as having assumed that he was acting lawfully, which meant that he was not deliberately indifferent as to the law.[158] Admittedly, Rand J found Duplessis guilty of ‘malice’,[159] but his definition slid from deliberate illegality, to action taken in good faith but for an ‘improper purpose’ in administrative law terms.[160] Improper purpose is a review ground that almost never involves personal dishonesty or impropriety. If targeted malice (meaning the deliberate infliction of harm) provides no more than a strong but rebuttable presumption[161] that the defendant knew that he or she was exceeding the law, and if Minister Duplessis is to be taken as having broken the law entirely inadvertently, then he would nowadays escape liability under that head. He would likewise escape liability for reckless indifference, because his illegality was not advertent. Today, Minister Duplessis should escape misfeasance liability for want of relevant fault; he was objectively reckless but not subjectively indifferent.[162]

VII ACTIONS FOR BREACH OF DUTY: WHICH DUTY?

The early precedents sometimes cited as part of the history of the misfeasance tort all discussed the common law’s remedial reach for breaches of public duty. As explained below, that could be misleading these days, because it suggests the need either for an antecedent relationship between the parties or for a legal duty requiring the defendant to have the plaintiff in mind. If there is a duty nowadays, it is to not deliberately abuse a public power, and expressed at that level, it is not very useful. It is instructive to track the history of the search for a meaningful action for breach of duty.

Tort law has a long history of experimentation with actions for breach of duties which might in some sense be characterised as duties of a public nature. There have been actions upon the statute, actions for breach of public duty, actions for breach of statutory duty, a short-lived attempt to use Lord Cairns’ Act[163] as a route to a damages award in lieu of a public law injunction, and even an attempt to extend damages for negligence wherever a public official’s failure to confer a benefit was invalid for Wednesbury unreasonableness.[164]

Some say that the story starts with the second Statute of Westminster.[165] Enacted in 1285, one of its chapters (in Consimili Casu) stated that in cases where no exact precedent for a writ could be found ‘from henceforth, where in one case a writ is granted, in like case, requiring like remedy, the writ shall be made as hath been used before’.[166] That certainly gave some impetus to the incremental development of the forms of action, but it is doubtful that it authorised actions for breach of any statutory duties,[167] let alone for breach of common law duties.

Then there was the relatively short-lived proposition that an action would lie for breach of a public duty. First aired in 1786,[168] it appears that this doctrine was intended to link up a number of previously distinct actions against those charged with duties towards the public for neglect, non-performance, or even abuse of office.[169] Although the House of Lords approved the rule twice in the early 19th century,[170] it was stated far too broadly to have survived. According to Paul Finn, the courts voiced concerns that so unrestricted a basis of public liability would have ruinous consequences for public authorities, particularly in light of the massive expansion of statutory authorities with finite budgets charged with the performance of public duties.[171]

The action for breach of public duty morphed into a narrower but always uncertain tort for breach of statutory duty.[172] This tort has survived, but with underlying policy concerns similar to those that had helped kill off the action for breach of public duty. In purely numerical terms, there are far more duties sourced to statute than to the common law, and the puzzle for the courts has always been how to set principled and predictively useful parameters for the statutory tort.[173]

Holt CJ himself had said something in support of an action for breach of statutory duty,[174] but that was obiter, and the action cannot be said to have been firmly established until the last quarter of the 19th century.[175] Even now, however, its field of operation seems largely confined to actions for breach of statutory duties relating to the prevention of injury in places of work.[176] In earlier times, the tort was useful in helping employees get around the common employment rule,[177] and (for a while) the defence of contributory negligence.[178] If the relevant statute prescribes a duty of strict liability, then the statutory tort will have a practical advantage over the common law negligence action. That advantage was reduced, however, by the advent of no-fault workers’ compensation.[179] It may also be theoretically possible for the statutory tort occasionally to fill a gap left by the common law’s denial of a general duty to conform to the morals of a Good Samaritan.[180]

The tort’s basis is the implication of a statutory intention to grant a right of action to a plaintiff suffering loss from the defendant’s breach of a statutory duty, provided that the duty was intended for the benefit of a limited class of persons to which the plaintiff belongs.[181] Although posed as an exercise in statutory construction, the legislative intention (if it be found) is fictional, and the list of factors going one way or the other has never been of much help, because none of them are dispositive. Some of the leading judgments read as if there were rebuttable presumptions of statutory construction, but others give more credit to the judge than to legislative drafters in determining whether the relevant Act has created a cause of action.[182] It would appear that the real reason for the tort’s ossification is a prevailing unwillingness on the part of the judiciary to indulge in such a haphazard divination of statutory torts, particularly where the plaintiff’s purpose is to establish a strict liability tort. That certainly appears to have been one of the reasons why the Canadian Supreme Court abolished the tort, folding it into negligence.[183] An additional concern in Australia is that any treatment of the construction exercise as an unconvincing cover for judicial creativity might threaten the constitutional separation of powers.[184] The tort survives in Australia, New Zealand and England, but cannot be said to have thrived.

Having regard to the evolution of the statutory tort from earlier doctrines that focused on breach of public duty, what is particularly noteworthy is how rarely the statutory tort is applied for what might loosely be called maladministration by public authorities.[185] Although it is theoretically available against private and public defendants alike, it appears to be more difficult to imply the statutory grant of a right of action against public authorities.

One of the big factors in favour of implying a right of action is that the statutory duty might otherwise lack an adequate sanction for its breach.[186] One of the difficulties here is that the alternative sanction is sometimes a criminal penalty,[187] and sometimes an administrative enforcement mechanism[188] or even a right of access to judicial review[189] or merits review.[190] Further, a test that turned upon the adequacy of the statutory sanctions for breach would involve a radical departure from text-based principles of statutory interpretation.[191]

The requirement that the statutory duty have been enacted for the benefit of the plaintiff or a class to which the plaintiff belongs also weighs heavily against its application to public authorities. Regulatory and social welfare schemes, for example, are said to have been passed for the benefit of society at large rather than for particular classes such as the homeless or the unemployed.[192] Lord Simonds took the provision of a criminal sanction as evidence that the duty was enacted for the public’s benefit.[193]

It has been said that the action for breach of a public authority’s statutory duty is confined to duties with little or no discretionary content,[194] because it would be inappropriate for a court to exercise a discretion that is legislatively vested in an administrative authority.[195] Two Australian states have legislated to remind those within their jurisdictions that breach of a public authority’s statutory duty cannot lead to liability if that would contradict the relevant Act or its ‘policy’.[196]

Mention might also be made of a short-lived attempt to use Lord Cairns’ Act[197] as a vehicle for delivering discretionary damages for violation of laws enacted for the public benefit. That Act (and its successors) empowered the court in its discretion to grant damages in lieu of an injunction if that had been sought for the prevention of a ‘wrongdoing’. The development of the public law injunction was achieved by a liberalisation of the standing rules, such that plaintiffs could seek injunctions against public wrongs even if they had no legal or equitable rights under threat, provided that they suffered (or would suffer) damage peculiar to themselves.[198] In Australia, that standing rule was further relaxed by switching from ‘peculiar’ to ‘special’ damage,[199] and in England, the standing requirement became entirely discretionary.[200] The courts in New Zealand and Australia have decided, in effect, that the injunction’s reach now extends considerably further than the power under Lord Cairns’ Act to award damages in lieu of an injunction, a power which should be confined to cases of threatened violations of a plaintiff’s legal or equitable rights or interests.[201] It was reasoned that the contrary proposition would have been tantamount to making discretionary damages available for threatened or continuing breach of statute.

Finally, Lord Hoffmann wondered aloud whether plaintiffs might occasionally (albeit rarely) be entitled to damages in negligence, on the ground, in effect, of Wednesbury unreasonableness. His Lordship had thought this possible if a body exercising public power had failed to exercise a statutory power to confer a benefit upon the plaintiff in circumstances where the only lawful option on the facts had been to confer that benefit.[202] In effect, the idea was that if mandamus could have been granted for Wednesbury unreasonableness, then that might be the basis for a claim in negligence. However, that idea was abandoned shortly afterwards, in a case that reaffirmed the distinction between a statutory duty enforceable by mandamus and a common law duty of care, which remained a precondition to an award of damages in negligence.[203]

VIII THE LIMITS OF NEGLIGENCE LAW

Although misfeasance is classified as an intentional tort,[204] it now stretches to include actual reckless indifference, in which the indifference is defined subjectively so as to exclude the defendant who failed to think of a risk that any reasonable person would have foreseen.[205] Apart from that, however, one might question whether there is much practical difference between indifferent tortfeasors in misfeasance and negligence. The Law Commission for England and Wales (‘Commission’) had thought the two to be so close that if negligence were to be appropriately expanded, then misfeasance could be safely abolished.[206] The Commission eventually abandoned the whole idea,[207] because of widespread opposition from the profession and the academy on normative grounds, and from the government which declined to assist the Commission’s speculation as to the cost of its proposals.

The Commission’s methodology adapted the English common law’s approach to novel ‘duty of care’ issues in negligence law,[208] balancing normative issues with considerations designed to make its proposals cost-neutral so far as that could be predicted. The liability of public authorities in negligence is usually assessed on the same basis as the liability of anyone else, but where the complaint relates to an activity that has no close private sector analogue or raises issues best left to the political branches, the courts deploy a number of control devices that limit or even deny a duty of care, or that limit the amount of liability. In essence, the judges shape the contours of negligence in response to certain types of relational or cost–benefit considerations and in response to operational pressures on the defendant.

At common law, for example, authorities investigating possible child abuse owe no duty of care to suspect parents;[209] regulators of nursing homes might well owe a duty of care to the residents, but not to the operators;[210] in most places, the police owe no duty of care to potential victims in their task of crime prevention;[211] and litigants (even if they are public authorities) owe no duty of care to their opponents.[212] Negligence also has tight restrictions on claims for compensation for purely economic loss, and yet as far as one can tell, these are typically the only losses alleged in misfeasance cases.[213]

Lawyers can be liable for getting the law wrong because they are legal professionals; even so, their liability is usually limited to their clients or those the client seeks to benefit.[214] Negligence law rarely requires those not legally qualified to get the law right, and that principle equally holds for public authorities, who usually have no duty to take care to ensure that they act validly.[215] If public officials were under such a duty of care, then it would sometimes be the shortest way around the proposition that invalidity per se is no ground for a tort claim. Furthermore, one would expect the duty usually to be discharged by obtaining legal advice.[216] However, it would be difficult for a court to set standards as to when an administrative authority should seek legal advice.[217]

Misfeasance has adopted none of these strategies in response to fears that it might overreach, burdening individual defendants or their governments with potentially unlimited liability for what might have been an entirely understandable (if wrong) excess of public zeal. It also lacks the protection of negligence law’s troubled abstention from cases of so-called ‘pure omission’.[218] Negligence law rarely requires defendants to take active steps in the protection of plaintiffs either from themselves[219] or from harm caused by third parties;[220] this is usually explained in terms of respecting an individual defendant’s autonomy, especially where the parties are strangers.[221] If a public authority is already under a duty to assist, however, then misfeasance will cover that authority’s conscious decision to violate that duty by taking no action.[222] Negligence law would probably have imposed no liability on the constable in R v Dytham (‘Dytham’),[223] who had callously chosen to do nothing to help or summon help as he watched a man being beaten to death; his uniform would have made no difference in a negligence action, but it would have made all the difference to a misfeasance action.[224]

These distinctions between negligence and misfeasance, therefore, go considerably beyond the difference between accidental and advertent risk-taking. Tort’s pervasive fears of excessive liability are never far from the surface in misfeasance cases, but the misfeasance tort lacks the usual tools for handling them. Without the interposition of a common law duty of care, and with actionability being possible for deliberate or consciously indifferent breach of statutory duties to assist or protect the public, the tort may yet show signs of strain. It currently relies on its very demanding mental elements to restrain liability, but if these prove insufficient, then the focus may well turn to a closer examination of the factors that might make indifference ‘reckless’, to causation issues, and to the limits of vicarious liability.

IX RIGHTS, WRONGS AND DUTIES

Reckless indifference in misfeasance law, therefore, is not about want of care because it has no predicate of a duty of care. Indeed, misfeasance can apply in the absence of any duty lying upon the defendant or correlative right inhering in the plaintiff, the most obvious example being the case where the defendant deliberately and unlawfully refuses to exercise a discretionary function. This was not always the case, however.

In Ashby itself, Holt CJ’s judgment was anchored to a theory of rights protection, such that Mr Ashby’s right to vote was cast in terms of a property right.[225] Modern judges rightly find that entirely unconvincing,[226] and one might speculate as to whether even Holt CJ saw it as no more than a convenient device, designed to get him to his damages conclusion in an era when there could be no common law damages without rights. Many judgments still talk of abuse of ‘duty’, but usually interchangeably with abuse of ‘power’.[227]

In Australia, however, there is a troubling trickle of cases flowing from a Full Court decision of the Victorian Supreme Court in Tampion v Anderson (‘Tampion’),[228] which said quite plainly that the misfeasance tortfeasor must have owed the plaintiff ‘a duty not to commit the particular abuse complained of.’[229] That was one of the reasons for excluding a misfeasance claim against counsel assisting a Board of Inquiry and its chairperson, where the gist of the complaint was that the defendants had deliberately exceeded their terms of reference in eliciting evidence from persons other than the plaintiff. In other words, if there was any misfeasance, its only compensable victims had been the third-party witnesses, because only they were owed duties not to be improperly coerced.

The joint judgment in Mengel quoted Tampion without apparent disapproval.[230] Writing separately in Mengel, however, Brennan J was at pains to distance himself from Tampion’s asserted need for an antecedent duty,[231] and Deane J was in general agreement with Brennan J.[232] In Leerdam v Noori (‘Leerdam’),[233] the New South Wales Court of Appeal did not formally side with Brennan J, but it came very close. Spigelman CJ said that misfeasance covers abuse of powers and duties,[234] and Macfarlan JA was disposed to say that if there must be a duty, then it need be owed only to the public generally, or perhaps to a class to which the plaintiff belongs.[235] Leerdam in its turn was responding to Cannon v Tahche (‘Cannon’),[236] which had lined up with Tampion. The issue in Leerdam and Cannon was whether misfeasance could be founded upon breaches by legal practitioners of their ethical duties towards a court or tribunal. If (as Cannon supposed) the ‘model litigant’ obligations borne by government’s legal representatives were purely ethical,[237] then it would follow that the defendant lawyers’ alleged misbehaviour would not have constituted illegalities. Their misconduct would therefore be an insufficient basis for a misfeasance action unless (as discussed below in Part XI) the tort were to extend beyond illegality, to include abuse of position or influence.

That is not to deny the relevance of distinguishing duties from powers. A plaintiff’s loss is more easily connected to a defendant’s wilful breach of a tightly confined legal duty than to a defendant’s wilful breach of a broad discretion. It will often be difficult to satisfy causation’s prima facie ‘but for’ test in cases where the defendant illegally chose not to perform a protective or interventionist duty for the plaintiff’s benefit.[238] It will be even more difficult as the discretionary elements in the defendant’s functions increase, and most difficult where the defendant has ruled the plaintiff out of consideration for the discretionary award of benefits in the future. In the case of lost future benefits that are contingent on the future exercise of a discretionary power, the court cannot determine how those discretions should be exercised.[239] To avoid usurping the administrative decision-maker’s role, the court must confine itself to valuing the opportunities lost to the plaintiff.[240]

The New Zealand Court of Appeal agreed with Brennan J’s decision in Mengel not to follow Tampion,[241] and Lord Hobhouse said in Three Rivers that misfeasance in public office ‘does not, and does not need to, apply where the defendant has invaded a legally protected right of the plaintiff.’[242] As a purely descriptive matter, Lord Hobhouse was surely correct, and it appears that all but one of the other judgments came to the same view.[243] No misfeasance case, old or modern, has attempted to catalogue the sorts of legal rights or interests that the tort might protect, the reality being that the relevant ‘right’ is no less (and possibly more) than the right to compensation for loss caused by the wilful misuse of state power.

There are some who regret the absence in misfeasance of a right–duty relationship between the parties. Those regrets are to an extent located in the broader debate between the corrective justice and distributive justice models of tort law,[244] but this is not the place (and I am not the author) to enter upon debates as to tort’s taxonomy.[245]

X MORAL EQUIVALENCE AND THE VARIABILITY OF ‘RECKLESSNESS’

There is little if any need for doctrines of standing, proximity or remoteness in the case of targeted malice, where the moral case for full recovery is plain. The cases concerning the mental elements of the tort of misfeasance, however, now appear to have established a moral equivalence between consciously indifferent risk-taking (whether as to illegality or the potential for harm), and the knowing use of illegal means for the deliberate infliction of harm. That moral equivalence applies both to cases of power and duty.

It might now become necessary to set some additional criteria connecting the defendant and the plaintiff, and some limits to the harms for which the defendant might be liable. The joint judgment in Mengel said that the tort’s reach must bear some correlation to the defendant’s ability to pay, especially if (as it supposed was the case in Australia) the government might not indemnify its officers.[246] Lord Hobhouse spoke in Three Rivers of the need for a nexus between the defendant’s state of mind and the type or extent of harm for which he or she would be liable.[247]

The allegations against the Bank of England in Three Rivers were always highly implausible, but imagine if the plaintiffs had succeeded in establishing that at some point, the Bank had just dithered for some considerable time after it had reached the conclusion that the crooked bank it was meant to be regulating simply could not be saved. The only members of the class action were the failed bank’s existing or potential depositors, but the Bank would have known that many others would also have lost money. Three Rivers rejected the Bank’s call to require an antecedent legal right in a plaintiff, and it also rejected the Bank’s argument for a ‘proximity’ limit either to the class of plaintiffs or to their compensable losses. It held that these restraints were unnecessary in light of its requirement that a misfeasance tortfeasor must at the very least have consciously decided to risk inflicting probable harm on the plaintiff or on a class to which the plaintiff belonged.[248] At the same time, however, it hinted that some other limits might be needed in the future: limits variously framed as requirements that there be standing to sue,[249] or special damage not suffered by the general public,[250] or membership of a class that the defendant was meant to have protected,[251] or a ‘direct’ link between the defendant’s misconduct and the plaintiff’s loss.[252] It is difficult to place much faith in limits such as these. Judicial review’s locus standi learning would be inadequate, especially in England which has in practical terms converted the lack of standing into no more than a discretionary bar.[253] Limiting the tort to damage caused ‘directly’ would be equally vague.

The Court of Appeal declared that Three Rivers was mistaken in ever thinking that there was a problem. That was in Akenzua v Secretary of State for the Home Department (‘Akenzua’), whose facts cried out for compensation.[254] The estate of a murdered woman sued the defendant in misfeasance for her death. The authorities had twice secured her assailant’s release from custody, because he was useful to them as a paid informer. He was at large at the time of the murder because the authorities had interfered with the proper handling of serious charges relating to drugs, offensive weapons, and rape, all of which they knew he had committed whilst improperly released. They had also known that he had entered the country illegally, but they had procured a temporary visa to get over that problem. They had known that he was extremely dangerous, because he had told them that he had murdered people in his home country. In terms of Three Rivers, therefore, they had known of the probability of him committing a violent crime, and the issue was whether it mattered that the authorities could have had no idea who his next victim might be. The Court held that any suggestion in Three Rivers that the defendant must have appreciated risk to a class of probable victims[255] was both obiter and misguided. It was morally misguided because it sought to draw lines that were ‘purely numerical’,[256] and from negligence law. In comparison, the conduct of a misfeasance tortfeasor is ‘altogether more blameworthy’.[257] The Court said that misfeasance liability should apply equally to the bad faith release of three different types of murderers, namely, the man known to be intent on murdering his wife, Hannibal Lecter intent on murdering a few more than that, and a terrorist bent on a single act of mass destruction.[258]

The case for liability in all three instances supposed in Akenzua is indeed strong, but it fails to overcome the Three Rivers concern for articulating some limits to liability. Akenzua is almost unique in misfeasance law, which hardly ever sees claims for personal injury or death.[259] Misfeasance claimants typically assert purely economic loss, and fears of liability to an indeterminate class for an indeterminate amount for that type of loss are surely as valid in misfeasance claims as in negligence claims.

To return to Lord Hope’s implicit distinction between indifference and recklessness,[260] the concept of recklessness is not purely subjective. As the New Zealand Court of Appeal held in Minister of Fisheries v Pranfield Holdings Ltd (‘Pranfield’), the ‘recklessness’ element in misfeasance is both subjective and objective.[261] The result in Pranfield was to hold that despite knowledge of doubts about the legality of their actions, government officials were not, in the circumstances, reckless in failing to obtain a legal opinion. The Court said that one could not reasonably expect government officials to suspend all action every time they encountered legal doubt. It would be easier in Three Rivers to characterise as ‘reckless’ the Bank’s hypothetical indifference to depositors than its hypothetical indifference to sections of the wider community which would also suffer, even though the Bank’s brief is wider than protection of depositors’ interests.[262]

XI MUST THE DEFENDANT BE EXERCISING A PUBLIC FUNCTION?

The moral case for a misfeasance tort is typically put as the need for protection from a deliberate abuse of coercive state power over the subject, but in fact, the tort has always gone wider than the improper use of coercive power — it has always covered wilful refusals to perform duties to provide protection for the subject. In the old case of Henly v Lyme,[263] there was a duty to keep a sea wall in good repair; in Three Rivers, there was a duty to protect a trading bank’s potential depositors (at least), and perhaps existing depositors; and in Dytham,[264] there was a duty to make some attempt to stop a murder taking place before the very eyes of an indifferent police officer.

The duty cases are harder to prove than the coercive power cases, because a mere omission to perform a duty is not enough. The requirement of subjective fault means that defendants must either have decided not to perform a duty of which they were aware, or have consciously decided not to care whether they were under a duty.[265] Further, a discretionary power of protection will not become a duty unless the discretion has run out in the sense that no legally available reasons apply for declining to intervene.[266]

The duty cases have gone a step further in circumstances where the gist of the allegation is that the authorities have deliberately and illegally suppressed or distorted evidence, so that criminals go free to the distress of their victims and the victims’ families. The Canadian Supreme Court allowed such a claim to go forward in Odhavji, leaving (for future consideration) the difficult issue of whether the family had suffered tortiously recognised psychiatric harm. A cover-up of a police rape in Garrett had effectively ruined the victim’s reputation, because her assailant’s lurid denials gained credibility for want of a proper investigation.[267]

Misfeasance clearly draws no distinction between powers or duties according to whether their provenance is statutory or prerogative,[268] but uncertainty remains as to whether they must bear a ‘public’ aspect and if so, how one might define that limitation. Current doctrine extends only to ‘public’ officers, a limitation discussed separately below. In this Part, however, it is necessary to discuss whether the conduct of public officers to which the tort extends has an additional ‘public’ aspect, defined perhaps in the same or similar terms that are commonly used to describe the reach of judicial review of administrative action.

In Leerdam, Macfarlan JA explained his reasons for wanting a ‘public’ aspect in terms that assumed that the tort might extend beyond public servants:

If the tort were not limited to the abuse of public powers and authorities, its scope would be wide indeed. There would be the potential for a multitude of actions to be brought by members of the public in relation to the conduct by public servants and public contractors of their day to day duties. This would in my view involve an unwarranted extension of the tort well beyond what has been treated thus far as its scope.[269]

However, Slade LJ said in Jones v Swansea City Council (‘Jones’) that what matters is not whether the power is public or private, but whether it is exercised by a public body.[270] Jones was a tenant of commercial property that the Council owned. She alleged that the Council had imposed a restriction upon her use of that property out of spite and revenge. Slade LJ’s statement lost some of its force, however, because the Court also said that the Council’s property powers could be exercised only in the public interest.[271] The case went to the House of Lords, which did not rule on that issue.[272] It is now clear that the Human Rights Act 1998 (UK) c 42 occasionally trumps the property rights of local authorities.[273]

The parallel criminal offence of misfeasance or misconduct in public office is unconcerned with whether the power is public or private, focusing instead on the status of the public officer and the gravity of his or her misconduct. The gist of the statutory offence is the improper use of either the power or the influence that comes with the position,[274] and the common law offence can be committed by serious misconduct that disgraces the office.[275] Brennan J said in Mengel that the misfeasance tort might flow from a deliberate abuse of ‘position or power’.[276]

It is difficult to know what to make of Jones. In terms of principle, it is hard to justify a liability rule whose imposition turns solely on whether the defendant is public or private. In terms of precedent, it is also difficult to square Jones with Calveley v Chief Constable of Merseyside Police (‘Calveley’), in which the House of Lords held that a deliberately misleading internal affairs report about the plaintiff police officer could not be the basis of a misfeasance claim, because the investigating officer had neither needed nor used any special powers to make his report.[277] The English Court of Appeal, however, followed Jones in Cornelius v Hackney London Borough Council (‘Cornelius’),[278] even though Calveley had not been overruled. Cornelius held that misfeasance extends beyond abuse of power to abuse of public position, with the result that a council officer could be liable for blackening a whistleblower’s name with press releases he knew to be false.[279]

Neasey J said in Pemberton v Attorney-General (Tas) that a school teacher in the public sector could not claim in misfeasance for wrongful dismissal because the defendant was not exercising a ‘public’ power, and the teacher was not a member of the ‘public’, even though the dismissal power was wholly governed by statute law.[280] The case is relatively old, and the other two judgments dismissed the misfeasance claim on the uncontentious ground that the defendant had acted in good faith.[281]

A Victorian court drew a line similar to that in Calveley, saying that so far as a Board of Inquiry exercised no special or coercive common law or statutory powers, but simply exceeded its terms of reference, it was not guilty of an abuse of ‘power’ for the purposes of the tort, even if it had acted maliciously; it may have abused its position or influence, but not its power.[282] The Full Court of the Federal Court did not deal satisfactorily with the issue in Emanuele v Hedley,[283] a case involving the sale of government real estate. The Court was prepared to assume that misfeasance could catch a government officer’s conduct in touting the sale, but ruled out that same officer’s internal report to his superior about misconduct committed by the reporting officer’s subordinate.[284]

Decisions such as Odhavji and Garrett prompt speculation as to the assumption made in most other cases that the exercise of the power or refusal to perform the duty must occur in circumstances warranting a judicial review declaration of invalidity. Invalidity was a critical requirement in Three Rivers and Mengel, but it would be a stretch to describe the deliberate suppression of evidence as ‘invalid’ conduct. Invalidity is needed to repel a defence of lawful authority,[285] and that will usually be the case where (as in Three Rivers) the breadth of the defendant’s discretionary power is the plaintiff’s chief obstacle. Invalidity, however, is only one way of establishing unlawfulness. According to Lord Hobhouse in Three Rivers, it is also established ‘from a straightforward breach of the relevant statutory provisions’.[286] Invalidity is clearly irrelevant to a claim that police have breached their statutory obligation to launch (as in Garrett) or cooperate with (as in Odhavji) an internal inquiry, or have wilfully refused to preserve the peace, in the knowledge that the plaintiff will suffer as a consequence.[287] It is submitted that for misfeasance to apply in those circumstances, the defendant’s illegality must have consisted of a breach of a requirement that applied only to public officials. Hitching misfeasance to invalidity in these cases is no more than an unintended hangover from the failed campaign to extend the negligence action to loss caused by careless invalidity.

Regardless of whether misfeasance applies only to the performance of public functions, a question remains as to whether it can apply to the judiciary. New Zealand’s Court of Appeal held that misfeasance extended beyond the abuse of administrative functions to include misconduct of a district court judge,[288] and Victoria’s Court of Appeal was inclined to agree.[289] The issue is unlikely to arise very often, because most judges now enjoy complete immunity from tort actions regarding their official conduct.[290]

XII THE DEFENDANT MUST BE A PUBLIC OFFICER

The cases require not just that defendants be guilty of an abuse of a public power, duty or possibly office, but also that they have been public officers. The precedents undoubtedly support this additional requirement, but it is otherwise difficult to justify. Its abolition would accord with the tort’s moral basis that the function is public in the sense that it must be exercised with the public interest in mind, and probably that it be a function which members of the public generally have no power or responsibility to perform. Abolition, however, is an option available only to the highest courts,[291] who have declared that the defendant must be a public officer.[292] All other courts must require that both the power and the person who exercises it be relevantly ‘public’.[293]

There are many cases discussing the extent to which private bodies or individuals may be subject to the processes of judicial review if they can be said in some sense to be performing public functions. Speaking generally, Australia has yet to resolve the issue of a government contractor’s susceptibility to the processes of judicial review,[294] whilst English law occasionally extends those processes beyond institutionally public bodies to persons whose powers are functionally public.[295] The issue is often one of mere process in administrative law as where, for example, private parties might be contractually obliged to accord procedural fairness even though they might not be subject to judicial review. In misfeasance, however, the issue is likely to be more important, because its principles currently apply only to defendants who not only exercise public power but are also public officers.

Lord Steyn said that ‘office’ should be understood in a ‘relatively wide sense’,[296] and Lord Hobhouse said that it ‘is a broad concept’,[297] applying to ‘those vested with governmental authority and the exercise of executive powers’.[298] There is very little authority on whether a person or body is a public officer for the purposes of misfeasance. Buxton LJ said in Society of Lloyd’s v Henderson that this was because the answer is usually obvious.[299] His Lordship said that the critical points were whether the defendant was exercising powers for a public, governmental purpose as opposed (in that case) to Lloyds, which existed solely for profit.[300]

Brennan J referred to an old definition of public officers, which in essence contained two elements. First, they must have been appointed to perform a public duty. Secondly, they must be remunerated, although that may come in the form of money or land from the Crown, or fees from the public.[301] The second element would not apply nowadays;[302] it reflects a bygone era when public offices were treated as property that could be bought and sold,[303] an era that had a very different conception of corruption.

Not all public servants fall within the scope of the misfeasance tort, even though their salaries come from public funds, and even though they may be ‘officers’ for administrative purposes and have to take an oath on appointment. A person might be a public employee but not a public officer.[304] There is in fact no single definition of ‘public officer’ across all contexts.[305]

Lawyers from the private profession increasingly conduct court and tribunal work for government clients, and some concern has been raised as to whether their contractual status should make any difference. It is unlikely that a person whose only powers and responsibilities flow from contract would be treated as a public officer for misfeasance purposes.[306] In Australia, this would appear to be one of two reasons for holding that lawyers drawn from the private sector are not amenable to the misfeasance tort. The other (and more straightforward) reason is that they are unlikely to be exercising specifically public powers or duties.[307] Hodgson JA concluded that the contractor must not only be carrying out ‘some task’, but also ‘himself or herself hold a public office’.[308] In contrast to these Australian decisions, it was suggested that officers working for England’s Crown Prosecution Service might be liable in misfeasance,[309] a suggestion distinguished in Australia on the ground that the Crown Prosecution Service is a creature of statute with statutory functions.[310]

The decision of the Full Court of the Federal Court in Emanuele v Hedley[311] presents a problem. In brief, the alleged misconduct was criminal entrapment to pay a bribe; an entrapment authorised at very senior levels within the public sector. The Court gave two reasons for saying that it was ‘a legal nonsense’ to suggest that the Commonwealth itself could commit misfeasance. Its first reason was that the Commonwealth could act only through agents, and its second reason was that the Commonwealth does not itself hold public office.[312] The first reason would suggest that institutions could only ever be liable vicariously and never as a principal through their agents, a suggestion at odds with decisions of the Privy Council and the House of Lords.[313] It is true that only natural persons have mental states, but it is no ‘nonsense’ to suggest that a principal has in law the mental states of its agents, or an organisation the mental states of the individuals on its governing body. The second reason puts form over substance. Of course the Commonwealth ‘holds’ no ‘office’, but applying that reasoning is to return to a conception that made sense when offices were seen as ways of making money.

It would be preferable to rebadge the tort as abuse of public power (or position, if it were to extend beyond instances of public law invalidity); the deliberate abuse of public power is no less serious if committed by either a public employee who holds no office or a government contractor performing a governmental function. The tort’s concern is with conscious maladministration, which is a wrong that can be committed by people high and low in the public sector and by some contractors to the public sector. Any concern about imposing misfeasance liability on low-level staff is misplaced. Low-ranking staff are unlikely to have enough power to abuse. Further, they are even less likely to know whether they are abusing that power, and if they are consciously indifferent about that abuse, they are highly unlikely to be adjudged reckless for having decided to give no further thought to the legal limits to their power.

XIII VICARIOUS LIABILITY ISSUES: A PUBLIC PURSE FOR A PUBLIC TORT?

Unlike their individual members, companies and public bodies have no minds of their own. That does not prevent public bodies from being directly liable for misfeasance. In the right circumstances, the mental state of their staff can be imputed to the organisations themselves. For example, if all the members of a local government council voted unanimously to cancel a land use development consent, and if they did that entirely out of a sense of revenge and self-interest, and in the knowledge that they were acting illegally, then they will have been guilty of bad faith sufficient for the purposes of misfeasance. However, they will not as individuals have caused the property developer’s loss, because only the council itself could cancel the development consent. In such a case, the council will be fixed with the mental state of the individuals comprising its governing body, and will be directly rather than vicariously liable in misfeasance for the harm it caused.[314] In many misfeasance cases, however, only individual staff members will be directly liable because causal responsibility and the requisite mental states resided only in them. The issue then becomes whether the public bodies for which they worked can be fixed with vicarious liability.[315]

Two concerns have been raised concerning the possibility of vicarious liability. Because the minimum requisite mental state comes close to dishonesty, and because illegality is required, doubts have arisen as to whether the misconduct of misfeasance tortfeasors can properly be regarded as an incident of their employment. Further, many (if not most) of the individual tortfeasors will have been abusing a statutory or common law function invested directly in them by virtue of their office or position, with the result that they will have been performing discretionary functions free of their employers’ control or direction. The common law does not impose vicarious liability on employers where the relevant tort was committed in the exercise of an independent discretion.[316] The second concern is more formidable than the first.

There have long been difficulties in formulating the basis of vicarious liability for deliberately illegal conduct committed without the employer’s de facto authority or ratification.[317] The difficulties increase when the primary tortfeasors act in their own interests and against those of their employers. The courts have recently propounded different tests for resolving claims against schools for their teachers’ sexual abuse of students. These tests turned on whether the illegal act bore a sufficiently close connection to the employee’s job, or whether the tortious conduct was no more than an unauthorised mode of performing authorised acts.[318] Vicarious liability for misfeasance, however, should present fewer problems than in the sexual assault cases. The individual tortfeasors’ conduct in cases of targeted malice would usually have been lawful if only their motives had been proper; the acts themselves would have been of a type that those individuals could usually have performed with propriety. The same applies to most other instances of misfeasance. The absence of targeted malice diminishes the tortfeasors’ impropriety, but their misbehaviour will usually be of a kind that they could have performed with propriety. And if the test be whether the misconduct was ‘closely connected’ to the misfeasance tortfeasors’ job, then once again, it will usually be easy enough to establish vicarious liability. Indeed, the sort of misconduct alleged in most misfeasance cases can only be committed ‘on the job’. As a private individual, I can neither cancel a trading bank’s licence (as in Three Rivers) nor impose regional restrictions on cattle droving (as in Mengel).

A more difficult problem arises from the common law’s protection of employers from vicarious liability for tortious behaviour that occurs in the exercise of an independent discretion. That protection is difficult to defend in policy terms, and has the potential to be raised in many (if not most) cases against public officers, whose discretionary powers are typically independent.[319] Statute abolished the protection in England,[320] New South Wales,[321] New Zealand,[322] and Canada.[323] It is unclear whether that protection remains elsewhere in Australia. South Australia used to have an Act that abolished most of the protection,[324] and it seems to have been assumed that when that Act was replaced by a more modern and slimmer version that made no mention of the independent discretion rule,[325] the common law rule was not revived.[326]

The English cases appear to have accepted that individual officers will transmit vicarious liability for their misfeasance torts.[327] The Commission wanted to abolish misfeasance entirely. It believed that individual liability for misfeasance was inappropriate and (in the Three Rivers case), intrusive and distressing. Its preference was that government alone should be liable, and that the criminal offence of misconduct could be used to achieve any necessary disciplinary or denunciation effect on individual miscreants.[328]

The Australian position presents a marked contrast between doctrine and practice. The High Court has not explored the issue,[329] but its analysis in Mengel of the tort’s structure and principles proceeded on the premise that ‘ordinarily’, individual misfeasance tortfeasors would receive no indemnity or contribution from their employing authorities.[330] One must doubt, however, whether that accurately describes the position. There are no official figures, but as far as I am aware, governments have always borne the defence costs in misfeasance claims, and have also paid the bills in those few cases which they have settled or lost. Indeed, it would be surprising if the position were otherwise. Few (if any) public servants would have professional indemnity insurance, and one might doubt whether professional indemnity insurance would protect against misfeasance. If the financial burden of misfeasance liability were indeed ‘ordinarily’ to remain with the individual, the larger claims of recent times would never have been brought. Billions of pounds were claimed in Three Rivers. More recently, the Australian government settled two individual claims and a related class action regarding the misfeasance of its pharmaceuticals regulator for a total of roughly $127 500 000.[331] Those Australian settlements appear to have conformed to the Government’s published guidelines, which basically offer the prospect of complete indemnities for public servants who act responsibly, and without ‘serious or wilful misconduct or culpable negligence’.[332]

There appears to be a similar gap between doctrine and practice in the case of police torts. All Australian governments bear sole responsibility to plaintiffs who sue for police torts but, with the exception of the Commonwealth, the police must have been acting honestly or in good faith.[333] In practice, however, governments appear to have conceded vicarious liability for police torts even in circumstances where they might have been able to establish bad faith on the part of individual police officers.[334] Perhaps the police associations have wrung this concession from their governments but if so, it would appear to be no more than the concessions wrung by the broader union movement from employers more than a generation earlier. In the mid 1950s, Lister v Romford Ice & Cold Storage Ltd (‘Lister’)[335] had allowed an employer, whose tort liability to the plaintiff was wholly vicarious, to seek a full indemnity from its employed tortfeasor. However, legislation in some places has overturned Lister on the proviso that the employee was not guilty of serious or wilful misconduct.[336] On the same proviso, Australian insurers have no right of subrogation to an employer’s rights against its employee.[337] Whilst gaps clearly remain, it appears that governments are cautious about exploiting them.

These matters are mentioned here not to question the obvious (albeit complex) interdependence of tort and insurance, but to challenge Mengel’s assertion that things are (or should be) different for misfeasance — that individual defendants are (or should) ‘ordinarily’ be unable to obtain indemnities from their governments. It is submitted that the assertion is not just descriptively dubious, but also normatively dubious. Back in 1963, the Privy Council said, in effect, that the misfeasance tort was one part of the judiciary’s answer (along with an expansion of judicial review) to the growth of the administrative state.[338] If that is right, then the tort is more about holding the state to account than its individual officers, and if that last proposition is right, then the independent discretion rule should have no place in the tort’s operation. If misfeasance is a public tort, its damages should come from the public purse.

XIV SUGGESTIONS

Articles commonly start with introductions and end with conclusions, but in the case of misfeasance, ‘conclusions’ might be misleading; the cases have too many loose ends. What follows is a list of suggestions, some more tentative than others, as to how some of the larger issues should be resolved.

This article has not touched on what is perhaps the largest issue, which is whether it might be best to stop calling misfeasance a tort. It would certainly be an attractive law reform option to introduce greater flexibility into the assessment of damages. Small sums could be available for ‘vindicatory’ purposes where the plaintiffs are secondary or more remote victims and their losses are purely economic, and even then, perhaps only where the state has failed to undertake genuine disciplinary and remedial action of its own.[339] Reform along those lines would need to be achieved by legislation, but it would be a risky venture in the current political climate. It could end up granting public authorities the same protections from their primary victims as from their secondary victims, and even apply equally to claims for personal injury and pure economic loss.

On the assumption that misfeasance remains as a tort, one must then ask whether it should continue to be a purely public law tort, available only against public actors. Misfeasance responds to malice, but only when that comes from public actors, the underlying rationale being that public actors are different from private actors, as indeed they usually are. Destructive motivations towards competitors are regarded as an inherent part of a free market, and the common law has left their regulation to the legislature. However, it is going too far to say that only public actors need to put their personal feelings to one side, because that fails to consider the position of trustees who must also act altruistically. It would nevertheless be a non sequitur to say that one should therefore attempt a merger of the rules for the pecuniary liability of trustees and public officials. In the absence of evidence that trustee liability is radically dysfunctional, the real issue is not whether trustees and public actors must both act altruistically, but the sufficiency of the sanctions against public actors who behave maliciously. Whilst public actors are subject to judicial review and the regular torts, and to a range of disciplinary measures that are not court-based, misfeasance performs valuable compensatory and punitive functions beyond the capacity of other remedies. In virtually all of the cases considered in this article, judicial review would have been a meaningless remedy from the plaintiffs’ perspective because they had already suffered irreparable damage. Furthermore, it seems highly likely that the individual tortfeasors in most cases were not subjected to internal disciplinary measures. Ultimately, public power is exercised in our name, and without misfeasance liability, public actors (and their governments) would get away with its deliberate abuse to inflict loss that they know is wrong. Misfeasance therefore has a good claim to existence as a public law tort.

It is suggested that two consequences should flow from an unequivocal acceptance of misfeasance as a public tort. First, there can be no excuse for denying government’s vicarious liability for the misfeasance torts of its officials. Indeed, one could make good policy arguments for legislative intervention to impose liability solely upon the government except in the case of harm caused deliberately with knowing illegality and for reasons personal to the individual tortfeasor. The state’s vicarious liability is needed to make the tort meaningful. The common law’s independent discretion rule currently stands in the way of vicarious liability in most places in Australia, but it is a rule that seems not to have been applied in practice in misfeasance cases, and is in any event ripe for repeal in those jurisdictions where that step remains to be taken.

The second consequence flowing from the tort’s public law status is perhaps more controversial, but it is nevertheless suggested that the tort should apply as much to government contractors who abuse public power as it does to those who are on the full-time public payroll. The essence of misfeasance is surely that it is a deliberate abuse of public power, and it should be no excuse that a particular defendant is not subject to the internal disciplinary processes of the public service. If anything, that should be seen as an argument for liability, because there are fewer alternative remedies against the contractor.

Further, there can be no plausible defence of some of the fine distinctions between public servants who are or are not ‘holders’ of ‘public office’. Those distinctions open up a gap between public power and tort responsibility for its deliberate abuse that may have been justifiable in the days when holding office was a way of making money. Such days have gone, as should the distinctions which went with them in this context. There is a legitimate concern to avoid imposing liability on low-level public servants who simply cannot be expected to know the law, but the tort’s mental elements provide adequate protection. Low-level public servants who do not know the legal limits to their power will be liable only if they were reckless in consciously adverting to the risk of illegality and then deciding not to care about that issue. There will be very few low-level public actors who consciously advert to such a risk, and even fewer whose decision not to care could be described as reckless.

Misfeasance is designed to redress deliberate abuse of ‘public power’, but the cases are in some disarray as to how that might be defined. The tort clearly extends to wilful refusals to perform public duties, but there is an issue as to whether it extends (and if so, how far) beyond the sorts of powers and duties that are judicially reviewable. It is suggested that the tort must travel beyond the reach of judicial review — it can be a useful supplement to judicial review, but that should not be its defining feature. Like its criminal law forebear, the misfeasance tort should apply to abuses of public power[340] or position. There can be no difference between an elected local government authority that adversely rezones land to get back at its political rivals, and the same authority that determines its leases to those rivals for the same reason.

The great majority of the modern cases have focused their attention on the tort’s requisite mental elements, but even in that area, some issues need clarification. The cases have now relaxed the original requirements of deliberate illegality and deliberate harm, introducing the lesser alternative of reckless indifference provided that it, too, was deliberate. The minimum requirement of subjective indifference applies in most places as much to the prospect of harm as to the risk that the action taken will be illegal. However, Australia currently favours plaintiffs in requiring conscious indifference to the illegality issue but not to the prospect of harm, which need only be foreseeable. It is suggested that there is no sound argument for maintaining different mental elements for the illegality and harm components. As an intentional tort, misfeasance should set equally demanding fault standards at both points. Fault might occasionally be negated, however, where defendants bend the rules at the plaintiffs’ request.

The cases have yet to decide whether defendants who are guilty of targeted malice should escape liability if they neither knew nor subjectively suspected that they were breaking the law. It is suggested that there should be no misfeasance liability in such cases. A subjective intent to inflict loss is part of the job description for some public officers (police and the managers of immigration detention centres are the most obvious examples), and there is no good reason to make them assume the risk of accidental illegality. I am aware that this entails the prospect of Minister Duplessis defeating a misfeasance claim if Mr Roncarelli were to sue him today, but only if the court were to believe that Minister Duplessis neither knew nor suspected his want of lawful power. Defendants who intentionally harm their plaintiffs should bear at least an evidential burden of proof.

Finally, it is reasonably clear that if misfeasance vindicates ‘rights’, they are rights in only the loosest sense of the term — the political right to be free of deliberate abuse of public power. That admittedly raises difficulties for a tort that has forsworn some of the constraints so well-known to negligence law — limits designed to avoid the risk of indeterminate liability to an indeterminate number of plaintiffs for purely economic loss. The only protection from that risk that this article has identified lies in the requirement that where liability is premised on conscious indifference, that indifference must also be reckless. A requirement of recklessness has elements that are both objective and subjective.


[*] BJuris, LLB (Monash), DPhil (Oxon); Emeritus Professor, Faculty of Law, The University of New South Wales. I am grateful for the advice and assistance I received from Roderick Bagshaw, John Basten, Erika Chamberlain, Jim Davis, Matthew Groves, Carol Harlow, Susanna Khouri, Keith Mason, Martin Matthews, David Mullan, Jason Neyers, Robert Stevens, Prue Vines, Greg Weeks, Lucia Zedner, and the Melbourne University Law Review’s anonymous referees. My thanks go also to Corpus Christi College, Oxford, for generously providing me with a Visiting Fellowship for a term, during which I was able to write the bulk of this article.

[1] Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; (1998) 192 CLR 330, 376 [124] (Gummow J); Robert J Sadler, ‘Liability for Misfeasance in a Public Office’ [1992] SydLawRw 13; (1992) 14 Sydney Law Review 137, 138–9.

[2] The tort of misfeasance is therefore an exception to a fundamental Diceyan principle of holding government to the same standard of liability as applies to private individuals: see A V Dicey, Lectures Introductory to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (Macmillan, 1885) 178–9,

200–1. The principle is necessarily aspirational, because ‘perfect equality is not attainable’: Graham Barclay Oysters Pty Ltd v Ryan [2002] HCA 54; (2002) 211 CLR 540, 556 [12] (Gleeson CJ).

[3] Three Rivers District Council v Bank of England [No 3] [2003] 2 AC 1, 235 (Lord Millett).

[4] Ibid 229 (Lord Hobhouse); R v Secretary of State for Transport; Ex parte Factortame Ltd [No 2] (1990) UKHL 13; [1991] 1 AC 603, 672 (Lord Goff); X (Minors) v Bedfordshire County Council [1995] UKHL 9; [1995] 2 AC 633, 730 (Lord Browne-Wilkinson).

[5] See, eg, Maurice Sunkin, ‘Remedies Available in Judicial Review Proceedings’ in David Feldman (ed), English Public Law (Oxford University Press, 2004) 915, 949 (citations omitted): ‘The absence of a right of damages for losses sustained as a consequence of public law wrongs is widely recognized as being one of the most serious of the remaining gaps in our remedial system. It is a gap that does not exist in more developed systems.’ In the second edition, Sunkin added that ‘[t]his gap has been widely criticised over the years by judges, by legal commentators, and by the Law Commission. This is an issue that now cries out for reform’: Maurice Sunkin, ‘Remedies Available in Judicial Review Proceedings’ in David Feldman (ed), English Public Law (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed, 2009) 793, 820 (citations omitted).

[6] The prominent report of the Justice–All Souls Review Committee, Administrative Justice: Some Necessary Reforms (Oxford University Press, 1988), proposed legislative reform with no general limits. See also Law Commission, ‘Administrative Redress: Public Bodies and the Citizen’ (Consultation Paper No 187, 2008) 58–60 [4.27]–[4.30] for references to other criticisms of the limited availability of damages when administrative authorities act invalidly.

[7] All recent legislative interventions in Australia have restricted the common law liability of public authorities: see Mark Aronson, ‘Government Liability in Negligence’ [2008] MelbULawRw 2; (2008) 32 Melbourne University Law Review 44.

[8] See, eg, Human Rights Act 1998 (UK) c 42, s 8(3)(b), where no award of damages is to be made unless the court considers that the award is necessary to afford ‘just satisfaction’ to the claimant.

[9] Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; (1998) 192 CLR 330, 376 [124] (Gummow J).

[10] This question potentially has great significance and may potentially broaden the tort’s scope. For example, the Australian government has outsourced the assessment of some claims for asylum: Plaintiff M61/2010E v Commonwealth [2010] HCA 41; (2010) 272 ALR 14. In that case, the High Court left open the question of whether a party identified as an independent contractor was an officer of the Commonwealth for the purposes of judicial review: at 26 [51] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).

[11] (1995) 185 CLR 307.

[12] [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332. The facts given here are taken from the pleadings, the jury’s answers to a number of specific questions, and the Court of Appeal’s inferences drawn from the way that the plaintiff’s counsel had conducted the claim. Further, the constable was taken to have raped the plaintiff, although he was never brought to trial since he had left the country.

[13] [2003] 2 AC 1.

[14] Ibid 192 (Lord Steyn), 229–30 (Lord Hobhouse), 235 (Lord Millett), 267 (Lord Hutton).

[15] [2003] 3 SCR 263.

[16] Ibid 282, 289 (Iacobucci J for McLachlin CJ, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ).

[17] Ibid 285–6.

[18] (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253; [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126. It is generally acknowledged that various reports of the case (including three by Holt CJ himself), and of its aftermath in the House of Commons and the House of Lords, are patchy: Watkins v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2006] 2 AC 395, 416 [52] (Lord Rodger); Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 356 n 292 (Brennan J). The report of Ashby in Smith’s Leading Cases also includes accompanying notes at the end of the judgment. This appears to be the favoured report in the UK: Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 (Lord Steyn); Watkins v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2006] 2 AC 395, 416 [52] (Lord Rodger). In comparison, the High Court of Australia usually uses Lord Raymond’s report: see, eg, Dorman v Rogers [1982] HCA 25; (1982) 148 CLR 365, 374 n 40 (Murphy J); Dietrich v The Queen [1992] HCA 57; (1992) 177 CLR 292, 324 n 17 (Brennan J), 356 n 16 (Toohey J); Grollo v Palmer [1995] HCA 26; (1995) 184 CLR 348, 366 n 74 (Brennan CJ, Deane, Dawson and Toohey JJ); Langer v Commonwealth [1996] HCA 43; (1996) 186 CLR 302, 350 n 94 (Gummow J); Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 356 n 290 (Brennan J).

[19] Most accounts of the misfeasance tort start with Holt CJ’s judgment, although it has also been traced to common law cases on the liability of judicial officers in inferior courts: R P Balkin and J L R Davis, Law of Torts (LexisNexis Butterworths, 4th ed, 2009) 705. The liability of judicial officers certainly figured prominently in some of the judgments in Ashby itself: (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 941 (Gould J), 943 (Powys J), 946–7 (Powell J), 950 (Holt CJ); 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 257–8 (Gould J), 259 (Powys J), 264 (Powell J), 268 (Holt CJ); [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126, 129 (Gould J), 129–30 (Powys J), 132 (Powell J), 134 (Holt CJ). Lord Steyn in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 189–90 also relied on Turner v Sterling [1726] EngR 585; (1671) 2 Vent 25; 86 ER 287, which had allowed a claim that the defendant had maliciously refused to accept the result of a vote for installing the plaintiff to a vacancy in the remunerated office of a London bridgemaster. Lord Steyn, however, went on to say that it was Ashby that provided ‘the first solid basis for this new head of tort liability’: Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190.

[20] The Ashby case is an important part of English constitutional history. Ashby and a number of other voting cases sparked ‘one of the most furious controversies between the Houses of Lords and Commons of which there is any example in English history’: Ashby (1703) 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 281. The plaintiffs and most of their lawyers were arrested on warrants from the Speaker. The House of Commons believed that the matter was within its sole jurisdiction. One lawyer escaped, using sheets and a rope to climb down from a rear window in his second floor chambers in the Temple. The dispute between the two Houses came to an end only with the prorogation of the Parliament: at 282. Ashby was a poor cobbler backed by the Whigs, while the Tories backed the constables: Watkins v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2006] 2 AC 395, 416 [51]–[53] (Lord Rodger), citing Eveline Cruickshanks, ‘Ashby v White: The Case of the Men of Aylesbury 1701–4’ in Clyve Jones (ed), Party and Management in Parliament, 1660–1784 (Leicester University Press, 1984) 87.

[21] Ashby (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 956; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 276; [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126, 167.

[22] Ibid 957; 277; 138.

[23] See below Part VII.

[24] [2006] 2 AC 395.

[25] Ibid 408–9 [26] (Lord Bingham), 421–2 [68] (Lord Walker). Cf de Montigny v Brossard (Succession) [2010] 3 SCR 64, 86–7 [45]–[46] (LeBel J), upholding the availability of punitive damages, in the absence of material loss, for breaches of the Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms, RSQ 1975, c C-12.

[26] Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 403 [8].

[27] (1998) 196 CLR 329.

[28] Ibid 344 [37] (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, Kirby and Hayne JJ).

[29] Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 403 [9] (Lord Bingham). Cf Carol Harlow, ‘A Punitive Role for Tort Law?’ in Linda Pearson, Carol Harlow and Michael Taggart (eds), Administrative Law in a Changing State: Essays in Honour of Mark Aronson (Hart Publishing, 2008) 247.

[30] Lord Millett said in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 292 [188] that misfeasance was not made out by proof of ‘honest incompetence’ or ‘gross negligence’. Gummow J said in Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; (1998) 192 CLR 330, 376 [124] that misfeasance ‘concerns conscious maladministration rather than careless administration’. Further, the English Court of Appeal upheld the defence of honest but gross incompetence in Muuse v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2010] EWCA Civ 453 (27 April 2010).

[31] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 358 (Brennan J); Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 350 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ); Sanders v Snell (1998) 196 CLR 329, 344 [37] (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, Kirby and Hayne JJ). Lord Steyn added in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 196 that one should avoid a liability rule that would see public officers being ‘assailed by unmeritorious actions’, but this begs the question as to when an action would be unmeritorious.

[32] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ). For further discussion on this point, see below Part XIII.

[33] Cf Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; (1998) 192 CLR 330, 376 [124], where Gummow J said that the tort’s roots lay within public law.

[34] The proposition first appeared in the fourth edition of H W R Wade, Administrative Law (Clarendon Press, 4th ed, 1977) 340–1, and had become classic by the time it appeared substantively unaltered in Sir William Wade and Christopher Forsyth, Administrative Law (Oxford University Press, 10th ed, 2009) 296–7.

[35] Lionel Smith, ‘The Motive, Not the Deed’ in Joshua Getzler (ed), Rationalizing Property, Equity and Trusts: Essays in Honour of Edward Burn (LexisNexis, 2003) 53, 67.

[36] P D Finn, Fiduciary Obligations (Law Book, 1977) 15.

[37] [2003] 2 AC 1, 235–6.

[38] See, eg, Jones v Swansea City Council [1990] 1 WLR 54, 71 (Slade LJ); Sanders v Snell [No 2] [2003] FCAFC 150; (2003) 130 FCR 149, 172 [89] (Black CJ, French and von Doussa JJ).

[39] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 348 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).

[40] Sanders v Snell (1998) 196 CLR 329, 344–6 [36]–[39] (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, Kirby and Hayne JJ).

[41] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 359.

[42] Lord Steyn said in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 that misfeasance needed to fit within the ‘general scheme of the law of tort’, in order to ensure the ‘coherent development of the law’.

[43] See also Erika Chamberlain, ‘Misfeasance in a Public Office: A Justifiable Anomaly within the Rights-Based Approach?’ in Donal Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds), Rights and Private Law (Hart Publishing, 2011) (forthcoming).

[44] See, eg, Puntoriero v Water Administration Ministerial Corporation [1999] HCA 45; (1999) 199 CLR 575. In comparison, statutes protecting officials who acted unlawfully but in good faith used to be extremely common in England, but electronic searches suggest that they might now be less common. They remain standard drafting policy in Australia. The Policing and Crime Act 2009 (UK) c 26, s 136N is probably unique. It applies to all police acting in good faith in the performance or purported performance of their functions relating to the enforcement of orders to close certain premises. The section provides that no police or police force shall be liable in damages ‘in proceedings for judicial review or for the tort of negligence or misfeasance in public office’.

[45] See Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 356 n 292 (Brennan J), adopting the view expressed in Ashby (1703) 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 283. The New Zealand Court of Appeal agreed with Brennan J: Rawlinson v Rice [1998] 1 NZLR 454, 458 (Gault J for Richardson P, Gault, Thomas, Keith and Tipping JJ). In Tozer v Child, Campbell CJ interpreted Ashby as treating malice as an essential element of actionability: [1856] EngR 450; (1856) 6 El & Bl 289, 295; [1856] EngR 450; 119 ER 872, 875 (Lord Campbell CJ for Lord Campbell CJ, Wightman, Erle and Crompton LJJ).

[46] Ashby (1703) 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 283.

[47] Cf Bradford Corporation v Pickles [1895] AC 587, 601, where Lord Macnaghten could see no malice in Mr Pickles’ conduct, even if it was ‘churlish, selfish and grasping’, or morally ‘shocking’. Mr Pickles had diverted underground water flowing in no defined course through his land from entering the city’s water catchment, presumably to drive a hard bargain against the Bradford Water Corporation. For a book-length case study, see Michael Taggart, Private Property and Abuse of Rights in Victorian England: The Story of Edward Pickles and the Bradford Water Supply (Oxford University Press, 2002). Taggart was unsure about heaping all of the criticisms upon Mr Pickles, noting that the Town Clerk had also been quite intransigent — the Bradford Corporation had not taken any of the opportunities presented to it to purchase the land or the water rights: at 72.

[48] O’Brien v Dawson [1942] HCA 8; (1942) 66 CLR 18, 28 (Starke J).

[49] See Bradford Corporation v Pickles [1895] AC 587, 594 (Lord Halsbury LC), 598–9 (Lord Ashbourne), 601 (Lord Macnaghten); Allen v Flood [1897] UKLawRpAC 56; [1898] AC 1, 92 (Lord Watson), 152–3 (Lord Macnaghten); McKernan v Fraser [1931] HCA 54; (1931) 46 CLR 343, 380 (Evatt J); Crofter Hand Woven Harris Tweed Co Ltd v Veitch [1941] UKHL 2; [1942] AC 435, 442 (Viscount Simon LC); O’Brien v Dawson [1942] HCA 8; (1942) 66 CLR 18, 28 (Starke J); Sanders v Snell (1998) 196 CLR 329, 342 [32] (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, Kirby and Hayne JJ); Perre v Apand Pty Ltd [1999] HCA 36; (1999) 198 CLR 180, 306 [347] (Hayne J); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 (Lord Steyn); OBG Ltd v Allan [2007] UKHL 21; [2008] 1 AC 1, 22 [13] (Lord Hoffmann).

[50] Discretionary functions were usually labelled judicial or quasi-judicial. Non-discretionary functions (ie duties to act, as opposed to duties to consider how to act) were usually labelled ministerial.

[51] See S A de Smith, Judicial Review of Administrative Action (Stevens & Sons, 1959) 201, quoting Everett v Griffiths [1921] 1 AC 631, 695 (Lord Moulton).

[52] See John W Salmond, The Law of Torts (Stevens and Haynes, 2nd ed, 1910) 478–80; J F Clerk and W H B Lindsell, The Law of Torts (Sweet & Maxwell, 6th ed, 1912) ch 22; Mark Aronson and Harry Whitmore, Public Torts and Contracts (Law Book, 1982) 138–47. The propositions in the text are stated with some diffidence. This corner of the law was never neat, and the leading cases struggled to accommodate several principles that pulled in different directions, some dealing with the provision of damages for breach of duty, or for breach of statutory duty, and others dealing with exceptions in relation to discretionary or judicial duties. Retreat from a generalised right of action for breach of duty was inevitable in the face of the welter of statutory duties being imposed upon both private and public actors: see P D Finn, ‘Public Officers: Some Personal Liabilities’ (1977) 51 Australian Law Journal 313; P D Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken: The Boyce Plaintiff and Lord Cairns’ Act (Part 1)’ (1983) 57 Australian Law Journal 493; P D Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken: The Boyce Plaintiff and Lord Cairns’ Act (Part 2)’ (1983) 57 Australian Law Journal 571.

[53] Sirros v Moore [1975] QB 118, 135 (Lord Denning MR); Maharaj v A-G (Trinidad and Tobago) [No 2] [1978] UKPC 3; [1979] AC 385, 404 (Lord Hailsham); Re McC (A Minor) [1985] 1 AC 528, 559 (Lord Templeman); A-G (NSW) v Agarsky (1986) 6 NSWLR 38, 40 (Kirby P); Rajski v Powell (1987) 11 NSWLR 522, 527–30 (Kirby P); Fingleton v The Queen [2005] HCA 34; (2005) 227 CLR 166, 184–7 (Gleeson CJ), 214 (Kirby J).

[54] See Everett v Griffiths [1921] 1 AC 631.

[55] Brennan J put these issues aside in Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355–6. Member states of the European Union (but not their individual officers) are liable when their supreme courts commit manifest and inexcusable breaches of European Union law: Köbler v Republik Österreich

(C-224/01) [2004] ECR I-10290.

[56] See, eg, Judicial Officers Act 1986 (NSW) s 44A, granting all judicial officers the same ‘protection and immunity’ afforded to Supreme Court judges; Courts Act 2003 (UK) c 39, s 32(1), providing that actions lie against justices of the peace acting beyond or without jurisdiction only on proof of bad faith. The legislation in New South Wales has taken care to include protection for conduct in the performance of ‘ministerial duties’: Judicial Officers Act 1986 (NSW) ss 44A44C. Statutory protection for inferior court judicial officers formerly depended on whether they had acted in good faith: see Constables Protection Act 1750 (Imp) 24 Geo 2, c 44, s 6; Justices Protection Act 1848 (Imp) 11 & 12 Vict, c 44.

[57] See below n 333.

[58] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190.

[59] Ibid 191.

[60] Ibid 190.

[61] L H Hoffmann, ‘Rookes v Barnard(1965) 81 Law Quarterly Review 116, 138.

[62] Ibid 140–1. Lord Devlin entertained a similar possibility in Rookes v Barnard [1964] UKHL 1; [1964] AC 1129, 1215–16.

[63] For a discussion of this doctrine, see Taggart, above n 47, 145–9.

[64] The unsatisfactory tort of conspiracy by lawful means was left untouched: see Roderick Bagshaw, ‘Can the Economic Torts Be Unified?’ (1998) 18 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 729, 731.

[65] OBG Ltd v Allan [2007] UKHL 21; [2008] 1 AC 1, 22 [14], 34 [56] (Lord Hoffmann). Lord Nicholls thought that these were complex issues best left to statute, the competition regulators and the industrial relations regulators: at 54–5 [148]. Australia had rejected the prima facie tort option a few years earlier: Sanders v Snell (1998) 196 CLR 329, 342 [32] (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, Kirby and Hayne JJ); Perre v Apand Pty Ltd [1999] HCA 36; (1999) 198 CLR 180, 306 (Hayne J); Zhu v Treasurer (NSW) [2004] HCA 56; (2004) 218 CLR 530, 566 [105], 570–1 [114]–[118] (Gleeson CJ, Gummow, Kirby, Callinan and Heydon JJ). A prima facie tort theory presumes the tortiousness of harms caused deliberately or maliciously unless the defendants can persuade the court that their conduct was justified.

[66] See below Part VI.

[67] Ashby (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 956; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 276; [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126, 137.

[68] Measured in terms of average wages, the Bank of England’s rough estimate was that £200 in 1694 (when the Bank was founded) equated to £80 000 in 1994: Helen MacFarlane and Paul Mortimer-Lee, ‘Inflation over 300 Years’ (1994) 34 Bank of England Quarterly Bulletin 156, 158–62 <http://www.bankofengland.co.uk/publications/quarterlybulletin/qb940201.pdf> . If from the £80 000 in 1994 one then uses the index for average weekly earnings in the Bank’s quarterly Inflation Reports (published since 1993), the overall result is that £200 in 1694 equated to roughly £148 500 by the end of January 2011.

[69] As if regulators, tribunals and administrative agencies need not be considered. Gleeson CJ, McHugh, Gummow and Hayne JJ said in Gray v Motor Accident Commission [1998] HCA 70; (1998) 196 CLR 1, 7–8 [16] that the old intermingling of criminal and civil law has proceeded apace in recent times with statutory schemes for criminal injury compensation and civil penalties. Tribunals and regulatory agencies typically administer such schemes, although appeals and judicial review are administered by the superior courts.

[70] See Harlow, above n 29, 247. See also P S Atiyah, ‘Personal Injuries in the Twenty First Century: Thinking the Unthinkable’ in Peter Birks (ed), Wrongs and Remedies in the Twenty-First Century (Clarendon Press, 1996) 1; Andrew Burrows, ‘Reforming Exemplary Damages: Expansion or Abolition?’ in Peter Birks (ed), Wrongs and Remedies in the Twenty-First Century (Clarendon Press, 1996) 153; Peter Cane, ‘Exceptional Measures of Damages: A Search for Principles’ in Peter Birks (ed), Wrongs and Remedies in the Twenty-First Century (Clarendon Press, 1996) 301.

[71] See Harlow, above n 29, 249–71.

[72] [2008] UKHL 25; [2008] 1 AC 962.

[73] Ibid 976 [23] (Lord Scott). Lord Scott also said that the assault and battery claim was legitimately rights-centred, not loss-centred: at 975–6 [22]. Lumba v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2011] UKSC 12; [2011] 2 WLR 671 held by majority that there should be no separate measure of ‘vindicatory’ or ‘conventional’ damages that were not nominal, compensatory or exemplary: at 702 [101] (Lord Dyson SCJ), 739 [237] (Lord Collins SCJ).

[74] Kuddus v Chief Constable of Leicestershire Constabulary [2001] UKHL 29; [2002] 2 AC 122, 134–5 [21]–[27] (Lord Slynn), 145 [68] (Lord Nicholls), 153 [89] (Lord Hutton) (‘Kuddus’).

[75] Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 408–9 [26] (Lord Bingham). New Zealand does not require material damage: Donselaar v Donselaar [1982] NZCA 13; [1982] 1 NZLR 97, 109 (Richardson J), 115 (Somers J).

[76] Fernando v Commonwealth [No 4] [2010] FCA 1475; (2010) 276 ALR 586 is an exception.

[77] Giving the leading judgment in Rookes v Barnard [1964] UKHL 1; [1964] AC 1129, Lord Devlin conceded the possibility of exemplary damages in only three situations, one of which was where legislation makes specific provision for it. He also stated that there were two categories of cases in which an award of exemplary damages can afford ‘a practical justification for admitting into the civil law a principle which ought logically to belong to the criminal’: at 1226. His first general law category comprised cases of ‘oppressive, arbitrary or unconstitutional action by the servants of the government’: at 1226. No-one has taken that category as restricted to people directly engaged in the civil service, or even to people working only for central government. His second general law category was for cases where defendants (whether public or private) have cynically calculated on making a net profit from their wrongdoing after allowing for anything they may be legally obliged to pay the plaintiff by way of compensation: at 1226–7. The subsequent development in England of restitutionary principles has diminished the force of the second category. See also Broome v Cassell & Co Ltd [1972] UKHL 3; [1972] AC 1027. The Law Commission could not enlist sufficient support for its proposal to abolish exemplary damages, and ended up recommending not abolition, but legislative reform: Law Commission, Aggravated, Exemplary and Restitutionary Damages, Report No 247 (1997). No legislation followed.

[78] See Uren v John Fairfax & Sons Pty Ltd [1966] HCA 40; (1966) 117 CLR 118; XL Petroleum (NSW) Pty Ltd v Caltex Oil (Australia) Pty Ltd [1985] HCA 12; (1985) 155 CLR 448; Lamb v Cotogno [1987] HCA 47; (1987) 164 CLR 1; Gray v Motor Accident Commission [1998] HCA 70; (1998) 196 CLR 1, 12–13 [32]–[37] (Gleeson CJ, McHugh, Gummow and Hayne JJ); Whitbread v Rail Corporation New South Wales [2011] NSWCA 130 (24 May 2011) [20] (McColl JA), [232] (Whealy JA). A relatively recent Australian attempt to add punitive damages to equity’s remedies (or at least, to its remedies for breach of fiduciary duty) was rebuffed with extraordinary hostility and an emphatic insistence that punishment be awarded only by the criminal courts: Harris v Digital Pulse Pty Ltd [2003] NSWCA 10; (2003) 56 NSWLR 298, 390 [351]–[352] (Heydon JA). This article will not discuss the considerable number of legislative provisions in Australia for regulating the award of exemplary damages. It must suffice to mention that all jurisdictions have banned them in defamation actions: see, eg, Defamation Act 2005 (NSW) s 37. Some jurisdictions have banned them in negligence claims for personal injury or death: see, eg, Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW) s 21; cf Wrongs Act 1958 (Vic) s 24AP(d). Some have come to the relief of motor vehicle insurers but not their insured drivers: see, eg, Motor Vehicles Act 1959 (SA) s 113A.

[79] See Taylor v Beere [1982] NZCA 15; [1982] 1 NZLR 81, 89–91 (Richardson J). New Zealand’s position has wavered since then. First, it allowed stand-alone exemplary damages to get around legislative abolition of compensatory damages: Donselaar v Donselaar [1982] NZCA 13; [1982] 1 NZLR 97, 107 (Cooke J), 116 (Somers J). Secondly, it restricted exemplary damages to cases where the defendant had acted either deliberately or with subjective recklessness: Bottrill v A [2001] 3 NZLR 622, 642 [63] (Richardson P for Richardson P, Gault and Blanchard JJ). Thirdly, the Privy Council reversed the latter decision: Bottrill v A [2003] 2 NZLR 721. Fourthly, the Supreme Court recently overturned the Privy Council decision: Couch v A-G (NZ) [No 2] [2010] NZSC 27; [2010] 3 NZLR 149.

[80] See Vorvis v Insurance Corporation of British Columbia [1989] 1 SCR 1085, 1107–8 [27] (McIntyre J for Beetz, McIntyre and Lamer JJ); Whiten v Pilot Insurance Co [2002] 1 SCR 595, 613 [36], 635 [69] (Binnie J for McLachlin CJ, L’Heureux-Dubé, Gonthier, Major, Binnie and Arbour JJ).

[81] Rookes v Barnard [1964] UKHL 1; [1964] AC 1129, 1226.

[82] See Kuddus [2001] UKHL 29; [2002] 2 AC 122, 145 (Lord Nicholls).

[83] Uren v John Fairfax & Sons Pty Ltd [1966] HCA 40; (1966) 117 CLR 118, 132–3 (Taylor J), 160 (Owen J).

[84] Peter Birks (ed), Wrongs and Remedies in the Twenty-First Century (Clarendon Press, 1996) viii. Another factor might well be the re-emergence of classical economic assumptions as to the causes of crime and the ways it may be managed: see Lucia Zedner, ‘Policing before and after the Police: The Historical Antecedents of Contemporary Crime Control’ (2006) 46 British Journal of Criminology 78.

[85] See Burrows, above n 70, 168–9.

[86] Kuddus [2001] UKHL 29; [2002] 2 AC 122, 144–5 (Lord Nicholls), 147–9 (Lord Hutton).

[87] Watkins [2006] AC 395, 408–9 (Lord Bingham) insisted that misfeasance in public office was actionable only by plaintiffs who had sustained material loss, even if their defendants had breached a ‘constitutional’ protection. One of Lord Bingham’s reasons was that the offending officers could be prosecuted for the indictable misdemeanour of misconduct in public office. Lord Walker was sceptical: at 422 [69]. The defendants were prison officers who had flagrantly flouted a rule protecting a prisoner’s right of privacy for communications covered by legal professional privilege. Lord Scott’s position in Kuddus [2001] UKHL 29; [2002] 2 AC 122, 155–6 [104]–[107] was not as explicit as Lord Bingham’s in Watkins, but it came close.

[88] Whitbread v Rail Corporation New South Wales [2011] NSWCA 130 (24 May 2011) [242] (Whealy JA), citing Gray v Motor Accident Commission [1998] HCA 70; (1998) 196 CLR 1, 14 [40] (Gleeson CJ, McHugh, Gummow and Hayne JJ). Whitbread also held that the employer’s disciplinary action against its officer was another factor against awarding exemplary damages: at [252] (Whealy JA).

[89] The leading English work on the offence is Colin Nicholls et al, Corruption and Misuse of Public Office (Oxford University Press, 2006) ch 3. On page 66, that work traces the offence back at least as far as Crouther’s Case [1653] EngR 1860; (1600) Cro Eliz 654; 78 ER 893. Modern cases tend not to go further back than Lord Mansfield CJ’s judgment in R v Bembridge (1783) 3 Doug 327; 99 ER 679.

[90] Ashby (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 955; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 275; [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126, 137.

[91] Ibid. The stated reason was that the law needed to avoid a multiplicity of civil actions for the same event. The applicability of the representative (or class) action to the misfeasance claim in Three Rivers seems to have passed without comment.

[92] See Leon Radzinowicz, A History of English Criminal Law and Its Administration from 1750 (Stevens & Sons, 1956) vol 2, 138–47, 161–3. See also Downey v Acting District Court Judge Boulton [No 5] [2010] NSWCA 240; (2010) 272 ALR 705, 722 [67] (Basten JA).

[93] Zedner, above n 84.

[94] The Director of Public Prosecutions for England and Wales had urged codification in 2003, but both the Joint Committee and the government disagreed. See Joint Committee on the Draft Corruption Bill, Draft Corruption Bill: Report and Evidence (House of Lords Paper No 157/House of Commons Paper No 705, Session 2002–03, 2003) 19–20 [40]–[45], 28–30 [73]–[81]; Nicholls et al, above n 89, 93, 764–803. The Bill failed to pass, principally because it had sought to adapt ‘misconduct’ to a Corruption Bill built on a model of agent and principal, in which the essence of corruption was the agent’s disloyalty to the principal’s interests. The Bribery Act 2010 (UK) c 23 overcame that problem by abandoning the principal/agent structure in its definition of bribery, but it dealt with no other offences, and therefore left the misfeasance offence untouched.

[95] This is an amalgam drawn from R v Dytham [1979] QB 722; R v Bowden [1996] 1 WLR 98;

A-G’s Reference (No 3 of 2003) [2004] EWCA Crim 868; [2005] QB 73; Sin Kam Wah v Hong Kong Special Administrative Region [2005] HKCFA 29; [2005] 2 HKLRD 375; R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522; Nicholls et al, above n 89, 66–71.

[96] Sin Kam Wah v Hong Kong Special Administrative Region [2005] HKCFA 29; [2005] 2 HKLRD 375, 391 [45].

[97] A-G’s Reference (No 3 of 2003) [2004] EWCA Crim 868; [2005] QB 73, 90.

[98] See ibid 85; Nicholls et al, above n 89, 83–7; Sin Kam Wah v Hong Kong Special Administrative Region [2005] HKCFA 29; [2005] 2 HKLRD 375; R v Boulanger [2006] 2 SCR 49; R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522.

[99] For England, see P J Richardson (ed), Archbold 2010: Criminal Appeal Cases Index Second Cumulative Index to the 2010 Edition (Sweet & Maxwell, 2010) 58–9, citing A-G’s Reference (No 3 of 2003) [2004] EWCA Crim 868; [2005] QB 73. For Australia and Hong Kong, see Sin Kam Wah v Hong Kong Special Administrative Region [2005] HKCFA 29; [2005] 2 HKLRD 375; R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522. See also P D Finn, ‘Public Officers: Some Personal Liabilities’ (1977) 51 Australian Law Journal 313; Paul Finn, ‘Official Misconduct’ [1978] 2 Criminal Law Journal 307.

[100] The Criminal Code Act 1995 (Cth) s 142.2 makes it a criminal offence for Commonwealth public officials to misuse their powers either to benefit or to harm someone dishonestly. Section 359 of the Criminal Code 2002 (ACT) does the same. Western Australia’s offence is similar, except that it requires corruption, rather than dishonesty: The Criminal Code (WA) s 83. South Australia’s offence is narrower in that it contains the ‘benefit’ ingredient but no ‘harm’ alternative. It is wider in so far as the prohibited ‘benefit’ motivation need only be ‘improper’, which is defined very broadly. See Criminal Law Consolidation Act 1935 (SA) ss 238, 251; Question of Law Reserved (No 2 of 1996) [1996] SASC 5674; (1996) 67 SASR 63. Queensland has equivalents, but it also has an offence called ‘abuse of office’. Section 92 of the Criminal Code Act 1899 (Qld) makes it an offence for anyone employed in the public service to do anything in abuse of their authority that is an arbitrary act prejudicial to the ‘rights’ of another. The Northern Territory has the same offence of ‘abuse of office’: Criminal Code Act 1983 (NT) s 82.

[101] Speaking for the Canadian Supreme Court in R v Boulanger [2006] 2 SCR 49, 74, McLachlin CJ said that there had been two common law offences. The first offence was misfeasance, and it had required the accused to have acted ‘for a purpose other than the public good, for example, for a dishonest, partial, corrupt, or oppressive purpose’: at 73–4 [58]. The second offence (nonfeasance) related to advertent and very serious neglect of duty, and had no requirement as to motive: at 58 [19]. R v Boulanger held that Criminal Code, RSC 1985, c C-46, s 122 imported only the first offence, so that nonfeasance was no longer a general offence.

[102] See R v Caldwell [1982] UKHL 1; [1982] AC 341.

[103] Watkins [2006] 2 AC 295, 408–9 (Lord Bingham).

[104] See, eg, Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 191–3 (Lord Steyn), citing R v Bowden [1996] 1 WLR 98, R v Cunningham [1957] 2 QB 396, R v Caldwell [1982] UKHL 1; [1982] AC 341 and R v Lawrence [1982] AC 510.

[105] See, eg, A-G’s Reference (No 3 of 2003) [2004] EWCA Crim 868; [2005] QB 73, 88–90 (Pill LJ); R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522, 530 [28] (Redlich JA).

[106] [1982] UKHL 1; [1982] AC 341.

[107] Ibid 353–4 (Lord Diplock).

[108] [2003] 2 AC 1, 192–3.

[109] See R v G [2003] UKHL 50; [2004] 1 AC 1034.

[110] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 345 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 (Lord Steyn).

[111] See R v Caldwell [1982] UKHL 1; [1982] AC 341, 351–2 (Lord Diplock).

[112] Lord Halsbury, The Laws of England (Butterworth, 1912) vol 23, 316–18 [659].

[113] See below n 239.

[114] [1959] VicRp 49; [1959] VR 286.

[115] The lack of intention by the police to cause illegal harm should have been what mattered.

[116] [1959] VicRp 49; [1959] VR 286, 293. Little v Law Institute of Victoria [No 3] [1990] VicRp 25; [1990] VR 257, 270 (Kaye and Beach JJ) confirmed this extension of misfeasance.

[117] S A de Smith, Judicial Review of Administrative Action (Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed, 1968) 19, 319.

[118] Noting the first instance decision of Roncarelli v Duplessis [1952] 1 DLR 680, the first edition of H W R Wade, Administrative Law (Clarendon Press, 1961) 83 said that an English plaintiff would not have succeeded. The switch came in H W R Wade, Administrative Law (Clarendon Press, 4th ed, 1977) 636–40, which gave enthusiastic coverage to Farrington v Thomson [1959] VicRp 49; [1959] VR 286 and to Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121.

[119] Jeremy McBride, ‘Damages as a Remedy for Unlawful Administrative Action’ (1979) 38 Cambridge Law Journal 323, 343.

[120] Dunlop v Woollahra Municipal Council [1982] AC 158, 172 (Lord Diplock for Lords Diplock, Simon, Edmund-Davies, Scarman and Bridge).

[121] [1986] 1 QB 716.

[122] Ibid 776 (Oliver LJ).

[123] Ibid. Oliver LJ went on to say that ‘[i]f an act is done deliberately and with knowledge of its consequences, I do not think that the actor can sensibly say that he did not “intend” the consequences or that the act was not “aimed” at the person who, it is known, will suffer them’: at 777.

[124] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ), 359 (Brennan J); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 196 (Lord Steyn), 223 (Lord Hutton), 231 (Lord Hobhouse), 236 (Lord Millett); Odhavji [2003] 3 SCR 263, 283 (Iacobucci J for McLachlin CJ, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ); Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 349 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ).

[125] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 192–3 (Lord Steyn). Cf Ruddock v Taylor (2005) 222 CLR 612, 622–3 [28] (Gleeson CJ, Gummow, Hayne and Heydon JJ) (emphasis added), where the joint judgment wondered whether misfeasance might lie against a Minister who ‘knew or ought to have known’ that he or she was acting beyond power. It was a throwaway line that should not be taken seriously.

[126] Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 350 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 196 (Lord Steyn), 227–8 (Lord Hutton), 231 (Lord Hobhouse), 235–6 (Lord Millett).

[127] Rawlinson v Rice [1997] 2 NZLR 651, 658 (McKay J), 663 (Barker J), 665 (Tipping J); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 196 (Lord Steyn), 230–1 (Lord Hobhouse), 236 (Lord Millett); Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 413 [39] (Lord Bingham).

[128] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 196 (Lord Steyn), 223 (Lord Hutton), 231 (Lord Hobhouse), 236 (Lord Millett).

[129] Ibid 247 [46], 251 [60].

[130] See below Part X.

[131] Strictly speaking, Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307 did not accept that it would be sufficient to establish reckless indifference as to the lawful limits of a defendant’s power, because there was no such indifference on the facts of that case. That might explain the High Court’s subsequent reference to reckless indifference being an acceptable alternative in England: see Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Futuris Corporation Ltd (2008) 237 CLR 146, 153 [11] (Gummow, Hayne, Heydon and Crennan JJ).

[132] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).

[133] The ambiguities flow from the references to harm ‘calculated’ to flow from the defendant’s intentional acts: Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ), 357 (Brennan J). That language was borrowed from Wilkinson v Downton [1897] 2 QB 57, 59, where Wright J had treated an obvious risk of harm as having been intended by a defendant who had given it no thought. Lord Hoffmann rejected Wilkinson’s fictionalised intent in Wainwright v Home Office [2003] UKHL 53; [2004] 2 AC 406, 425. Cf Denise Réaume, ‘The Role of Intention in the Tort in Wilkinson v Downton’ in Jason W Neyers, Erika Chamberlain and Stephen G A Pitel (eds), Emerging Issues in Tort Law (Hart Publishing, 2007) 533, 533–56.

[134] South Australia v Lampard-Trevorrow [2010] SASC 56; (2010) 106 SASR 331, 387–8 [263]–[265] (Doyle CJ, Duggan and White JJ).

[135] Ibid 387–8 [263]–[264].

[136] See, eg, Muuse v Secretary of State for the Home Office [2010] EWCA Civ 453 (27 April 2010) [53] (Thomas LJ).

[137] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230–1, 286 [167].

[138] Ibid 192 (Lord Steyn), 223 (Lord Hutton); Odhavji [2003] 3 SCR 263, 281 [22] (Iacobucci J for McLachlin CJ, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ); Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 423 [73] (Lord Walker).

[139] This is a view that is almost always implicit. Deane J’s pithy summary in Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 370–1 probably comes the closest to an explicit affirmation of this view.

[140] See, eg, Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230 (Lord Hobhouse), 235 (Lord Millett). See also Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 407 [22] (Lord Bingham).

[141] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 357.

[142] [2003] 2 AC 1, 246 [41]–[42] (Lord Hope), 267 [121] (Lord Hutton), 289 [175] (Lord Hobhouse), 290–1 [179]–[182] (Lord Millett).

[143] Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Futuris Corporation Ltd (2008) 237 CLR 146, 153 [11] (Gummow, Hayne, Heydon and Crennan JJ).

[144] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 235.

[145] Ibid 235–6.

[146] Australian criminal trial judges, for example, have a discretion whether to exclude illegally obtained evidence proffered against the accused, even where the illegality was deliberate. See Bunning v Cross (1978) 141 CLR 54; Evidence Act 1995 (Cth) s 138.

[147] In Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, for example, the sergeant should surely have overridden the plaintiff’s objections and made a timely internal report of the police rape. Further, the criminal misfeasance offence applied to a policeman who had consensual sex with a woman he was meant to be protecting and who he knew to be in a particularly fragile state: R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522.

[148] Poynder v Kent [2008] VSCA 245 (4 December 2008) [119]–[126] (Osborn AJA). In comparison, the officers in Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307 knew that they would be inflicting loss on the plaintiffs, but they had believed that they were acting lawfully. See further the discussion of Mengel in Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 346 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ).

[149] Cf Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230, where Lord Hobhouse treated targeted malice as no more than an extremely good evidentiary basis for inferring that the defendant lacked an honest belief that he or she was acting lawfully.

[150] Debelle J’s decision in Rowan v Cornwall [No 5] [2002] SASC 160; (2002) 82 SASR 152, 357–62 appears to be inconsistent with the analysis in this paragraph. The defendant Minister was held liable for action intended to harm the plaintiff because that action was unlawful for having been taken in breach of natural justice and for improper purposes. The difficulty with Rowan is that the Minister had not known that he was acting illegally; nor had he been recklessly indifferent as to the limits of his lawful powers.

[151] Odhavji [2003] 3 SCR 263, 284–5 [28] (Iacobucci J for McLachlin CJ, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ).

[152] Sanders v Snell [No 2] [2003] FCAFC 150; (2003) 130 FCR 149, 177–8 [106]–[108] (Black CJ, French and von Doussa JJ).

[153] Goldie v Commonwealth (2002) 117 FCR 566, 586 [74] (Stone J).

[154] (1997) 90 A Crim R 526.

[155] Ibid 566.

[156] [1959] SCR 121. See further ‘The Legacy of Roncarelli v Duplessis 1959–2009’, a collection of 14 articles in (2010) 55 McGill Law Journal 375–741, a special issue to mark the 50th anniversary of the Canadian Supreme Court’s decision.

[157] Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121, 185 (Abbott J).

[158] Abbott J may well have been wrong. It appears likely that Duplessis’s only concern was not the law, but whether he was aiming at the right man. He had ordered a detective to check whether Roncarelli was indeed the same man who both held the permit and was acting as bail bondsman for many of his co-religionists who had been arrested for protesting against the government. The court in Odhavji [2003] 3 SCR 263, 285 [30] (Iacobucci J for McLachlin CJ, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ) glossed over the problem, saying that Duplessis knew that he had acted illegally.

[159] Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121, 141.

[160] Ibid 143.

[161] If the presumption were irrebuttable, there would be a significant increase in the risk of liability for police and others with lawful (albeit limited) power to inflict harm.

[162] One could argue that Rand J found Duplessis liable for a gross violation of the rule of law: see Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121, 142, where his Honour said that it was a fundamental postulate of the rule of law that the victim of arbitrary and ultra vires action on the part of administrative officials should have ‘recourse or remedy’. The rule of law’s abhorrence of arbitrary conduct certainly informs misfeasance: Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 (Lord Steyn). Its violation is not, however, a tort in itself: Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 352–3 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ), 354 (Brennan J), 373 (Deane J).

[163] Chancery Amendment Act 1858, 21 & 22 Vict, c 27, s 2.

[164] See Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corp [1947] EWCA Civ 1; [1948] 1 KB 223, 229–30 (Lord Greene MR); Mark Aronson, Bruce Dyer and Matthew Groves, Judicial Review of Administrative Action (Lawbook, 4th ed, 2009) 367–78 [6.175]–[6.220]. In Australia, the purported exercise of a discretionary power by a public officer is invalid for Wednesbury unreasonableness if its outcome is so grossly unreasonable that no reasonable official similarly placed would agree with it.

[165] See Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken’, above n 52, 495.

[166] Statute of Westminster the Second (De Donis Conditionalibus) 1285, 13 Edw 1, c xxiv (Of Writs in Consimili Casu).

[167] Keith Stanton et al, Statutory Torts (Sweet & Maxwell, 2003) 17.

[168] Baron Eyre said in Sutton v Johnstone [1786] EngR 18; (1786) 1 TR 493, 509; [1786] EngR 18; 99 ER 1215, 1224: ‘every breach of a public duty, working wrong and loss to another, is an injury, and actionable’. This was a malicious prosecution case against George III for action he had taken whilst still a prince.

[169] Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken’, above n 52, 493–4.

[170] Mayor of Lyme Regis v Henley (1834) 8 Bli NS 690, 714; 5 ER 1097, 1106 (Park J); Ferguson v Kinnoull (1842) 9 Cl & Finn 251, 279; [1842] EngR 942; 8 ER 412, 423 (Lord Lyndhurst LC).

[171] Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken’, above n 52, 494–5, citing Atkinson v Newcastle and Gateshead Waterworks Co [1851] EngR 417; (1877) 2 Ex D 441, 445–6 (Lord Cairns LC) and Glossop v Heston and Isleworth Local Board [1879] UKLawRpCh 173; (1879) 12 Ch D 102, 109–10 (James LJ).

[172] Cf Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; (1998) 192 CLR 330, 376 [124], where Gummow J said that the action for breach of statutory duty sprang originally ‘from the relationship between the legislature and the promoters of private Acts’.

[173] For a comparative analysis, see Caroline Forell, ‘Statutes and Torts: Comparing the United States to Australia, Canada and England’ (2000) 36 Williamette Law Review 865.

[174] Ashby (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 954; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 273; [1790] EngR 1492; 92 ER 126, 137: ‘Where a new Act of Parliament is made for the benefit of the subject, if a man be hindered from the enjoyment of it, he shall have an action against such person who so obstructed him.’

[175] Stanton et al, above n 167, 17–19.

[176] Francis Trindade, Peter Cane and Mark Lunney, The Law of Torts in Australia (Oxford University Press, 4th ed, 2007) 665–6; Neil Foster, ‘Breach of Statutory Duty and Risk Management in Occupational Health and Safety Law: New Law in Old Wineskins?’ (2006) 14 Tort Law Review 79.

[177] Groves v Wimbourne [1898] UKLawRpKQB 138; [1898] 2 QB 402, 410 (Smith LJ), 413 (Rigby LJ), 415 (Vaughan Williams LJ).

[178] Bourke v Butterfield & Lewis Ltd [1926] HCA 38; (1926) 38 CLR 354 held that contributory negligence was no defence, but the House of Lords disagreed in Caswell v Powell Duffryn Associated Collieries Ltd [1940] AC 152. In Piro v W Foster & Co Ltd [1943] HCA 32; (1943) 68 CLR 313, the High Court fell into line with the House of Lords.

[179] A Wednesbury unreasonableness standard of care applies to actions brought in several Australian jurisdictions against public authorities for breach of statutory duty other than employees’ claims for workplace injuries. See Civil Law (Wrongs) Act 2002 (ACT) s 111; Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW) s 43; Civil Liability Act 2003 (Qld) s 36; Civil Liability Act 2002 (Tas) s 40. Victoria also imposes a Wednesbury standard, but only where the statutory duty is imposed specifically on the defendant in its public capacity, and not if it is a duty of strict liability: Wrongs Act 1958 (Vic) ss 84(2), (4).

[180] K M Stanton, Breach of Statutory Duty in Tort (Sweet & Maxwell, 1986) 26, citing Monk v Warbey [1935] 1 KB 75. The replacement work does not pursue the issue: see Stanton et al, above n 167.

[181] Stuart v Kirkland-Veenstra [2009] HCA 15; (2009) 237 CLR 215, 263–4 (Crennan and Kiefel JJ); Morrison Sports Ltd v Scottish Power [2010] UKSC 37; [2010] 1 WLR 1934, 1943–4 [28]–[29] (Lord Rodger).

[182] Lord Denning MR thought that his only honest alternative to tossing a coin was to follow his sense of justice: Ex parte Island Records Ltd [1978] Ch 122, 135. Dixon J thought that some judges were deciding according to their own preferences rather than genuinely treating the matter as a constructional issue: O’Connor v S P Bray Ltd [1937] HCA 18; (1937) 56 CLR 464, 478. Kitto J acknowledged the constructional difficulties, but insisted that the exercise remained a genuine issue of statutory interpretation: Sovar v Henry Lane Pty Ltd [1967] HCA 31; (1967) 116 CLR 397, 405. McHugh and Gummow JJ said in Byrne v Australian Airlines Ltd (1995) 185 CLR 410, 459 that legislative ‘intentions’ were illusory, particularly as regards Acts that represented compromises or deals between different forces. Rather, one should approach the matter on a principled basis as a matter of statutory construction. See also Gardiner v Victoria [1999] VSCA 100; [1999] 2 VR 461, 468–9 [23] (Phillips JA); Miller v Miller [2011] HCA 9; (2011) 275 ALR 611, 619 [29] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).

[183] R (Canada) v Saskatchewan Wheat Pool [1983] 1 SCR 205, 225 (Dickson J for Ritchie, Dickson, Beetz, Estey, McIntyre, Chouinard and Lamer JJ).

[184] Byrne v Australian Airlines Ltd (1995) 185 CLR 410, 458 (McHugh and Gummow JJ); Crimmins v Stevedoring Industry Finance Committee [1999] HCA 59; (1999) 200 CLR 1, 58 (Gummow J).

[185] See Stanton et al, above n 167, 449–50; Duncan Fairgrieve, State Liability in Tort: A Comparative Law Study (Oxford University Press, 2003) 36–41. Fairgrieve pointed to leading judgments emphasising the unlikelihood of the legislature impliedly creating a new cause of action with huge budgetary costs.

[186] See Doe dem Murray v Bridges [1831] EngR 57; (1831) 1 B & Ad 847, 859; [1831] EngR 57; 109 ER 1001, 1006–7 (Lord Tenterden CJ); Pasmore v Oswaldtwistle Urban District Council [1898] UKLawRpAC 17; [1898] AC 387, 394 (Earl of Halsbury LC).

[187] See Cutler v Wandsworth Stadium Ltd [1949] AC 398, 408 (Lord Simonds); Sovar v Henry Lane Pty Ltd [1967] HCA 31; (1967) 116 CLR 397, 405–6 (Kitto J); Gardiner v Victoria [1999] VSCA 100; [1999] 2 VR 461, 469 [25] (Phillips JA). The criminal penalty in the legislation under consideration in Groves v Wimbourne would have varied according to the defendant’s fault rather than the plaintiff’s loss, and would not necessarily have gone to the plaintiff: [1898] UKLawRpKQB 138; [1898] 2 QB 402, 406–8 (Smith LJ).

[188] See Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 350 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ).

[189] See O’Rourke v Camden London Borough Council [1997] UKHL 24; [1998] AC 188, 194 (Lord Hoffmann); Cullen v Chief Constable of the Royal Ulster Constabulary [2003] UKHL 39; [2003] 1 WLR 1763.

[190] See Repacholi Aviation Pty Ltd v Civil Aviation Safety Authority [2010] FCA 994 (10 September 2010) [30] (Gilmour J).

[191] See Miller v Miller [2011] HCA 9; (2011) 275 ALR 611, 629–30 [65]–[68] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).

[192] X (Minors) v Bedfordshire County Council [1995] UKHL 9; [1995] 2 AC 633, 731–2 (Lord Browne-Wilkinson); O’Rourke v Camden London Borough Council [1997] UKHL 24; [1998] AC 188, 193–4 (Lord Hoffmann). See also Phelps v Hillingdon London Borough Council [2000] UKHL 47; [2001] 2 AC 619, 652 (Lord Slynn); A-G (NZ) v Daniels [2003] 2 NZLR 742, 767–8 [87]–[88] (Keith J for Keith, Blanchard, Tipping, McGrath and Anderson JJ).

[193] Cutler v Wandsworth Stadium Ltd [1949] AC 398, 408.

[194] O’Rourke v Camden London Borough Council [1997] UKHL 24; [1998] AC 188, 194 (Lord Hoffmann).

[195] Semantic distinctions are sometimes drawn between duties on the one hand, and prohibitions or powers on the other hand: see, eg, Lonrho Ltd v Shell Petroleum Co Ltd [1982] AC 173, 186 (Lord Diplock). Even in the case of a statutory discretion, however, there might occasionally be a relevant ‘duty’ in circumstances where there is only one way in which the discretion can lawfully be exercised: Stuart v Kirkland-Veenstra [2009] HCA 15; (2009) 237 CLR 215, 265 [146] (Crennan and Kiefel JJ). The idea that flagrant abuse of discretionary power should be actionable has a long history. See Sutton v Johnstone [1786] EngR 18; (1786) 1 TR 493, 504; [1786] EngR 18; 99 ER 1215, 1221 (Eyre B):

And one may observe in general, in respect of what is done under powers incident to situations, that there is a wide difference between indulging to situation a latitude touching the extent of power, and touching the abuse of it. Cases may be put of situations so critical that the power ought to be unbounded: but it is impossible to state a case where it is necessary that it should be abused; and it is the felicity of those who live under a free constitution of Government, that it is equally impossible to state a case where it can be abused with impunity.

[196] Wrongs Act 1958 (Vic) s 84(3); Civil Liability Act 2002 (WA) s 5Y.

[197] Chancery Amendment Act 1858, 21 & 22 Vict, c 27, s 2.

[198] Boyce v Paddington Borough Council [1902] UKLawRpCh 174; [1903] 1 Ch 109, 114 (Buckley J).

[199] Australian Conservation Foundation Inc v Commonwealth (1980) 146 CLR 493; Onus v Alcoa of Australia Ltd [1981] HCA 50; (1981) 149 CLR 27.

[200] See Inland Revenue Commissioners v National Federation of Self-Employed and Small Businesses Ltd [1981] UKHL 2; [1982] AC 617.

[201] Stininato v Auckland Boxing Association (Inc) [1978] 1 NZLR 1, 23 (Cooke J); Wentworth v Woollahra Municipal Council [1982] HCA 41; (1982) 149 CLR 672. See Finn, ‘A Road Not Taken’, above n 52, 494–5.

[202] Stovin v Wise [1996] UKHL 15; [1996] AC 923, 952–3 (Lord Hoffmann).

[203] Gorringe v Calderdale Metropolitan Borough Council [2004] UKHL 15; [2004] 2 All ER 326.

[204] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).

[205] See below Part X.

[206] Law Commission, ‘Administrative Redress’, above n 6, 34 [3.116], 78 [4.105]. It is admittedly a slight exaggeration to characterise the Commission’s reform proposals as having focused on negligence law, although a consideration of negligence law was the principal basis for the Commission’s court-centred reform proposals. Liability would have attached to the acts and even ‘pure omissions’ of persons exercising truly public functions. There must have been ‘serious fault’ on the defendant’s part in a manner which frustrated a legislative intent to confer a benefit on the plaintiff or a class to which the plaintiff belonged. This legislative intention will almost never be explicit. Its requirement would therefore raise the same constructional problems that currently plague actions for breach of statutory duty, which the Commission also wanted to abolish. The new compensation right would have extended into territories previously reserved for government ‘policy’ or ‘discretion’.

[207] See ibid. The Commission’s proposals were met with widespread opposition from most quarters. Most importantly, all government agencies and relevant Ministers were opposed: at 1 [1.3].

[208] The differences in the approaches of Australian and Canadian courts are not relevant to this discussion.

[209] See Sullivan v Moody (2001) 207 CLR 562; D v East Berkshire Community Health NHS Trust [2005] UKHL 23; [2005] 2 AC 373.

[210] Jain v Trent Strategic Health Authority [2009] 1 AC 853.

[211] See Tame v New South Wales [2002] HCA 35; (2002) 211 CLR 317; Brooks v Metropolitan Police Commissioner [2005] UKHL 24; [2005] 1 WLR 1495; Smith v Chief Constable of Sussex Police [2009] 1 AC 225, 278 (Lord Phillips CJ). Canada, however, does have a tort of negligent investigation: Hill v Hamilton-Wentworth Regional Police Services Board [2007] 3 SCR 129, 140 (McLachlin CJ for McLachlin CJ, Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish and Abella JJ).

[212] Elguzouli-Daf v Commissioner of Police of the Metropolis [1994] EWCA Civ 4; [1995] QB 335, 348 (Lord Steyn); Brooks v Metropolitan Police Commissioner [2005] UKHL 24; [2005] 1 WLR 1495, 1511–12 [38] (Lord Rodger).

[213] See Perre v Apand Pty Ltd [1999] HCA 36; (1999) 198 CLR 180, 245 [178] (Gummow J). The position might be changing. See P Vines, ‘Misfeasance in Public Office: Old Torts, New Tricks?’ in James Edelman and Simone Degeling (eds), Torts in Commercial Law (forthcoming), which lists several cases where the harms were reputational, personal injury, or false imprisonment. Vines suggests that part of the upsurge in Australian misfeasance claims might be the result of the recent imposition of legislative restrictions on the negligence liability of public authorities. Where other torts are available, it is difficult to see the advantage in pursuing a misfeasance claim; cf Habib v Commonwealth [No 2] [2009] FCA 228; (2009) 175 FCR 350; Habib v Commonwealth [2010] FCAFC 12; (2010) 183 FCR 62. In England, a murdered woman’s estate sued for misfeasance in Akenzua v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2003] 1 WLR 741, in circumstances where there was no proximity and therefore no common law duty of care in negligence. It has been suggested that Canadian pleading rules permit allegations of bad faith without genuine particulars, and that a misfeasance claim occasionally has the procedural advantage over other torts of affording broader (and potentially more embarrassing) discovery: Erika Chamberlain, ‘What is the Role of Misfeasance in a Public Office in Modern Canadian Tort Law?’ (2009) 88 Canadian Bar Review 575, 593–5. Chamberlain also argues that the lack of a broad judicial discretion to limit individual misfeasance claims by reference to public policy considerations sometimes makes it a more attractive tort than negligence: at 588–91.

[214] White v Jones [1995] UKHL 5; [1995] 2 AC 207; Hill v Van Erp (1997) 188 CLR 159.

[215] Lord Hobhouse said in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 229 that ‘[t]here is no principle in English law that an official is the guarantor of the legality of everything he does’. Cf Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 353 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ), where the joint judgment speculated that there might be ‘very many circumstances’ in which government officials have a duty of care to ensure that their subordinates know and stay within the limits of their power. In such cases, their Honours said that there would usually be an additional duty on those officials, to ascertain their power. Deane J appeared to agree: at 373–4.

[216] See Dunlop v Woollahra Municipal Council [1982] AC 158, 171–2 (Lord Diplock); Rowling v Takaro Properties Ltd [1987] UKPC 2; [1988] 1 AC 473, 500, 502–3 (Lord Keith for Lords Keith, Brandon, Mackay and Goff).

[217] Allsop P said in Precision Products (NSW) Pty Ltd v Hawkesbury City Council [2008] NSWCA 278; (2008) 74 NSWLR 102, 128 [119] that a duty to take care to act intra vires would require the courts to set public sector management standards, which would be both difficult and a violation of the separation of powers.

[218] See Geoff McLay, ‘Book Comment: What Are We to Do with the Public Law of Torts?’ (2009) 7 New Zealand Journal of Public International Law 373, 375–6.

[219] See, eg, Stuart v Kirkland-Veenstra [2009] HCA 15; (2009) 237 CLR 215, which held that police owe no common law duty of care towards would-be suicides. The situation is obviously different as regards special relationships, such as parent and child, jailer and prisoner, or teacher and pupil.

[220] See, eg, Modbury Triangle Shopping Centre Pty Ltd v Anzil [2000] HCA 61; (2000) 205 CLR 254; Smith v Chief Constable of Sussex Police [2009] 1 AC 225, 278–9 (Lord Phillips CJ).

[221] Cf Peter Benson, ‘Misfeasance as an Organizing Normative Idea in Private Law’ (2010) 60 University of Toronto Law Journal 731, arguing that the distinction between misfeasance and nonfeasance is a normative principle permeating much of private law.

[222] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230 (Lord Hobhouse), 236–7 (Lord Millett).

[223] [1979] QB 722. The Court of Appeal upheld Mr Dytham’s conviction for the indictable offence of misconduct in public office.

[224] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230 (Lord Hobhouse), 236–7 (Lord Millett). Lords Bingham and Brown said in Smith v Chief Constable of Sussex Police [2009] 1 AC 225, 264 [53] (Lord Bingham), 282 [120] (Lord Brown) that the constable in Dytham would now be said to have owed the victim a common law duty of care. It is curious that they made no mention of the possibility of an action for misfeasance.

[225] (1703) 2 Ld Raym 938, 956; 1 Smith LC (13th ed) 253, 276; [1746] EngR 605; 96 ER 126, 138.

[226] See Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 404–5 (Lord Bingham), 415–17 (Lord Rodger). See also A-G (Cth) ex rel McKinlay v Commonwealth [1975] HCA 53; (1975) 135 CLR 1, 76 (Murphy J): ‘Enforcement of constitutional political rights does not have to be justified by characterizing them as rights of property. This degrades the political right. The exaltation of property rights over civic and political rights is a reflection of the values of a bygone era.’

[227] Leerdam v Noori [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 554–5 [4] (Spigelman CJ).

[228] [1973] VicRp 70; [1973] VR 715.

[229] Ibid 720 (Smith J for Smith, Pape and Crockett JJ). McInerney J at first instance dealt at greater length with the requirement that there be a duty, but his point was that unless it was owed to the public, the defendant would not be a ‘public officer’ for the purposes of the tort: see Tampion v Anderson [1973] VicRp 32; [1973] VR 321, 336–7.

[230] (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).

[231] Ibid 357.

[232] Ibid 371.

[233] [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553.

[234] Ibid 554–5 [4]–[6].

[235] Ibid 577 [116]. Western Australia’s Court of Appeal took the same view in Neilson v City of Swan (2006) 147 LGERA 136, 158–9 [66] (Buss JA, Wheeler and Pullin JJA agreeing).

[236] [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 347 [77] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA).

[237] This would fit with the fact that they owe no duty of care to their adversaries: Elguzouli-Daf v Commissioner of Police of the Metropolis [1994] EWCA Civ 4; [1995] QB 335, 348 (Lord Steyn); Brooks v Metropolitan Police Commissioner [2005] UKHL 24; [2005] 1 WLR 1495, 1511–12 [38] (Lord Rodger).

[238] The claimants discontinued in Three Rivers, for example, before getting to the stage of proving that their losses were as much the Bank of England’s fault as that of the fraudsters who had run the failed bank.

[239] Vaughan Williams LJ thought it ‘perfectly clear’ in Davis v Bromley Corporation [1907] UKLawRpKQB 158; [1908] 1 KB 170, 173 that a builder could not get damages for a council’s malicious refusal of a building permit; even a grant of mandamus would have gone no further than compelling reconsideration according to law. Davis is treated nowadays as a case of judicial amnesia with regard to the misfeasance tort more generally: see Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 190 (Lord Steyn); Watkins [2006] 2 AC 395, 404 (Lord Bingham).

[240] See Sellars v Adelaide Petroleum NL (1994) 179 CLR 332; Commonwealth v Cornwell [2007] HCA 16; (2007) 229 CLR 519. The Privy Council said in David v Abdul Cader [1963] 1 WLR 834, 839–40 (Viscount Radcliffe for Viscount Radcliffe, Lords Evershed, Morris and Devlin and Sir Kenneth Gresson) that Davis v Bromley Corporation [1907] UKLawRpKQB 158; [1908] 1 KB 170 no longer applies. The Canadian Supreme Court in Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121 fudged the problem that the plaintiff’s permit was entirely discretionary and renewable annually; the Court awarded a considerable sum for loss of goodwill attaching to a wrongfully cancelled permit that had very little time left to run. Cf McLay, above n 218, 379.

[241] Garrett [1996] NZCA 430; [1997] 2 NZLR 332, 346 (Blanchard J for Richardson P, Gault, Henry, Keith and Blanchard JJ).

[242] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 229.

[243] Ibid 193 (Lord Steyn, who added that there was also no requirement of proximity), 197 (Lord Hope, agreeing with Lords Steyn and Hutton), 228 (Lord Hutton, dismissing the need for a separate and additional showing of ‘some other link or relationship between [the plaintiff] and the officer’). Lord Millett said that it was unnecessary to determine that issue: at 237.

[244] Erika Chamberlain, ‘The Need for a “Standing” Rule in Misfeasance in a Public Office’ (2007) 7 Oxford University Commonwealth Law Journal 215; J W Neyers, ‘The Economic Torts as Corrective Justice’ (2009) 17 Torts Law Journal 162. Cf Peter Cane, ‘The Anatomy of Private Law Theory: A 25th Anniversary Essay’ (2005) 25 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 203; Peter Cane, ‘Torts and Rights’ (2008) 71 Modern Law Review 641. See also Chamberlain, ‘Misfeasance in a Public Office’, above n 43; J W Neyers, ‘Explaining the Inexplicable? Four Manifestations of Abuse of Rights in English Law’ in Donal Nolan and Andrew Robertson (eds), Rights and Private Law (Hart Publishing, 2011) (forthcoming).

[245] Corrective justice theorists might respond either that misfeasance is a private law tort responding (unusually) to an abuse of rights in a non-Hohfeldian sense, or even that it is best left to public law. See McLay, above n 218, 375; Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights (Oxford University Press, 2007) 218, 242–3. Stevens regards it as a ‘regulatory’ mechanism: at 218. It appears that Oxford University Press’s prestigious volumes on public and private law could not decide where to deal with misfeasance, with the result that it is scarcely mentioned. For private law, see James Edelman and John Davies, ‘Torts and Equitable Wrongs’ in Andrew Burrows (ed), English Private Law (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed, 2007) 1185, 1315–16; Andrew Burrows, ‘Judicial Remedies’ in Andrew Burrows (ed), English Private Law (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed, 2007) 1617, 1677–9. For public law, see A W Bradley, ‘The Constitutional Position of the Judiciary’ in David Feldman (ed), English Public Law (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed, 2009) 281, 310.

[246] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ). The suggested unavailability of vicarious liability gives the damages some colour of punitive damages. According to Lord Hailsham, punitive damages are quantified by reference to what the defendant should pay, rather than what the plaintiff should receive: Broome v Cassell & Co Ltd [1972] UKHL 3; [1972] AC 1027, 1077.

[247] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 229–30.

[248] Ibid 196 (Lord Steyn), 228 (Lord Hutton), 229 (Lord Hobhouse), 235, 237 (Lord Millett).

[249] Ibid 193 (Lord Steyn), 246 (Lord Hope).

[250] Ibid 231 (Lord Hobhouse).

[251] Ibid 235 (Lord Millett).

[252] Ibid 230–1 (Lord Hobhouse).

[253] See Aronson, Dyer and Groves, above n 164, 772–4 [11.115].

[254] [2003] 1 WLR 741. This was a strike-out application, so that strictly speaking, the facts had not yet been established. The Court nevertheless painted a compelling picture, drawn largely from remarks at sentencing.

[255] Sedley LJ said that any suggestion that the victim’s class was 3.5 million London women was ‘a spurious endeavour to give specificity to the unspecific’: Akenzua [2003] 1 WLR 741, 746 [15].

[256] Ibid 747 [20] (Sedley LJ).

[257] Ibid 751 [35] (Brown LJ).

[258] The wife-murderer and terrorist were Sedley LJ’s examples, and Hannibal Lecter was Brown LJ’s: ibid 747 [16] (Sedley LJ), 750 [33] (Brown LJ).

[259] See above n 213 and accompanying text.

[260] See text accompanying above n 130.

[261] [2008] NZCA 216; [2008] 3 NZLR 649, 674 [116] (O’Regan J for O’Regan, Ellen France and Baragwanath JJ).

[262] See, eg, Banking Act 1959 (Cth) s 9(2); Australian Prudential Regulation Authority Act 1998 (Cth) s 8(2); Banking Act 2009 (UK) c 1, s 4.

[263] [1828] EngR 701; (1828) 5 Bing 91; 130 ER 995. Brennan J treated Henly as an early misfeasance case: Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355; but Lord Millett treated it as an action for breach of statutory duty: Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 237. It is submitted that it was an action for breach of non-statutory duty.

[264] [1979] QB 722.

[265] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 228 (Lord Hutton), 230 (Lord Hobhouse), 237 (Lord Millett), quoted in Neilson v City of Swan (2006) 147 LGERA 136, 152–3 [47], 162 [84] (Buss JA).

[266] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 237 (Lord Millett).

[267] The claim failed in Garrett, but only for want of proof of a key mental element of the tort. It was not established that the sergeant either knew or actually suspected that a cover-up would seriously harm the plaintiff.

[268] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355 (Brennan J).

[269] [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 576 [109].

[270] [1990] 1 WLR 54, 70–1.

[271] Ibid 71. See also at 85 (Nourse LJ).

[272] Jones v Swansea City Council [1990] 1 WLR 1453, 1458–9 (Lord Lowry).

[273] Manchester City Council v Pinnock [2010] UKSC 45; [2010] 3 WLR 1441, 1457 [54] (Lord Neuberger).

[274] See, eg, Criminal Code Act 1995 (Cth) s 142.2(1)(a)(i); Criminal Code Act 2002 (ACT) s 359(1)(a)(i); Criminal Code Act 1899 (Qld) s 92A(5).

[275] See, eg, R v Quach [2010] VSCA 106; (2010) 201 A Crim R 522, where the charge related to an off-duty policeman having sex with a woman he knew to be in a particularly fragile state, having conducted an on-duty ‘welfare check’ on her earlier in the day because she had attempted suicide.

[276] (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355 (emphasis added).

[277] [1989] 1 AC 1228, 1240–1 (Lord Bridge).

[278] [2002] EWCA Civ 1073 (25 July 2002).

[279] Ibid [14] (Waller LJ).

[280] [1978] TASStRp 1; [1978] Tas SR 1, 14.

[281] Ibid 31 (Chambers J), 38 (Nettlefold J). An employee’s dismissal in McGuirk v University of New South Wales was held not to be an exercise of public power, but it was not governed by statute: [2010] NSWSC 1471 (17 December 2010) [27]–[28], [36] (Johnson J).

[282] Tampion v Anderson [1973] VicRp 70; [1973] VR 715, 720 (Smith J for Smith, Pape and Crockett JJ).

[283] [1998] FCA 709; (1998) 179 FCR 290.

[284] Ibid 300 [34] (Wilcox, Miles and R D Nicholson JJ).

[285] See Aronson, above n 7, 53.

[286] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 230. His Lordship added that it must be unlawful not because it was itself tortious, but because it was unauthorised or forbidden by law: at 286. The House of Lords in Kuddus [2001] UKHL 29; [2002] 2 AC 122, 136 [30] (Lord Mackay), 153 [90] (Lord Hutton) accepted without demur the defence concession that it was misfeasance for a police officer to forge a document dropping a theft complaint.

[287] Dytham [1979] QB 722. The deceased in Akenzua [2003] 1 WLR 741 was murdered by an extremely dangerous man who was at large because the authorities had perverted the criminal justice system. His release on bail should have been revoked, but it was not a nullity.

[288] Rawlinson v Rice [1998] 1 NZLR 454. Brennan J noted the issue in Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355.

[289] Cannon [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 336 [48] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA).

[290] See above nn 506 and accompanying text.

[291] Spigelman CJ insisted in Leerdam [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 555 [9] that the requirement that the defendant be a public officer is ‘quite distinct’ from the requirement that the power or duty that was abused be public.

[292] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355 (Brennan J), 370 (Deane J); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 191 (Lord Steyn), 229–30 (Lord Hobhouse).

[293] See, eg, Cannon [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 328 [28] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA).

[294] The issue and cases are discussed at length in Chase Oyster Bar Pty Ltd v Hamo Industries Pty Ltd [2010] NSWCA 190; (2010) 272 ALR 750 and noted in Plaintiff M61/2010E v Commonwealth [2010] HCA 41; (2010) 272 ALR 14, 26 [51] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).

[295] The leading case is R v Panel on Take-Overs and Mergers; Ex parte Datafin plc [1986] EWCA Civ 8; [1987] 1 QB 815.

[296] Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 191.

[297] Ibid 230.

[298] Ibid 229. See also Percy v Church of Scotland [2005] UKHL 73; [2006] 2 AC 28, 38 [17] (Lord Nicholls), 46 [54] (Lord Hoffmann).

[299] [2007] EWCA Civ 930; [2008] 1 WLR 2255, 2263 [23]. Spigelman CJ agreed in Leerdam [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 554 [3].

[300] Society of Lloyd’s v Henderson [2007] EWCA Civ 930; [2008] 1 WLR 2255, 2263 [24]–[25].

[301] Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 355, referring to Henly v Lyme (1828) 5 Bing 91, 107–8; [1828] EngR 701; 130 ER 995, 1010 (Best CJ).

[302] See R v McCann [1998] 2 Qd R 56, 72, where Byrne J gave as examples justices of the peace and university chancellors.

[303] Marks v Commonwealth [1964] HCA 45; (1964) 111 CLR 549, 567–8 (Windeyer J).

[304] In R v McCann [1998] 2 Qd R 56, 68, Byrne J listed classes of people who are appointed to exercise functions pertaining to public life but which fell outside the definition of ‘public office’: engine drivers, porters, fettlers, cleaners, railway clerks and temporary lecturers.

[305] Byrne J helpfully analysed a large number of cases from a range of contexts and jurisdictions: ibid 67–74.

[306] Cannon [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 342 [61] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA); Leerdam [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 556 [17]–[18] (Spigelman CJ), 562 [51] (Allsop P), 576 [109] (Macfarlan JA); Stewart v Ronalds [2009] NSWCA 277; (2009) 76 NSWLR 99, 121 [106] (Hodgson JA).

[307] Cannon gave both reasons, but emphasised the second: [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 342 [61], 343 [63] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA). In comparison, Leerdam emphasised the first reason: [2009] NSWCA 90; (2009) 255 ALR 553, 556 [17]–[18] (Spigelman CJ), 562 [51] (Allsop P), 576 [109] (Macfarlan JA).

[308] Stewart v Ronalds [2009] NSWCA 277; (2009) 76 NSWLR 99, 121 [106].

[309] Elguzouli-Daf v Commissioner of Police [1994] EWCA Civ 4; [1995] QB 335, 347 (Lord Steyn), 352 (Morritt LJ).

[310] Cannon [2002] VSCA 84; (2002) 5 VR 317, 344 [66] (Winneke P, Charles and Chernov JJA).

[311] [1998] FCA 709; (1998) 179 FCR 290.

[312] Ibid 300 [36] (Wilcox, Miles and R D Nicholson JJ).

[313] Dunlop v Woollahra Municipal Council [1982] AC 158, 172 (Lord Diplock for Lords Diplock, Simon, Edmund-Davies, Scarman and Bridge); Jones v Swansea City Council [1990] 1 WLR 1453, 1458–9 (Lord Lowry); Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 191 (Lord Steyn).

[314] The example is drawn from Jones v Swansea City Council [1990] 1 WLR 54 (Court of Appeal), revd [1990] 1 WLR 1453 (House of Lords). The claim failed for want of proof that a majority of councillors had been improperly motivated. It appears that in the Court of Appeal, the plaintiffs in Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 54 (Hirst LJ) had sought to make the Bank of England directly liable for the conduct of its senior officials. The same position probably applied in the appeal: see at 240 (Lord Hope), 270 (Lord Hutton); but other passages suggest that the Bank’s liability may have been alleged to have been vicarious: at 191 (Lord Steyn), 230 (Lord Hobhouse).

[315] This Part draws on Jim Davis, ‘Misfeasance in Public Office, Exemplary Damages and Vicarious Liability’ [2010] AIAdminLawF 29; (2010) 64 AIAL Forum 59.

[316] Enever v The King [1906] HCA 3; (1906) 3 CLR 969.

[317] De facto authority suffices where an employer could not legally have authorised a breach of the law: James v Commonwealth [1939] HCA 9; (1939) 62 CLR 339, 359–60 (Dixon J); Mengel (1995) 185 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).

[318] See Bazley v Curry 1999 Can LII 692 (SCC); [1999] 2 SCR 534; Jacobi v Griffiths [1999] 2 SCR 570; Lister v Lesley Hall Ltd [2002] 1 AC 215; New South Wales v Lepore [2003] HCA 4; (2003) 212 CLR 511.

[319] See Little v Commonwealth [1947] HCA 24; (1947) 75 CLR 94, 114 (Dixon J); Grimwade v Victoria (1997) 90 A Crim R 526, 567–70 (Harper J); Balkin and Davis, above n 19, 752–4 [26.56]–[26.59].

[320] Crown Proceedings Act 1947, 10 & 11 Geo, c 44, s 2(3).

[321] Law Reform (Vicarious Liability) Act 1983 (NSW) ss 78.

[322] Crown Proceedings Act 1950 (NZ) s 6(3).

[323] Crown Liability and Proceedings Act, RSC 1985, c C-50, s 3(b)(i).

[324] Crown Proceedings Act 1972 (SA) s 10(2) precluded Crown resort to the ‘independent discretion’ rule for acts or omissions that only Crown servants (and possibly other public bodies) had authority to perform: South Australia v Kubicki (1987) 46 SASR 282; De Bruyn v South Australia (1990) 54 SASR 231, 244–5 (Legoe J).

[325] Crown Proceedings Act 1992 (SA), replacing Crown Proceedings Act 1972 (SA).

[326] Balkin and Davis, above n 19, 752 n 258. There have been several cases since 1992 in which the independent discretion rule was not raised, even though the torts pleaded clearly involved the exercise of independent discretions. See, eg, X v South Australia [No 3] [2007] SASC 125; (2007) 97 SASR 180; South Australia v Lampard-Trevorrow [2010] SASC 56; (2010) 106 SASR 331. See also TransAdelaide v Evans [2005] SASC 175; (2005) 98 SASR 394, 398 [16] (Doyle CJ).

[327] Racz v Home Office [1994] 2 AC 45 held that there were no special rules governing vicarious liability in misfeasance, making such liability possible. See also Three Rivers [2003] 2 AC 1, 191 (Lord Steyn), 230 (Lord Hobhouse).

[328] See Law Commission, Administrative Redress: Public Bodies and the Citizen, Report No 322 (2010) 35–7 [3.65]–[3.72].

[329] Indeed, it revoked special leave to appeal on the question of vicarious liability in Tepko Pty Ltd v Water Board [2001] HCA 19; (2001) 206 CLR 1, 13 [34] (Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ). See also Transcript of Proceedings, Tepko Pty Ltd v Water Board (High Court of Australia, No S36 of 2000, Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow, Kirby, Hayne and Callinan JJ, 22 November 2000).

[330] Mengel (1995) 187 CLR 307, 347 (Mason CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ). See also Rogers v Legal Services Commission (SA) (1995) 64 SASR 572, 587 (Lander J).

[331] The allegations of misfeasance were outlined in Pharm-a-Care Laboratories Pty Ltd v Commonwealth [No 3] [2010] FCA 361; (2010) 267 ALR 494 and Pharm-a-Care Laboratories Pty Ltd v Commonwealth [No 5] [2010] FCA 1204 (5 November 2010). Both the individual action and the class action received widespread media coverage: see, eg, Samantha Bowers, ‘Pan Customers Get $67m Settlement’, The Australian Financial Review (Sydney), 26 March 2011, 10, which reported the settlement of the individual action for around $55 million and the settlement of the class action for $67.5 million. For the Federal Court’s approval of the class action settlement, see Pharm-a-Care Laboratories Pty Ltd v Commonwealth [No 6] [2011] FCA 277 (25 March 2011). The Commonwealth paid $5 million to Vita Life Sciences Ltd in settlement of a separate claim brought in the New South Wales Supreme Court: Vita Life Sciences Ltd, Vita Life Sciences Limited Annual Report 2010 (25 March 2011) 2 <http://www.vitalifesciences.com/v2/

areports.html>.

[332] Legal Services Directions 2005 (Cth) app E paras 5–6.

[333] See Australian Federal Police Act 1979 (Cth) s 64B; Law Reform (Vicarious Liability) Act 1983 (NSW) pt 4; Police Act 1990 (NSW) s 213; Police Administration Act 1978 (NT) pt VIIA; Police Service Administration Act 1990 (Qld) s 10.5; Police Act 1998 (SA) s 65; Police Service Act 2003 (Tas) s 84; Police Regulation Act 1958 (Vic) s 123; Police Act 1892 (WA) s 137.

[334] See De Reus v Gray [2003] VSCA 84; (2003) 9 VR 432, 437–8 [3], [5] (Winneke P); New South Wales v Ibbett [2006] HCA 57; (2006) 229 CLR 638.

[335] [1956] UKHL 6; [1957] AC 555.

[336] Employees Liability Act 1991 (NSW) ss 3, 5; Law Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) Act 1956 (NT) s 22A; Law Reform (Contributory Negligence and Apportionment of Liability) Act 2001 (SA) s 6(9)(c).

[337] Insurance Contracts Act 1984 (Cth) s 66. See also Balkin and Davis, above n 19, 824–5 [29.39].

[338] David v Abdul Cader [1963] 1 WLR 834, 839–40 (Viscount Radcliffe for Viscount Radcliffe, Lords Evershed, Morris and Devlin and Sir Kenneth Gresson).

[339] Harlow, above n 29 argued for a new tort that I suspect would cross the public–private divide. It would apply to conduct that is contumelious, deliberate and outrageous. It would also allow punitive damages in the absence of material loss, because it would reverse the common law’s parsimonious attitude to dignitarian loss. A majority ruled against the creation of a separate measure of damages for ‘vindicatory’ purposes in Lumba v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2011] UKSC 12; [2011] 2 WLR 671, 702 [101] (Lord Dyson SCJ), 739 [237] (Lord Collins SCJ).

[340] Actual or (as in Odhavji) assumed.


AustLII: Copyright Policy | Disclaimers | Privacy Policy | Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/MelbULawRw/2011/1.html